751 lines
35 KiB
Plaintext
751 lines
35 KiB
Plaintext
Newsgroups: rec.food.veg
|
|
From: altar@beaufort.sfu.ca (Ted Wayn Altar)
|
|
Subject: Plant Pain
|
|
Message-ID: <altar.724697657@sfu.ca>
|
|
Sender: news@sfu.ca
|
|
Organization: Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, B.C., Canada
|
|
Date: Fri, 18 Dec 1992 16:54:17 GMT
|
|
Lines: 389
|
|
|
|
[This document contains both parts concatenated.]
|
|
|
|
I see that the old chestnut of "plant pain" has again been
|
|
invoked. Apparently, this is a common argument and so, dear
|
|
reader, permit me to re-post an older message of mine that
|
|
attempts to address this issue in a discursive, but also
|
|
humourous manner.
|
|
|
|
Happy Holiday Season,
|
|
|
|
ted
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
THE DIVERSIONARY TACTIC OF PLANT PAIN
|
|
|
|
TED ALTAR
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
A. HOW MIGHT CHARLES DARWIN RESPOND?
|
|
|
|
With respect to this extravagant debate on plant pain we
|
|
have at hand a most promiscuous adjoining of some verified
|
|
facts with improper inferences. This reminds me of a story
|
|
(probably apocryphal as are so many of the best anecdotes)
|
|
about Charles Darwin who in his later years was the guest of
|
|
a family whose two boys approached him with a clever
|
|
deception. Using some old desiccated specimens of insects,
|
|
they had deftly attached the wings of a butterfly, the head
|
|
of a beetle and the legs of a grasshopper to the body of a
|
|
centipede. "We have this strange bug we caught some time
|
|
ago" they innocently said, "Can you tell us what it might
|
|
be?" Darwin squinted and examined it as best he could and
|
|
asked, "Can you remember if it hummed when you caught it?"
|
|
he asked in all seriousness. Without smirking, the boys
|
|
answered yes, whereupon Darwin replied, "Just as I thought,
|
|
it is a humbug!"
|
|
|
|
|
|
B. THE SPECIOUS INFERENCE OF PLANT PAIN.
|
|
|
|
No doubt we all have been amazed by much "humbug" on this
|
|
conference, but maybe no greater example is to be given than
|
|
that of "plant pain". Those whose common sense remains
|
|
intact will have no difficulty in accepting as sufficient
|
|
the following:
|
|
|
|
1. Our best science to date shows that plants lack any
|
|
semblance of a central nervous system or any other system
|
|
design for such complex capacities as that of a conscious
|
|
suffering from felt pain.
|
|
|
|
2. Plants simply have no evolutionary need to feel pain.
|
|
Animals being mobile would benefit from the ability to sense
|
|
pain; plants would not. Nature does not create gratuitously
|
|
such complex capacities as that of feeling pain unless there
|
|
should be some benefit for the organism's survival.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Well, as Oliver Goldsmith realistically observed, "Every
|
|
absurdity has its champions to defend it". And yes, we
|
|
have some defenders who would ignore common sense and argue
|
|
for plant pain. Remarkable!. But maybe not so remarkable
|
|
if we keep in mind the motivation for such humbug. The
|
|
following argument has repeated been voiced against the
|
|
concern of us who would forward greater regard for the
|
|
woefully neglected and grievous suffering of those sentient
|
|
creatures who cannot defend, nor articulate in words, their
|
|
plight. The following `reductio ad absurdum' is supposed to
|
|
suffice as an irrefutable trashing of animal rights.
|
|
|
|
Premise(1) If a sentient being can consciously experience
|
|
pain and suffering, then it is wrong to inflict
|
|
pain & suffering on such a sentient being
|
|
Premise(2) Plants are sentient beings that can experience
|
|
pain & suffering
|
|
Conclusion: It is wrong to inflict pain & suffering on plants.
|
|
|
|
In order to challenge the acceptability of premise(1), the
|
|
anti-AR would have us believe that such a premise
|
|
ineluctably leads to the absurd conclusion as stated above.
|
|
In order to achieve this coup de grace of animal rights, the
|
|
anti-AR who would give little or no coin to premise (1),
|
|
would instead introduce the claims of premise(2) as somehow
|
|
"scientifically established". In order to debunk animal
|
|
rights as foolish, the anti-AR would first have us believe
|
|
in the reality of "plant pain". Hence, they would attempt
|
|
to bury AR into a hole but ironically by first bulldozing a
|
|
much deeper one for themselves.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
E. "EVERY ABSURDITY HAS ITS CHAMPIONS TO DEFEND IT"
|
|
|
|
You say that I am merely spinning my wheels on a straw man?
|
|
Then permit me to quote from two of the most loquacious and
|
|
articulate promoters of plant "pain" on this conference.
|
|
|
|
Poster A would bait us with the following argument, an
|
|
argument that presumably he still holds as having merit by
|
|
virtue of his repeated postings of this worn polemic:
|
|
|
|
AR: "You're crude and unfeeling; you'd probably laugh
|
|
at your mother's death."
|
|
non-AR: "That's silly, my mother is a human. A deer isn't."
|
|
AR: "Deer can suffer, and so do cattle...so I don't eat meat."
|
|
non-AR: "You apparently have no problem killing plants, though."
|
|
AR: "It's not the same. Plants aren't animals."
|
|
non-AR: "You're killing a living thing for food, nevertheless."
|
|
AR: "But it can't feel; it's not sentient; it has no nervous
|
|
system."
|
|
non-AR: "Does dissimilarity rule out 'pain'?"
|
|
AR: "Yes."
|
|
non-AR: "That's completely illogical and unscientific."
|
|
|
|
Note how Poster A would invoke the authority of logic and
|
|
science as "completely" on his side. Next, consider the
|
|
assertions of Poster B:
|
|
|
|
As a plant molecular biologist with quite a few
|
|
refereed papers on the subject of cellular
|
|
communication in plants, please allow me to debunk the
|
|
unsubstantiated mythology described above. Plants have
|
|
no *need* to feel pain? Ridiculous.
|
|
|
|
When a plant is attacked by an herbivorous insect,
|
|
might it not be in the best interest of the plant to
|
|
mobilize its chemical defenses in other parts of the
|
|
plant in anticipation of further insect attack? When a
|
|
leaf is infected by a pathogenic fungus, might the rest
|
|
of the plant wish to bolster its chemical and enzymatic
|
|
defenses against the spread of the pathogen? News
|
|
flash -- the plant *would* benefit, hence the
|
|
development of a systemic (throughout the plant)
|
|
response to local tissue damage by herbivores and
|
|
pathogens. (Many) references available upon request.
|
|
It might easily be argued that *because* plants can't
|
|
move they need effective chemical defenses and
|
|
effective detection and communication. This is the
|
|
case. You may doubt the sensory and integrative
|
|
abilities of plants, so I invite you to spend a few
|
|
weeks in my lab and learn the truth. Plants don't have
|
|
nerves, since they don't share a particularly recent
|
|
common ancestor with animals. Plants feel tissue
|
|
injury and respond quickly, precisely, and with an
|
|
effective battery of defenses. They don't feel *like
|
|
us*, but it would be a mistake to say that they *don't
|
|
feel*.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Here we have the authority of logic, science and "truth"
|
|
being imprecated against the sorry state of AR nescience and
|
|
"mythology". Yet, no single published book, or paper in a
|
|
scientific journal, has been cited as indeed making this
|
|
claim that "plants feel pain". Sure, there is interesting
|
|
evidence about plants reacting to local tissue damage and
|
|
even sending signalling molecules serving to stimulate
|
|
certain chemical defenses of nearby plants. But what has
|
|
this got to do with supporting the only morally relevant
|
|
claim worth considering, namely that "plants FEEL AND SUFFER
|
|
from pain"? Where are the scientific references for this
|
|
putative fact?
|
|
|
|
Now, dear reader, please be patient with my indulgence to
|
|
develop a reasoned reply to such assertive and authoritative
|
|
pronouncements about plant pain.
|
|
|
|
|
|
C. A REDUCTIO ON A REDUCTIO
|
|
|
|
Although the plant pain promoters are fond of reductios,
|
|
they will not likely appreciate the following extension of
|
|
their own. By their "logic", it would equally be the case
|
|
that rain clouds behave purposefully in the sense that they
|
|
could be said to functionally remove, by way of raining,
|
|
excessive moisture that is causing their overstaturation.
|
|
Furthermore, rain clouds bear meaningful information about
|
|
their level of oversaturation in the form of weight relative
|
|
to volume. Do not clouds, therefore, "sense" (in some
|
|
tortured notion of the word) when atmospheric pressure is
|
|
insufficient for their moisture content to remain in a
|
|
vaporous state? The promoters of plant pain would have us
|
|
believe, against our good common sense, that by the mere
|
|
presence of purposive BEHAVIOURS of avoidance and REACTIONS
|
|
to tissue damage in plants we therefore must attribute to
|
|
plants mental states like that of some kind of "felt pain".
|
|
Well, then by the same logic we must do the same to clouds.
|
|
In the hole that these promoters of plant pain would dig for
|
|
themselves, not only must we accept the thesis of plant
|
|
pain, we would also have to swallow some notion of "cloud
|
|
sentience"!
|
|
|
|
|
|
D. THE BEHAVIOURAL INFERENCE OF MENTAL STATES
|
|
|
|
Lest we forget the ultimate point of what follows, let us
|
|
not forget the central thesis of AR. Simply stated: to the
|
|
extent other animals share with us, at least to some degree,
|
|
certain morally relevant attributes, then to that extent we
|
|
cannot ignore, for the purposes of consistency or justice,
|
|
giving due regard and concern towards those animals. Two
|
|
attributes that are arguably relevant are:
|
|
|
|
1. our commonly shared interest in the avoidance of
|
|
pain and suffering.
|
|
|
|
2. and the quality of other animals also being
|
|
subjects-of-a-life which matters to them as to how such
|
|
a life fares well or ill.
|
|
|
|
Both these qualities posit other animals having certain
|
|
mental states. Also note that in order to speak of "mental
|
|
states" proper, we would denote, as common usage would
|
|
dictate, that such states are marked by consciousness. It
|
|
is simply insufficient to mark off mental states by only the
|
|
presence of purposefulness or intentionality since many
|
|
objects, like thermostats and hand calculators, possess
|
|
purposeful-looking behaviours or are in an information-
|
|
bearing state.
|
|
|
|
Let us further observe that the attribution of morally
|
|
relevant mental states to even humans was at one time an
|
|
issue of contention. For example, consider the case of that
|
|
very prestigious scientific apologist of his society's
|
|
ambient prejudices, Silas Mitchell, founder of American
|
|
neurology. He claimed that civilized men suffered pain in a
|
|
far more ethically relevant manner:
|
|
|
|
"In our process of being civilized we have won . . .
|
|
intensified capacity to suffer. The savage does not
|
|
feel pain as we do" [1].
|
|
|
|
Today, we can witness a similar prejudice that animals do
|
|
not suffer pain to the same capacity as we do. For
|
|
instance, a cow after surgery will right away start eating
|
|
grass, therefore it will be said that the cow cannot be
|
|
suffering from post-surgery pain. Just as with the stoic
|
|
"savage", who is to say that a cow is not likewise simply
|
|
bearing the pain more "heroically" since, as with the non-
|
|
civilized human, food is more of an imperative than moaning
|
|
with pain; indeed, what else can they do?
|
|
|
|
So then, how do we properly attribute the existence of
|
|
mental states to other animals, or even to ourselves for
|
|
that matter, since in the past we have certainly made
|
|
mistakes on this score? As we have seen, the *criterion of
|
|
outward functional behaviour* has been faulty with even
|
|
humans. Yet, our plant pain promoters would employ this
|
|
same criterion at a different level, turn things on their
|
|
head and argue that because plants react to noxious stimuli,
|
|
they therefore feel pain. Now, if the inference of pain
|
|
from overt behaviours has been faulty for attributing pain
|
|
where we now know pain most assuredly exists, then it is
|
|
probably equally faulty in attributing pain where pain does
|
|
not exist. If reactions or behaviours were sufficient, then
|
|
we would have to say that a mere toy doll crying and
|
|
wriggling, when triggered to do so by certain stimuli, was
|
|
indeed in pain.
|
|
|
|
Similarly, we cannot infer the presence of felt pain simply
|
|
by the presence of a sub-class of behaviours which are
|
|
functional for an organism's amelioration or avoidance of
|
|
noxious stimuli. Thermostats obviously react to thermal
|
|
changes in the environment and respond in a functionally
|
|
appropriate manner to restore an initial "preferred" state
|
|
thereby maintaining an equilibrium of the status quo. We
|
|
would be dirt foolish, however, to then attribute to
|
|
thermostats that therefore they must "sense" or "feel" some
|
|
kind of "pain". Even warning quotes around our terms don't
|
|
protect us from such an catachrestic absurdity.
|
|
|
|
Clearly, the behavioral criterion of even functional
|
|
avoidance/defense reactions, is simply not sufficient nor
|
|
even necessary for the proper attribution of pain as a felt
|
|
mental state. This is not to say that it is completely
|
|
irrelevant for it can at least index the presence of pain in
|
|
those creatures we already know or have good reason to
|
|
believe experience and suffer pain. Behaviour by itself
|
|
does not index pain in our toy doll or thermostat, but
|
|
behaviour does usefully index the occurrence of pain and
|
|
suffering in those animals that we already have reason to
|
|
believe have the capacity to suffer.
|
|
|
|
|
|
E. THE RELEVANCE OF SPECIALIZED STRUCTURE
|
|
|
|
To state the obvious, science, including the biological
|
|
sciences, are generally committed to the working assumption
|
|
of scientific materialism or physicalism [2]. Now, unless
|
|
the "new" biology has returned to some arcane version of
|
|
vitalism or dualism, then we must start with the generally
|
|
accepted scientific assumption that matter is the only
|
|
existent or real primordial constituent of the universe.
|
|
|
|
Let it be said at the outset that scientific materialism as
|
|
such does not preclude the existence of emergent or
|
|
functional qualities like that of mind, consciousness, and
|
|
feeling (or even, dare I say it, free will), but all such
|
|
qualities are dependant upon the existence of organized
|
|
matter. If there is no hardware, there is nothing for the
|
|
software to run on. If there is no intact, living brain,
|
|
there is simply no mind. Now, just for the record it should
|
|
also be said that even contemporary versions of dualism or
|
|
mind-stuff theories will also make depended their embodied
|
|
mental states in this world on the presence of sufficiently
|
|
organized matter.
|
|
|
|
To briefly state the case, what is referred to as non-
|
|
reductive materialism [3] would simply consider cognitive
|
|
functions like consciousness and mind as emergent properties
|
|
of sufficiently organized matter. Just as breathing is a
|
|
function of a complex system of organs referred to
|
|
aggregately as the respiratory system, so too is
|
|
consciousness a function of the immensely complex
|
|
information-processing capabilities of a central nervous
|
|
system. Now, according to such a neo-functionalist account
|
|
of mental states, HOW the matter is organized and in with
|
|
WHAT materials is not necessarily delimited to the mammalian
|
|
brain. It is possible in theory, that our Alpha Centaurians
|
|
who evolved from carrots could equally instantiate some
|
|
"higher" functions of consciousness. This may even be
|
|
possible with a future computer given a sufficiently complex
|
|
and orderly organization of its hardware and clever
|
|
software. While such a computer does not yet exist, and we
|
|
don't yet know about those Alpha Centaurians, we DO know
|
|
that certain living organisms on this planet do possess the
|
|
requisite complexity of specialized and highly organized
|
|
structure for the emergence of mental states.
|
|
|
|
In theory, plants could possess a mental state like pain,
|
|
but IF, AND ONLY IF there is a requisite complexity of
|
|
organized plant tissue which could serve to INSTANTIATE the
|
|
kinds of complex information processing that is prerequisite
|
|
to such higher order mental states as that of consciousness
|
|
and felt pain. A mammalian brain is not necessary but an
|
|
immensely complex hierarchically organized central processor
|
|
of some form would be.
|
|
|
|
Now, where is the morphological evidence that such a
|
|
complexity of tissue in plants exist? Single cells or even
|
|
aggregates of surrounding tissue is not sufficient for there
|
|
to be a functional state of felt pain any more than even
|
|
todays complex integrated circuit chips evince consciousness
|
|
of any kind. A lot is required and plants just don't have
|
|
it. This is not to say that they cannot exhibit complex
|
|
reactions, but we are simply OVER-INTERPRETING such
|
|
reactions when they are designated as "felt pain".
|
|
|
|
With respect to all mammals, birds, and reptiles, we know
|
|
that they possess a sufficiently complex neural structure to
|
|
enable felt pain plus an evolutionary need for such
|
|
consciously felt states. They possess complex and
|
|
specialized organizations of tissue call sense organs, they
|
|
possess a specialized and complex structure for processing
|
|
information and for centrally orchestrating appropriate
|
|
behaviours in accordance with mental representations,
|
|
integrations and reorganizations of that information. The
|
|
proper attribution of felt pain in these animals is well
|
|
justified, but it is not for plants by any stretch of the
|
|
imagination.
|
|
|
|
|
|
ted
|
|
|
|
|
|
I. REFERENCES
|
|
|
|
[1] Cited from M. Pernick's (1985) "A CALCULUS OF SUFFERING:
|
|
PAIN, PROFESSIONALISM AND ANESTHESIA IN 19TH C.
|
|
AMERICA. New York: Columbia University Press. Cited
|
|
in turn in Bernard Rollin's (1989), "THE UNHEEDED CRY:
|
|
ANIMAL CONSCIOUSNESS, ANIMAL PAIN AND SCIENCE".
|
|
Oxford: Oxford University Press. I would strongly
|
|
recommend Rollin's book as a very well argued and
|
|
documented scholarly work on this important issue.
|
|
|
|
[2] Burtt, E. A. (1924). THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS OF
|
|
MODERN SCIENCE. London: Routledge & Kegan
|
|
[3] See Flanagan, Owen's THE SCIENCE OF THE MIND (2n ed).
|
|
Mass.: The MIT Press. Provides for a good review of
|
|
these issues.
|
|
THE FALLACIES BEHIND THE PLANT PAIN ARGUMENT
|
|
|
|
Many are destined to reason wrongly, others, not to
|
|
reason at all; and others, to persecute those who do
|
|
reason. (Voltaire)
|
|
|
|
|
|
How, then, could anybody seriously entertain this humbug of plant
|
|
pain? Is it not remarkable that the most persistent and
|
|
articulate of the anti-AR would forward such contentious and
|
|
prima facie absurd claims. But I guess it is not so remarkable
|
|
if we keep in mind their dogged intent to debunk the claims of
|
|
animal rights, seemingly no matter at what cost to good sense,
|
|
rationality, or even established scientific fact. Since, as we
|
|
have seen, many would claim to be avowed ethical subjectivists,
|
|
at least when it is convenient to do so, I guess we should not be
|
|
surprised that rationality and intellect is merely made sullied
|
|
handmaidens for advancing their quest to discredit the case for
|
|
animal rights.
|
|
|
|
What follows, dear reader, are five of the common flaws of reason
|
|
masquerading as arguments on behalf of plant rights.
|
|
|
|
|
|
1. Error #1: THE ARGUMENTUM AD IGNORANTIUM
|
|
|
|
In the name of open-mindedness, we are asked to take seriously
|
|
the claim of plant pain because the disbelievers and the
|
|
incredulous simply cannot prove that plants have no felt pain, or
|
|
that our knowledge of such things as with many other things, is
|
|
simply incomplete and uncertain. For instance, it has been said
|
|
that:
|
|
|
|
"The simple fact that "cruelty" cannot be DIS-proved
|
|
introduces reasonable doubt into this argument."
|
|
|
|
Here we have the presumption of innocence found in a court of law
|
|
being inappropriately transferred to how scientific theories are
|
|
to be established or seriously entertained. Normally, we would
|
|
argue on BEHALF of a scientific theory by presenting evidence for
|
|
it, not by pointing to our current lack of evidence unless one is
|
|
arguing AGAINST a theory. The plant pain promoters would turn
|
|
the logic of scientific justification on its head.
|
|
|
|
Now, in a general or ultimate sense it is TRIVIALLY TRUE that
|
|
there is no final "proof" against such wild notions, but then
|
|
there is also no ultimate proof against unicorns or ghosts. It
|
|
is a well known INFORMAL FALLACY to conclude from a lack of
|
|
disproof for something's existence that it therefore exists or
|
|
must be taken as a serious possibility for existence. That is to
|
|
say, it is simply false to argue that a proposition is true
|
|
simply on the basis that it has not been proved false. The idea
|
|
here is to try to persuade people of a proposition which avails
|
|
itself of facts and reasons the falsity or inadequacy of which is
|
|
not readily discerned.
|
|
|
|
This flawed logic is technically referred to by logicians as the
|
|
"ARGUMENTUM AD IGNORANTIUM" (argument from ignorance). This is a
|
|
logically invalid argument, one that would exploit our common
|
|
ignorance of things. Now, you might ask, why shouldn't we permit
|
|
speculative theories to enter into our foundation of ethics.
|
|
Consider, however, the following example:
|
|
|
|
"no breath of scandal has ever touched the mayor,
|
|
therefore she is MUST be incorruptibly honest".
|
|
|
|
Maybe she is and maybe she is not, but our ignorance does not
|
|
establish the truth or falsity of the conclusion that she is
|
|
incorruptibly honesty. It is simply unfair to employ our
|
|
ignorance as the sole basis of support for some social/public
|
|
concern.
|
|
|
|
Similarly, what we DO KNOW about how animals experience pain and
|
|
suffering is of relevance for a system of public ethics. What we
|
|
do know about plants is that they DO NOT HAVE a nervous system
|
|
nor a structure at the cellular level designed to process
|
|
information in a manner that would conceivably enable a conscious
|
|
suffering of pain or discomfort. What we do NOT YET KNOW about
|
|
the workings of plants, of how consciousness in general is
|
|
enabled, or of how the universe as a whole works, is simply not
|
|
relevant. It is one thing to plea for open-mindedness, it is
|
|
quite another to promote intellectual promiscuity under the same
|
|
banner.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2. Error #2: EQUIVOCATION OF TERMS TO BOOTLEG A FALSE
|
|
CONCLUSION
|
|
|
|
To understand this very slippery and flawed reasoning that
|
|
logicians refer to as the informal fallacy of EQUIVOCATION,
|
|
consider the following example:
|
|
|
|
"The end of a thing is its perfection;
|
|
death is the end of life;
|
|
hence, death is the perfection of life"
|
|
|
|
Note the two senses of the word "end" and how the last part of
|
|
the sentence confuses them. The word "end" may mean either
|
|
"goal" or "last event". Both meanings are legitimate, but to
|
|
confuse the two in an argument is a fallacy. In the example
|
|
above we have two legitimate premises but a false conclusion that
|
|
does not follow from the premises, unless we remove the
|
|
equivocation and rewrite, say, the first premise as:
|
|
|
|
"The LAST EVENT of a thing is its perfection".
|
|
|
|
But such a premise is patently false.
|
|
|
|
This is exactly the kind of flawed argumentation that is
|
|
occurring with our promoters of plant pain. For instance, the
|
|
term "sentient" is deemed applicable to plants given ONE of its
|
|
meanings to simply be the "responsiveness to sensory stimuli".
|
|
After arguing further that what plants do at a molecular level
|
|
can be deemed a "sensory response", even thought they do not
|
|
possess specialized organizations of tissue called sense organs
|
|
(see error #3 below), they would then have us accept the
|
|
designation that plants are "sentient".
|
|
|
|
Let us, for the sake of argument, accept their twisted meaning of
|
|
the term of "sentient" to simply mean a functional reaction on a
|
|
biochemical or cellular level to noxious or warning stimuli. In
|
|
this sense, they will argue that a plant can be said to be
|
|
"sentient". But at a different juncture they would then have us
|
|
conclude that because plants are indeed "sentient" they also
|
|
"feel" tissue injury or assault as "unpleasant"! What the wily
|
|
plant pain promoters have done is simply bootleg a false
|
|
conclusion by switching between two quite difference meanings of
|
|
the word "sentient". Permit me to lay it out:
|
|
|
|
premise 1: Plants are responsive to "sense" impressions
|
|
premise 2: As defined in the dictionary, anything
|
|
responsive to sense impressions are sentient
|
|
conclusion 1: Plants are sentient
|
|
|
|
|
|
Note that premise 1 employs the word "sense" in a very
|
|
restrictive manner to mean, for the plant pain promoters,
|
|
"reactions to certain stimuli". Now, for them to jump from this
|
|
minimal and idiosyncratic usage of "sentient" to the issue of
|
|
plant pain, our wily abusers of ordinary language IMPLICITLY are
|
|
forwarding something like the following argument.
|
|
|
|
conclusion 1: Plants are sentient
|
|
premise 3: Sentient beings are conscious of sense
|
|
impressions
|
|
conclusion 2: plants are conscious of sense impressions
|
|
|
|
premise 4: To be conscious of a noxious stimuli is felt as
|
|
unpleasant
|
|
conclusion 3: noxious stimuli to plants is unpleasant
|
|
|
|
|
|
From unpleasant we then arrive at plant pain. Of course, our
|
|
plant promoters will protest that they never said that plants
|
|
have "consciousness" or "feel" pain, but only that they respond
|
|
in a manner similar to how we respond to pain. Well, if that be
|
|
truly the only claim and no more, then there is simply no
|
|
relevance whatsoever of such an idiosyncratic notion plant "pain"
|
|
to the real ethical issue of animals suffering from felt pain.
|
|
If it is not irrelevant, then we have either one of 2 results:
|
|
|
|
1. equivocating on usage of "sentient" to bootleg a false
|
|
conclusion. This is a logical, not a semantic, fallacy.
|
|
|
|
2. redefining what ordinary people mean by pain and
|
|
suffering so that these terms no longer refer to a conscious
|
|
awareness of pain/suffering. Now we have the error of
|
|
irrelevant re-definition. This brings us to the next error
|
|
of reasoning.
|
|
|
|
|
|
3. Error #3: LOGOMACHY OR "LET'S PLAY RE-DEFINITION"
|
|
|
|
. For most people, "sentient" designates the capacity to feel.
|
|
That is, it would refer to a mental state, not a mere set of
|
|
behaviours. The Oxford English Dictionary list 3 core meanings,
|
|
of which the plant pain promoters will selectively choose only
|
|
one, it being the most minimal definition, namely:
|
|
|
|
"def 2: Phys. Of organs or tissues: responsive to sensory
|
|
stimuli."
|
|
|
|
Of course, they do not look any further. If they were, they
|
|
might be surprised to discover that the word "sensory" refers to
|
|
the organs of "sense" or belonging to "sensation" In turn, the
|
|
words "sense" and "sensation" refers to the organs or mental
|
|
states of perception, of psychical affection, of consciousness,
|
|
etc. Indeed, it is designated right at the beginning that
|
|
"sensation" is "now commonly the subjective element in the
|
|
operation of the senses; psychical feeling" (OED). The meanings
|
|
that predominate refer to mental states, and as we have noted,
|
|
all mental states are marked by consciousness. Yet, our plant
|
|
pain promoters ignore these obvious conventions of ordinary word
|
|
meanings and would legislate their own. And what motivates this
|
|
re-definition of our terms? Certainly, not to promote clarity or
|
|
scientific accuracy. If plants have "pain" but no consciousness
|
|
then what are we to make of such muddy oxymorons as that of an
|
|
"unconscious pain" or an "unfelt pain"?
|
|
|
|
If our promoters of plant pain weren't so blunt serious, this
|
|
might all be very funny. Indeed, good puns and amusing gaffs
|
|
result from an incongruous and inapposite word usage. For
|
|
example, someone once stole the seats from all the toilets in a
|
|
Canadian RCMP station. The official press release by the
|
|
Mounties said that they still had nothing to go on. Methinks our
|
|
pain promoters also have nothing to go on.
|
|
|
|
|
|
4. Error #4: REMOTE PARALLELS DO NOT MAKE FOR IDENTITIES
|
|
|
|
Now, we have been entertained by our plant pain promoters of some
|
|
interesting facts like that of oak trees diverting some of its
|
|
activity to an increase production of tannic acid in respond to,
|
|
say, a Gypsy moth invasion. We are informed that:
|
|
|
|
> There IS a parallel here, and the relative complexity of the
|
|
> sensory and interpretive mechanisms is irrelevant.
|
|
|
|
The cruel fact remains, however, that PARALLELS DO NOT MAKE FOR
|
|
IDENTITIES. Indeed, how something is achieved is just as
|
|
important as what is being achieved in order to properly
|
|
attribute there to be identity. For animals, conscious
|
|
motivation to avoid pain figures very large in how they would
|
|
avoid or mitigate pain. Pain is not something that is unfelt.
|
|
It makes no sense to speak of "unfelt, unconscious pain", yet our
|
|
plant pain promoters will insist upon there being a morally
|
|
relevant parallel.
|
|
|
|
To illustrate this point about identity, please permit me to work
|
|
from a different and more familiar example. Now, it has been
|
|
argued that computers "think" as evidence by their capacity to
|
|
manipulate symbols. What shall we make of this?.
|
|
|
|
Searle's (1980) well-known Chinese room argument, however, at
|
|
least makes clear that computers as syntactic engines are not
|
|
"understanders" of language even if they should one day be
|
|
successful at translating from Chinese to English back to
|
|
Chinese. The subjective life and mind accompanying a person's
|
|
performances would seem to involve more than the computer's
|
|
superior efficiency at manipulating data according to sequences
|
|
of algorithm-governed operations. To even here speak of "rule-
|
|
governed operations" is misleading since it suggests we can talk
|
|
of these machines under the description of them "following
|
|
rules". Shanker (1987) makes the case that this violates our
|
|
logical grammar of rule-following being a normative rather a
|
|
mechanical action and that it is an action predicated on some
|
|
necessary minimal "understanding" of the rule. Due to the
|
|
literal ascription implied by this trope about computers, we are
|
|
lapsing into the same kind of conceptual confusion that would
|
|
occur if we were to literally ascribe to the members of a meeting
|
|
that they were following Robert's rules of order even though they
|
|
were ignorant of, or did not understand the rules. If we were to
|
|
say such a thing, it would only be FIGURATIVE for simply saying
|
|
that the members just happen to be inadvertently or unknowingly
|
|
abiding by Robert's rules. Notwithstanding the generosities of
|
|
idealization and wishful rhetoric, the computer analogue still
|
|
remains a metaphor and one that too often invites a misleading
|
|
anthropomorphism (Dreyfus, 1987).
|
|
|
|
Indeed, as the problems of the computer metaphor are becoming
|
|
more widely appreciated and, as Michie (1982) notes, the former
|
|
heuristic value of the metaphor is being replaced by more exact
|
|
and fruitful formalizations and mathematics, the metaphor is
|
|
beginning to become less frequent in the scientific prose of AI
|
|
science itself. While anthropomorphic speculation inaugurated
|
|
both the animal and computer models, it is a circumspect
|
|
anthropomorphism tempered with naturalism that now appears to be
|
|
the most fruitful approach for the understanding of animals
|
|
(Griffin, 1981), but it is an "objectivist", or more precisely an
|
|
electrical-mechanical and symbolic-mathematical prose, that is
|
|
more fitting for AI. With respect to plants, the language of
|
|
mental states is simply addleheaded and daft.
|
|
|
|
|
|
5. Error #5: OVER-INTERPRETATION OF ESTABLISHED FACTS
|
|
|
|
Now, we have been told that "there IS some evidence which shows
|
|
that plants are "sentient", in the broad sense of the word."
|
|
Hmm., more likely the narrow and twisted sense of the word. But
|
|
again, all we have is simply the interesting but morally
|
|
irrelevant facts about plants reacting to certain noxious
|
|
stimuli, or to the signalling molecules of other plants under
|
|
attack. We are then asked about how this might be different from
|
|
our own sense of smell. They would ask, "is this not equivalent
|
|
to plant sensation or of a plant sensing its environment?" By
|
|
now, we should be able to readily reply that such usage simply
|
|
stretches our ordinary definitions of the word "sense". Mere
|
|
behavioural reactions and avoidance to certain stimuli is
|
|
insufficient for the attributions of mental states like that of
|
|
perceptions and knowing sensation. Again, we have either an
|
|
equivocation of usage to bootleg false conclusion, or we simply
|
|
have a re-defninition of our ordinary meanings to something
|
|
idiosyncratic and morally irrelevant. HOW the plants do what
|
|
they do is just as important as the function of what those
|
|
reactions subserve.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Here is an example of over-interpretation that was due to this
|
|
error of only observing the end result and not the means. It was
|
|
once thought that army ants were comprised of a strategic
|
|
military column marching through the forest with direction,
|
|
purpose and foresight. Well, it turns out that these ants simply
|
|
follow the smell of the ants in front, and in turn the leading
|
|
ants simply, in a somewhat random manner, lurch or are, pushed
|
|
forward. If these ants were to be placed on a flat surface and
|
|
the leading ants were to make a circle back to the rump end of
|
|
the column, the marching column of ants would simply go around
|
|
and around until they died. Where is the intentional purpose,
|
|
planning and foresight? There is no scouting ahead of the
|
|
terrain, no deliberative leadership, just a very simply mechanism
|
|
that under normal conditions in the uneven terrain of the forest
|
|
works very effectively to keep the ants ever moving forward in
|
|
search new food supplies. The key point is that for many
|
|
centuries people over-interpreted what was going on simply
|
|
because they only observed the overt functional behaviours and
|
|
not the means and enabling conditions for those behaviours.
|
|
|
|
|
|
6. THE BELIEF IN NON-EXISTENT PAINS. :-)
|
|
|
|
Patient reader, permit me to finish with one last observation.
|
|
Hypochondriacs are, as you know, people who believe in pains that
|
|
simply don't exist. This much they have in common with our plant
|
|
pain promoters. Of course, hypochondriacs also are easily
|
|
persuaded that they must themselves have what even the most
|
|
superficial description of an illness would describe. I'll leave
|
|
it to the reader to decide if this parallel also applies to our
|
|
plant pain promoters. Now, there is the amusing story of one
|
|
such person who after hearing a lecture on diseases of the
|
|
kidney, immediately phoned his doctor. The good doctor patiently
|
|
explained that in that particular disease there were no pains or
|
|
discomfort of any kind, whereupon our hypochondriac gasped, "I
|
|
knew it, my symptoms exactly!" :-)
|
|
|
|
|
|
ted
|
|
|
|
|
|
REFERENCES
|
|
|
|
|
|
Dreyfus, Hubert L. (1987). Misrepresenting human intelligence.
|
|
In Rainer Born (Ed.), Artificial intelligence: The case
|
|
against. London: Croom Helm.
|
|
Griffin, Donald R. (1981). The question of animal awareness:
|
|
Evolutionary continuity of mental experience (2nd ed.).
|
|
California: William Kaufmann. Another good book that I
|
|
would highly recommend.
|
|
Michie, Donald (1982). Machine intelligence and related topics.
|
|
London: Gordon & Breach Science Publishers.
|
|
Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and
|
|
Brain Sciences, 3, 417-457.
|
|
Shanker, S. G. (1987). The decline and fall of the mechanist
|
|
metaphor. In Rainer Born (Ed.), Artificial intelligence:
|
|
The case against. London: Croom Helm.
|
|
Taylor, Charles (1964). The explanation of behaviour. London:
|
|
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
|
|
|