257 lines
17 KiB
Plaintext
257 lines
17 KiB
Plaintext
ÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÜ ÜÜÜ ÜÜÜÜ
|
|
ÜÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛßÛßßßßßÛÛÜ ÜÜßßßßÜÜÜÜ ÜÛÜ ÜÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜÜÜÜÜÛßß ßÛÛ
|
|
ßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜ ßÛÛ ÜÛÛÛÜÛÛÜÜÜ ßÛÛÛÛÜ ßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜÛÛÜÜÜÛÛÝ Ûß
|
|
ßßßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜ ÞÝ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛßßÛÜÞÛÛÛ ÛÛÛÛÛÜ ßßÛÛÛÞß
|
|
Mo.iMP ÜÛÛÜ ßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝÛ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÞÛÛÛÛ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÝ ßÛß
|
|
ÜÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÛÛÛ ÛÛÛÛÛÛ
|
|
ÜÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ß ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÜ ÜÛ
|
|
ÜÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÞÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛß
|
|
ÜÛßÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÜÜ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÛÛÞÛÛÛÛÛÝ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛßß
|
|
ÜÛßÛÛÛÛÛÛÜÛÛÛÛÜÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ÞÛ ßÛÛÛÛÛ Ü ÛÝÛÛÛÛÛ Ü
|
|
ÜÛ ÞÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛß ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛ ßÛÜ ßÛÛÛÜÜ ÜÜÛÛÛß ÞÛ ÞÛÛÛÝ ÜÜÛÛ
|
|
ÛÛ ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛß ÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜ ßÛÜ ßßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛß ÜÜÜß ÛÛÛÛÜÜÜÜÜÜÜÛÛÛÛÛß
|
|
ßÛÜ ÜÛÛÛß ßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÛÜ ßßÜÜ ßßÜÛÛßß ßÛÛÜ ßßßÛßÛÛÛÛÛÛÛßß
|
|
ßßßßß ßßÛÛß ßßßßß ßßßßßßßßßßßßß
|
|
ARRoGANT CoURiERS WiTH ESSaYS
|
|
|
|
Grade Level: Type of Work Subject/Topic is on:
|
|
[ ]6-8 [ ]Class Notes [Analysis on the ]
|
|
[ ]9-10 [ ]Cliff Notes [Philisopher Berkely ]
|
|
[x]11-12 [x]Essay/Report [and his view of God. ]
|
|
[ ]College [ ]Misc [ ]
|
|
|
|
Dizzed: 10/94 # of Words:2559 School: ? State: ?
|
|
ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>Chop Here>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ>ÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄÄ
|
|
As man progressed through the various stages of evolution, it is
|
|
assumed that at a certain point he began to ponder the world around him. Of
|
|
course, these first attempts fell short of being scholarly, probably
|
|
consisting of a few grunts and snorts at best. As time passed on, though,
|
|
these ideas persisted and were eventually tackled by the more intellectual,
|
|
so-called philosophers. Thus, excavation of "the external world" began. As
|
|
the authoritarinism of the ancients gave way to the more liberal views of
|
|
the modernists, two main positions concerning epistemology and the nature
|
|
of the world arose. The first view was exemplified by the empiricists, who
|
|
stated that all knowledge comes from the senses. In opposition, the
|
|
rationalists maintained that knowledge comes purely from deduction, and
|
|
that this knowledge is processed by certain innate schema in the mind.
|
|
Those that belonged to the empiricist school of thought developed quite
|
|
separate and distinct ideas concerning the nature of the substratum of
|
|
sensible objects. John Locke and David Hume upheld the belief that
|
|
sensible things were composed of material substance, the basic framework
|
|
for the materialist position. The main figure who believed that material
|
|
substance did not exist is George Berkeley. In truth, it is the
|
|
immaterialist position that seems the most logical when placed under close
|
|
scrutiny.
|
|
|
|
The initial groundwork for Berkeley's position is the truism that the
|
|
materialist is a skeptic. In the writing of his three dialogues, Berkeley
|
|
develops two characters: Hylas (the materialist) and Philonous (Berkeley
|
|
himself). Philonous draws upon one central supposition of the materialist
|
|
to formulate his argument of skepticism against him; this idea is that one
|
|
can never perceive the real essence of anything. In short, the materialist
|
|
feels that the information received through sense experience gives a
|
|
representative picture of the outside world (the representative theory of
|
|
perception), and one can not penetrate to the true essece of an object.
|
|
This makes logical sense, for the only way to perceive this real essence
|
|
would be to become the object itself! Although the idea is logical, it
|
|
does contain a certain grounding for agnosticism. Let the reader consider
|
|
this: if there is no way to actually sense the true material essence of
|
|
anything, and all knowledge in empiricism comes from the senses, then the
|
|
real material essence can not be perceived and therefore it can not be
|
|
posited. This deserves careful consideration, for the materialist has been
|
|
self-proclaimed a skeptic! If the believer in this theory were asked if a
|
|
mythical beast such as a cyclops existed he would most certainly say no. As
|
|
part of his reply he might add that because it can not be sensed it is not
|
|
a piece of knowledge. After being enlightened by the above proposed
|
|
argument, though, that same materialist is logically forced to agree that,
|
|
because the "material substratum1" itself can not be sensed, its existence
|
|
can not be treated as knowledge. The materialist belief has, in effect,
|
|
become as futile as proving that the cyclops exists; his ideas have lead
|
|
him into skepticism.
|
|
|
|
Having proven that the materialist is, at best, a doubter, Berkeley
|
|
goes on to offer the compelling argument that primary and secondary
|
|
qualities are, together, one thing. As the materialist believes, primary
|
|
qualities of an object are those things that are abstract (not sense
|
|
oriented). Examples of these would be number, figure, motion, and
|
|
extension. Secondary qualities are those things that are concrete (sense
|
|
oriented), such as color, smell, sound, and taste. The materialist feels
|
|
that these primary qualities persist even when the secondary ones are not
|
|
there. Thus, if a person were blind, then that individual would not be
|
|
able to hear or to touch items; yet the so-called real qualities such as
|
|
figure would remain existent in the objects. As previously shown, the
|
|
materialist is agnostic in his belief of these real (primary) qualities.
|
|
It is here that Berkeley directs an alternate hypothesis: that the abstract
|
|
primary qualities don't exist at all. In fact, the immaterialist position
|
|
states that these qualities are merely secondary in nature, as they, too,
|
|
can not be perceived as being separate from an object. For instance, if a
|
|
person is asked to imagine a primary quality alone, as an abstraction, it
|
|
is impossible. To illustrate this point, suppose that a person is asked to
|
|
think simply of number alone. This person may reply that the idea he is
|
|
formulating is that of three red spheres. In truth this is not an abstract
|
|
idea, because when the qualities of color (red) and shape (sphere) are
|
|
taken away, all that is left is three of nothing! Thus, it is impossible
|
|
to think of the abstraction of number, given that an abstract quality can
|
|
not focus on anything concrete (such as red spheres in the above mentioned
|
|
example). Therefore, it follows that, since no primary, abstract quality
|
|
can exist alone, it is the same as a secondary quality in which an actual
|
|
object must first be perceived.
|
|
|
|
Berkeley moves on to show that the perceived qualities of an object
|
|
are ideas which exist only in a mind. To do this, he states that a
|
|
sensation is an idea. This is logical, for sensations can not be felt by
|
|
mindless objects. However, it is this point which Berkeley scrutinizes in
|
|
the materialist statement that an external object "is a material substance
|
|
with the sensible qualities inhering in it.2" The materialist is
|
|
proclaiming that sensible qualities, which exist in the mind only, are
|
|
actually in the object. Logically, the only possible way for this to occur
|
|
is if the external object had a mind for the qualities to be thought of and
|
|
stored by. The notion that inanimate objects have minds is ridiculous, and
|
|
thus the materialists' belief has been reduced to absurdity. Let the
|
|
reader consider this example to reinforce the point. A ten-story building
|
|
is erected, and a person who lives in a single-story house in the country
|
|
sees the new building. To this person the structure may seem quite tall,
|
|
as he has never seen any building taller than three stories. However, a
|
|
construction worker comes across the same building and perceives its height
|
|
quite differently than the previous man. Since the second man usually works
|
|
on buildings about thirty stories high, he thinks that the building is
|
|
fairly short. Obviously, the new building can not be both tall and short
|
|
at the same time; yet this is the outcome if one believes that the quality
|
|
of tallness is inherent in the object. In fact, if the idealist
|
|
(immaterialist) position is considered it seems logical that one person
|
|
could view something differently than another. This is because the idea
|
|
concerning that thing could be different in the two separate minds.
|
|
|
|
At this point Berkeley explains that the so-called tertiary qualities
|
|
of an external object are non-existent. The materialist defines these
|
|
qualities as the ability in one object to produce change in another object.
|
|
In the three dialogues, Hylas brings up the point that these qualities are
|
|
"perceive[d] by the sense... and exist in the object that occasions
|
|
[them]3." An example of this quality would be a burning candle. Suppose
|
|
that a person puts his finger in the flame long enough to feel the pain of
|
|
a burn. The materialist would attribute this pain to the lit candle
|
|
itself, stating that the ability to produce pain is inherent in it.
|
|
However, this can not be the case. As previously discussed, the external
|
|
objects are merely ideas which we perceive through sense experience. Just
|
|
as these objects do not possess any primary or secondary qualities, they
|
|
also can not have the ability to cause change in something else. In fact,
|
|
these tertiary qualities are also ideas perceived only in the mind.
|
|
|
|
Given that objects are ideas and humans possess minds to perceive them
|
|
with, the nature of both ideas and minds deserves careful consideration.
|
|
Berkeley assumes the view that ideas are passive and only perceivable in a
|
|
mind. He goes on to state that these ideas are existent only when a mind is
|
|
perceiving them. This is logical, for when something is not being
|
|
ruminated upon it does not exist in the realm of knowledge at that
|
|
particular time. As an example, if I were to move to another country and,
|
|
after some time, forget about my old house in America, it would not exist
|
|
to me anymore. In accordance with the immaterialists' view, my actively
|
|
perceiving mind would be electing not to reflect back upon the past. Thus,
|
|
only the active mind can create the purely passive idea.
|
|
|
|
Since an idea only exists when it is being perceived or reflected upon,
|
|
this brings into question the nature of reality. For instance, assume that
|
|
a person attends an art museum early on Sunday morning. As that person
|
|
views the artwork, the paintings themselves are sensible things, or ideas,
|
|
actively being perceived by a mind; in short, they exist. However, when
|
|
the museum closes and the person goes home, does the artwork continue to
|
|
exist? Obviously the person pursues other activities of the day, and he
|
|
ceases to think about what he did earlier. However, at a certain time
|
|
those paintings were part of what the person knew to be true through
|
|
sensation; the artwork was part of the person's reality. Do the paintings
|
|
therefore cease to exist since they are no longer being thought of?
|
|
|
|
Berkley argues that such objects still exist because the mind of God is
|
|
always perceiving them. Unlike the materialists' view, the immaterialist
|
|
puts God at the center of his views. In truth, God is the "omnipresent
|
|
external mind which knows and comprehends all things, and exhibits them to
|
|
our view in such a manner and according to such rules as He Himself has
|
|
ordained and are by us termed the 'laws of nature.'4" It is important to
|
|
stress the idea that God shows people the ideas in his mind, and these
|
|
ideas make up the reality beheld by the human mind. Therefore, for any
|
|
person to perceive something, the idea must be in the mind of God first.
|
|
|
|
The fact that there are two distinct minds raises questions about the
|
|
nature of these minds. The idealist proclaims that the human mind is
|
|
strictly finite in its ability to have sense experience. With this being
|
|
the case, a person can only have a single sensation at a time. Since
|
|
sensations are the same as ideas, humans can only have one idea at once.
|
|
On the other hand, God's mind is infinite and is thus able to have multiple
|
|
perceptions. These perceptions of God are also ideas, and it follows that
|
|
these ideas comprise the reality beheld in the finite human mind. Instead
|
|
of the materialists' belief in the representative theory of perception,
|
|
where a material object has real (primary) qualities which humans perceive
|
|
as sensible (secondary) qualities, Berkeley has posited an alternate
|
|
theory. This is that God upholds all of the ideas which comprise human
|
|
reality, and people perceive these ideas as sensations directly from God's
|
|
infinite mind.
|
|
|
|
It should also be noted that just as the finite mind is different from
|
|
the infinite mind, the ideas in each mind have some certain distinctions.
|
|
The finite mind can only contemplate a limited range of thoughts. To
|
|
illustrate this, let the reader attempt to imagine an infinite number of
|
|
stars. After some intellection, the reader will realize that it is an
|
|
impossible task. This is because the human mind can only think in terms of
|
|
bounded entities; thus, in the above mentioned case, the reader may have
|
|
thought of a great many stars. However, the stars were finite in number and
|
|
could therefore not represent the notion of infinity. In short, the finite
|
|
mind can only conceive finite thoughts. Not only this, but, as previously
|
|
disgussed, humans can perceive only one thought at a time. If the reader
|
|
does not think this to be the case, then let her attempt to imagine a small
|
|
boy and a thunderstorm as completely separate ideas. Although both ideas
|
|
may be thought of, the only way for this to occur is when they are placed
|
|
in the same mental picture. In summary, the human mind has important
|
|
limits which can easily be observed.
|
|
|
|
On the contrary, the infinite mind of God is limitless in its ability
|
|
to perceive ideas. In God's mind, an infinite thought (a thought without
|
|
boundaries) can exist. This infinite idea's existence in God's mind is
|
|
more that possible; it must necessarily be the case. This is because
|
|
infinite concepts such as the number system and the universe must come
|
|
from, as do all thoughts, a mind. However, since the human mind is finite
|
|
and therefore incapable of conceiving boundless thoughts, then those
|
|
infinite ideas must arise from the infinite mind of God. Not only does
|
|
God's mind contain infinite thoughts, but it also must possess the ability
|
|
to think of, in the least, many thoughts at once. This is necessarily the
|
|
case for the collection of God's ideas which people call reality to exist;
|
|
if God did not have this ability then external objects would not exist when
|
|
the finite mind was not perceiving them.
|
|
|
|
Thus far the immaterialist position has been considered in its parts;
|
|
at this point it shall be viewed as one simple model. Let the reader
|
|
picture an isosceles triangle which is divided into three parts: the top,
|
|
middle, and bottom. At the apex of the figure is God's infinite mind. The
|
|
middle portion of the triangle is occupied by the finite minds of people.
|
|
Lastly, the bottom section contains the ideas perceived by humans. Because
|
|
God is at the pinnacle of the figure, He also perceives the ideas that
|
|
people do. However, since the human mind is finite, it can not conceive of
|
|
the infinite ideas in God's mind at the apex of the triangle. Now, the
|
|
concepts of either perceiving or being perceived can be added to the
|
|
picture. Both the top and middle portions of the figure are minds, so both
|
|
of these sections are perceivers. At the bottom of the model are ideas,
|
|
and since they do not act of their own volition, they are perceived. As
|
|
previously shown, perceivers are active and the perceived is passive.
|
|
Lastly, the concept of existence can be applied to the triangle. Since
|
|
existence is that which is either perceived or perceives5, and each part of
|
|
the model has been shown to meet one of these criteria, then the entire
|
|
triangle must be considered to exist.
|
|
|
|
In the final analysis, it is evident that Berkley's immaterialist
|
|
position is logically feasible. From his definitions of minds and ideas to
|
|
his careful attribution of their respective qualities, George Berkeley has
|
|
produced a compelling argument for his views. However, this is not all
|
|
that he has done; in fact, Berkeley has shown the necessary importance of
|
|
God. In the materialist view, a belief in God is not logically necessary
|
|
to uphold the "material substratum2." Berkeley shows that God must exist,
|
|
for He is at the heart of Berkeley's position. In short, the materialist
|
|
view allows for atheism as a possible option.
|
|
|
|
Notes. George Berkeley. "Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous."
|
|
Reason and Responsibility. Ed. Joel Feinberg p. 175.
|
|
|
|
2. Berkeley, p. 165.
|
|
3. Berkeley, p. 165.
|
|
4. Berkeley, p. 191.
|
|
5. Berkeley, p. 179.
|
|
|