604 lines
34 KiB
Plaintext
604 lines
34 KiB
Plaintext
|
|
What is Communality
|
|
|
|
The Democratic Dimension of Anarchism
|
|
|
|
by Murray Bookchin
|
|
|
|
Seldom have socially important words become more confused and
|
|
divested of their historic meaning than they are at present. Two
|
|
centuries ago, it is often forgotten, "democracy" was deprecated by
|
|
monarchists and republicans alike as "mob rule." Today, democracy is
|
|
hailed as "representative democracy," an oxymoron that refers to
|
|
little more than a republican oligarchy of the chosen few who
|
|
ostensibly speak for the powerless mass.
|
|
|
|
"Communism," for its part, once referred to a cooperative society
|
|
that would be based morally on mutual respect and on an economy in
|
|
which each contributed to the social labor fund according to his or
|
|
her ability and received the means of life according to his or her
|
|
needs. Today, "communism" is associated with the Stalinist gulag
|
|
and wholly rejected as totalitarian. Its cousin, "socialism"=D1 which
|
|
once denoted a politically free society based on various forms of
|
|
collectivism and equitable material returns for labor=D1is currently
|
|
interchangeable with a somewhat humanistic bourgeois liberalism.
|
|
|
|
During the 1980s and 1990s, as the entire social and political
|
|
spectrum has shifted ideologically to the right, "anarchism" itself
|
|
has not been immune to redefinition. In the Anglo-American sphere,
|
|
anarchism is being divested of its social ideal by an emphasis on
|
|
personal autonomy, an emphasis that is draining it of its historic
|
|
vitality. A Stirnerite individualism=D1marked by an advocacy of
|
|
lifestyle changes, the cultivation of behavioral idiosyncrasies and
|
|
even an embrace of outright mysticism =D1has become increasingly
|
|
prominent. This personalistic "lifestyle anarchism" is steadily
|
|
eroding the socialistic core of anarchist concepts of freedom.
|
|
|
|
Let me stress that in the British and American social tradition,
|
|
autonomy and freedom are not equivalent terms. By insisting on the
|
|
need to eliminate personal domination, autonomy focuses on the
|
|
individual as the formative component and locus of society. By
|
|
contrast, freedom, despite its looser usages, denotes the absence of
|
|
domination in society, of which the individual is part. This contrast
|
|
becomes very important when individualist anarchists equate
|
|
collectivism as such with the tyranny of the community over its
|
|
members.
|
|
|
|
Today, if an anarchist theorist like L. Susan Brown can assert that "a
|
|
group is a collection of individuals, no more and no less," rooting
|
|
anarchism in the abstract individual, we have reason to be
|
|
concerned. Not that this view is entirely new to anarchism; various
|
|
anarchist historians have described it as implicit in the libertarian
|
|
outlook. Thus the individual appears ab novo, endowed with natural
|
|
rights and bereft of roots in society or historical development.
|
|
|
|
But whence does this "autonomous" individual derive? What is the
|
|
basis for its =D2natural rights,=D3 beyond a priori premises and hazy
|
|
intuitions? What role does historical development play in its
|
|
formation? What social premises give birth to it, sustain it, indeed
|
|
nourish it? How can a "collection of individuals" institutionalize
|
|
itself such as to give rise to something more than an autonomy that
|
|
consists merely in refusing to impair the "liberties" of others =D1or
|
|
"negative liberty," as Isaiah Berlin called it in contradistinction to
|
|
"positive liberty," which is substantive freedom, in our case
|
|
constructed along socialistic lines.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 1. L. Susan Brown, The Politics of Individualism (Montreal:
|
|
Black Rose Books, 1993), p. 12. I do not question the sincerity of
|
|
Brown's libertarian views; she regards herself as an
|
|
anarcho-communist, as do I. But she makes no direct attempt to
|
|
reconcile her individualistic views with communism in any form.
|
|
Both Bakunin and Kropotkin would have strongly disagreed with her
|
|
formulation of what constitutes "a group," while Margaret Thatcher,
|
|
clearly for reasons of her own, might be rather pleased with it,
|
|
since it is so akin to the former British prime minister's notorious
|
|
statement that there is no such thing as society=D1there are only
|
|
individuals. Certainly Brown is not a Thatcherite, nor Thatcher an
|
|
anarchist, but however different they may be in other respects, both
|
|
have ideological filiations with classical liberalism that make their
|
|
shared affirmations of the "autonomy" of the individual possible. I
|
|
cannot ignore the fact, however, that neither Bakunin's, Kropotkin's
|
|
nor my own views are treated with any depth in Brown's book (pp.
|
|
156-62), and her account of them is filled with serious
|
|
inaccuracies.
|
|
|
|
In the history of ideas, "autonomy," referring to strictly personal
|
|
"self-rule," found its ancient apogee in the imperial Roman cult of
|
|
libertas. During the rule of the Julian Claudian Caesars, the Roman
|
|
citizen enjoyed a great deal of autonomy to indulge his own desires
|
|
and lusts=D1without reproval from any authority, provided that he did
|
|
not interfere with the business and the needs of the state. In the
|
|
more theoretically developed liberal tradition of John Locke and
|
|
John Stuart Mill, autonomy acquired a more expansive sense that
|
|
was opposed ideologically to excessive state authority. During the
|
|
nineteenth century, if there was any single subject that gained the
|
|
interest of classical liberals, it was political economy, which they
|
|
often conceived not only as the study of goods and services, but also
|
|
as a system of morality. Indeed, liberal thought generally reduced
|
|
the social to the economic. Excessive state authority was opposed in
|
|
favor of a presumed economic autonomy. Ironically, liberals often
|
|
invoked the word freedom, in the sense of "autonomy," as they do to
|
|
the present day.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 2. Liberals were not always in accord with each other nor
|
|
did they hold notably coherent doctrines. Mill, a free-thinking
|
|
humanitarian and utilitarian, in fact, exhibited a measure of
|
|
sympathy for socialism. I am not singling out here any particular
|
|
liberal theorist, be he Mill, Adam Smith or Friedrich Hayek. Each had
|
|
or has his or her individual eccentricity or personal line of thought. I
|
|
am speaking of traditional liberalism as a whole, whose general
|
|
features involve a belief in the "laws" of the marketplace and "free"
|
|
competition. Marx was by no means free of this influence: he, too,
|
|
unrelentingly tried to discover "laws" of society, as did many
|
|
socialists during the last century, including utopians like Charles
|
|
Fourier.
|
|
|
|
Despite their assertions of autonomy and distrust of state authority,
|
|
however, these classical liberal thinkers did not in the last instance
|
|
hold to the notion that the individual is completely free from lawful
|
|
guidance. Indeed, their interpretation of autonomy actually
|
|
presupposed quite definite arrangements beyond the individual=D1
|
|
notably, the laws of the marketplace. Individual autonomy to the
|
|
contrary, these laws constitute a social organizing system in which
|
|
all "collections of individuals" are held under the sway of the
|
|
famous "invisible hand" of competition. Paradoxically, the laws of
|
|
the marketplace override the exercise of "free will" by the same
|
|
sovereign individuals who otherwise constitute the "collection of
|
|
individuals".
|
|
|
|
No rationally formed society can exist without institutions, and if a
|
|
society as a "collection of individuals, no more and no less," were
|
|
ever to emerge. it would simply dissolve. Such a dissolution, to be
|
|
sure, would never happen in reality. The liberals, nonetheless, can
|
|
cling to the notion of a "free market" and "free competition" guided
|
|
by the "inexorable laws" of political economy.
|
|
|
|
Alternatively, freedom, a word that shares etymological roots with
|
|
the German Freiheit (for which there is no equivalent in Romance
|
|
languages), takes its point of departure not from the individual but
|
|
from the community or, more broadly, from society. In the last
|
|
century and early in the present one, as the great socialist theorists
|
|
further sophisticated ideas of freedom, the individual and his or her
|
|
development were consciously intertwined with social evolution=D1
|
|
specifically, the institutions that distinguish society from mere
|
|
animal aggregations.
|
|
|
|
What made their focus uniquely ethical was the fact that as social
|
|
revolutionaries they asked the key question=D1 What constitutes a
|
|
rational society?=D1a question that abolishes the centrality of
|
|
economics in a free society. Where liberal thought generally reduced
|
|
the social to the economic, various socialisms (apart from Marxism),
|
|
among which Kropotkin denoted anarchism the "left wing," dissolved
|
|
the economic into the social.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 3. See Kropotkin's "Anarchism," the famous Encyclopaedia
|
|
Britannica article that became one of his most widely read works.
|
|
Republished in Roger N. Baldwin, ed., Kropotkin=D5s Revolutionary
|
|
Pamphlets: A Collection of Writings by Peter Kropotkin (New York:
|
|
Vanguard Press, 1927; reprinted by Dover, 1970).
|
|
|
|
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, as Enlightenment thought
|
|
and its derivatives brought the idea of the mutability of institutions
|
|
to the foreground of social thought, the individual, too, came to be
|
|
seen as mutable. To the socialistic thinkers of the period, a
|
|
"collection" was a totally alien way of denoting society; they
|
|
properly considered individual freedom to be congruent with social
|
|
freedom, and very significantly, they defined freedom as such as an
|
|
evolving, as well as a unifying, concept.
|
|
|
|
In short, both society and the individual were historicized in the
|
|
best sense of this term: as an ever-developing, self-generative and
|
|
creative process in which each existed within and through the other.
|
|
Hopefully, this historicization would be accompanied by ev
|
|
expanding new rights and duties. The slogan of the First
|
|
International, in fact, was the demand, "No rights without duties, no
|
|
duties without rights"=D1a demand that later appeared on the
|
|
mastheads of anarchosyndicalist periodicals in Spain and elsewhere
|
|
well into the present century.
|
|
|
|
Thus, for classical socialist thinkers, to conceive of the individual
|
|
without society was as meaningless as to conceive of society
|
|
without individuals. They sought to realize both in rational
|
|
institutional frameworks that fostered the greatest degree of free
|
|
expression in every aspect of social life.
|
|
|
|
Part 2
|
|
|
|
Individualism, as conceived by classical liberalism, rested on a
|
|
fiction to begin with. Its very presupposition of a social
|
|
"lawfulness" maintained by marketplace competition was far
|
|
removed from its myth of the totally sovereign, "autonomous"
|
|
individual. With even fewer presuppositions to support itself, the
|
|
woefully undertheorized work of Max Stirner shared a similar
|
|
disjunction: the ideological disjunction between the ego and society.
|
|
|
|
The pivotal issue that reveals this disjunction=D1 indeed, this
|
|
contradiction=D1is the question of democracy. By democracy, of
|
|
course, I do not mean "representative government" in any form, but
|
|
rather face-to-face democracy. With regard to its origins in
|
|
classical Athens, democracy as I use it is the idea of the direct
|
|
management of the polis by its citizenry in popular assemblies
|
|
which is not to downplay the fact that Athenian democracy was
|
|
scarred by patriarchy, slavery, class rule and the restriction of
|
|
citizenship to males of putative Athenian birth. What I am referring
|
|
to is an evolving tradition of institutional structures, not a social
|
|
"model.=D3 Democracy generically defined, then, is the direct
|
|
management of society in face-to-face assemblies=D1in which policy
|
|
is formulated by the resident citizenry and administration is
|
|
executed by mandated and delegated councils.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 4. I have never regarded the classical Athenian democracy
|
|
as a "model" or an "ideal" to be restored in a rational society. I have
|
|
long cited Athens with admiration for one reason: the polis around
|
|
Periclean times provides us with striking evidence that certain
|
|
structures can exist=D1policy-making by an assembly, rotation and
|
|
limitation of public of offices and defense by a nonprofessional
|
|
armed citizenry. The Mediterranean world of the fifth century B.C.E.
|
|
was largely based on monarchical authority and repressive custom.
|
|
That all Mediterranean societies of that time required or employed
|
|
patriarchy, slavery and the State (usually in an absolutist form)
|
|
makes the Athenian experience all the more remarkable for what it
|
|
uniquely introduced into social life, including an unprecedented
|
|
degree of free expression. It would be naive to suppose that Athens
|
|
could have risen above the most basic attributes of ancient society
|
|
in its day, which, from a distance of 2,400 years we now have the
|
|
privilege of judging as ugly and inhuman. Regrettably, no small
|
|
number of people today are willing to judge the past by the present.
|
|
|
|
Libertarians commonly consider democracy, even in this sense, as a
|
|
form of "rule"=D1since in making decisions, a majority view prevails
|
|
and thus "rules" over a minority. As such, democracy is said to be
|
|
inconsistent with a truly libertarian ideal. Even so knowledgeable a
|
|
historian of anarchism as Peter Marshall observes that, for
|
|
anarchists, "the majority has no more right to dictate to the
|
|
minority, even a minority of one, than the minority to the majority."
|
|
Scores of libertarians have echoed this idea time and again.
|
|
|
|
What is striking about assertions like Marshall's is their highly
|
|
pejorative language. Majorities, it would seem, neither "decide" nor
|
|
"debate": rather, they "rule," "dictate," "command," "coerce" and the
|
|
like. In a free society that not only permitted but fostered the
|
|
fullest degree of dissent, whose podiums at assemblies and whose
|
|
media were open to the fullest expression of all views, whose
|
|
institutions were truly forums for discussion=D1one may reasonably
|
|
ask whether such a society would actually "dictate" to anyone when
|
|
it had to arrive at a decision that concerned the public welfa
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 5. Peter Marshall, Demanding the Impossible: A History of
|
|
Anarchism (London: Harper Collins, 1992), p. 2
|
|
|
|
How, then, would society make dynamic collective decisions about
|
|
public affairs, aside from mere individual contracts? The only
|
|
collective alternative to majority voting as a means of
|
|
decision-making that is commonly presented is the practice of
|
|
consensus. Indeed, consensus has even been mystified by avowed
|
|
"anarcho-primitivists," who consider Ice Age and contemporary
|
|
"primitive" or "primal" peoples to constitute the apogee of human
|
|
social and psychic attainment. I do not deny that consensus may be
|
|
an appropriate form of decision-making in small groups of people
|
|
who are thoroughly familiar with one another. But to examine
|
|
consensus in practical terms, my own experience has shown me that
|
|
when larger groups try to make decisions by consensus, it usually
|
|
obliges them to arrive at the lowest common intellectual
|
|
denominator in their decision-making: the least controversial or
|
|
even the most mediocre decision that a sizable assembly of people
|
|
can attain is adopted=D1 precisely because everyone must agree with
|
|
it or else withdraw from voting on that issue. More disturbingly, I
|
|
have found that it permits an insidious authoritarianism and gross
|
|
manipulations=D1even when used in the name of autonomy or freedom.
|
|
To take a very striking case in point: the largest consensus-based
|
|
movement (involving thousands of participants) in recent memory in
|
|
the United States was the Clamshell Alliance, which was formed to
|
|
oppose the Seabrook nuclear reactor in the mid-1970s in New
|
|
Hampshire. In her recent study of the movement, Barbara Epstein has
|
|
called the Clamshell the "first effort in American history to base a
|
|
mass movement on nonviolent direct action" other than the 1960s
|
|
civil rights movement. As a result of its apparent organizational
|
|
success, many other regional alliances against nuclear reactors
|
|
were formed throughout the United States.
|
|
|
|
I can personally attest to the fact that within the Clamshell
|
|
Alliance, consensus was fostered by often cynical Quakers and by
|
|
members of a dubiously "anarchic" commune that was located in
|
|
Montague, Massachusetts. This small, tightly knit faction, unified by
|
|
its own hidden agendas. was able to manipulate many Clamshell
|
|
members into subordinating their goodwill and idealism to those
|
|
opportunistic agendas. The de facto leaders of the Clamshell
|
|
overrode the rights and ideals of the innumerable individuals who
|
|
entered it and undermined their morale and will.
|
|
|
|
In order for that clique to create full consensus on a decision,
|
|
minority dissenters were often subtly urged or psychologically
|
|
coerced to decline to vote on a troubling issue, inasmuch as their
|
|
dissent would essentially amount to a one-person veto. This
|
|
practice, called "standing aside" in American consensus processes,
|
|
all too often involved intimidation of the dissenters, to the point
|
|
that they completely withdrew from the decision-making process,
|
|
rather than make an honorable and continuing expression of their
|
|
dissent by voting, even as a minority, in accordance with their
|
|
views. Having withdrawn, they ceased to be political beings=D1so that
|
|
a "decision" could be made. More than one "decision" in the Clamshell
|
|
Alliance was made by pressuring dissenters into silence, and
|
|
through a chain of such intimidations, "consensus" was ultimately
|
|
achieved only after dissenting members nullified themselves as
|
|
participants in the process.
|
|
|
|
On a more theoretical level, consensus silenced that most vital
|
|
aspect of all dialogue, dissensus. The ongoing dissent, the
|
|
passionate dialogue that still persists even after a minority accedes
|
|
temporarily to a majority decision, was replaced in the Clan shell by
|
|
dull monologues=D1and the uncontroverted and deadening tone of
|
|
consensus. In majority decision-making, the defeated minority can
|
|
resolve to overturn a decision on which they have been defeated=D1
|
|
they are free to openly and persistently articulate reasoned and
|
|
potentially persuasive disagreements. Consensus, for its part,
|
|
honors no minorities, but mutes them in favor of the metaphysical
|
|
"one" of the "consensus" group.
|
|
|
|
The creative role of dissent; valuable as an ongoing democratic
|
|
phenomenon, tends to fade away in the gray uniformity required by
|
|
consensus. Any libertarian body of ideas that seeks to dissolve
|
|
hierarchy, classes, domination and exploitation by allowing even
|
|
Marshall's "minority of one" to block decision-making by the
|
|
majority of a community, indeed, of regional and nationwide
|
|
confederations, would essentially mutate into a Rousseauean
|
|
"general will" with a nightmare world of intellectual and psychic
|
|
conformity. In more gripping times, it could easily "force people to
|
|
be free," as Rousseau put it=D1and as the Jacobins practiced it in
|
|
1793-76
|
|
|
|
The de facto leaders of the Clamshell were able to get away with
|
|
their behavior precisely because the Clamshell was not sufficiently
|
|
organized and democratically structured, such that it could
|
|
countervail the manipulation of a well-organized few. The de facto
|
|
leaders were subject to few structures of accountability for their
|
|
actions. The ease with which they cannily used consensus decisi
|
|
making for their own ends has been only partly told, but consensus
|
|
practices finally shipwrecked this large and exciting organization
|
|
with its Rousseauean "republic of virtue " It was also ruined, I may
|
|
add, by an organizational laxity that permitted mere passersby to
|
|
participate in decision-making, thereby destructuring the
|
|
organization to the point of invertebracy. It was for good reason that
|
|
I and many young anarchists from Vermont who had actively
|
|
participated in the Alliance for some few years came to view
|
|
consensus as anathema.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 6. Barbara Epstein, Political Protest and Cultural
|
|
Revolution: NonViolent Direct Action in the 1970s and 1980s
|
|
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991), especially pp. 59,
|
|
78, 89, 94-95, 167-68, 177. Although I disagree with some of the
|
|
facts and conclusions in Epstein's book=D1based on my personal as
|
|
well as general knowledge of the Clamshell Alliance=D1she vividly
|
|
portrays the failure of consensus in this movement.
|
|
|
|
If consensus could be achieved without compulsion of dissenters, a
|
|
process that is feasible in small groups, who could possibly oppose
|
|
it as a decision-making process? But to reduce a libertarian ideal to
|
|
the unconditional right of a minority=D1let alone a "minority of one"=D1
|
|
to abort a decision by a "collection of individuals" is to stifle the
|
|
dialectic of ideas that thrives on opposition, confrontation and, yes,
|
|
decisions with which everyone need not agree and should not agree,
|
|
lest society become an ideological cemetery. Which is not to deny
|
|
dissenters every opportunity to reverse majority decisions by
|
|
unimpaired discussion and advocacy.
|
|
|
|
Part 3
|
|
|
|
I have dwelled on consensus at some length because it constitutes
|
|
the usual individualistic alternative to democracy, so commonly
|
|
counterposed as "no rule"=D1or a free-floating form of personal
|
|
autonomy=D1against majority "rule." Inasmuch as libertarian ideas in
|
|
the United States and Britain are increasingly drifting toward
|
|
affirmations of personal autonomy, the chasm between
|
|
individualism and antistatist collectivism is becoming unbridgeable,
|
|
in my view. A personalistic anarchism has taken deep root among
|
|
young people today. Moreover, they increasingly use the word
|
|
"anarchy" to express not only a personalistic stance but also an
|
|
antirational, mystical, antitechnological and anticivilizational body
|
|
of views that makes it impossible for anarchists who anchor their
|
|
ideas in socialism to apply the word "anarchist" to themselves
|
|
without a qualifying adjective. Howard Ehrlich, one of our ablest and
|
|
most concerned American comrades, uses the phrase "social
|
|
anarchism" as the title of his magazine, apparently to distinguish
|
|
his views from an anarchism that is ideologically anchored in
|
|
liberalism and possibly wor??.
|
|
|
|
I would like to suggest that far more than a qualifying adjective is
|
|
needed if we are to elaborate our notion of freedom more
|
|
expansively. It would be unfortunate indeed if libertarians today had
|
|
to literally explain that they believe in a society, not a mere
|
|
collection of individuals! A century ago, this belief was presupposed;
|
|
today, so much has been stripped away from the collectivistic flesh
|
|
of classical anarchism that it is on the verge of becoming a personal
|
|
life-stage for adolescents and a fad for their middle-aged mentors,
|
|
a route to "self-realization" and the seemingly "radical" equivalent
|
|
of encounter groups.
|
|
|
|
Today, there must be a place on the political spectrum where a body
|
|
of anti-authoritarian thought that advances humanity's bitter
|
|
struggle to arrive at the realization of its authentic social life=D1the
|
|
famous "Commune of communes"=D1can be clearly articulated
|
|
institutionally as well as ideologically. There must be a means by
|
|
which socially concerned anti-authoritarians can develop a program
|
|
and a practice for attempting to change the world, not merely their
|
|
psyches. There must be an arena of struggle that can mobilize
|
|
people, help them to educate themselves and develop an
|
|
antiauthoritarian politics, to use this word in its classical meaning,
|
|
indeed that pits a new public sphere against the state and
|
|
capitalism.
|
|
|
|
In short, we must recover not only the socialist dimension of
|
|
anarchism but its political dimension: democracy. Bereft of its
|
|
democratic dimension and its communal or municipal public sphere,
|
|
anarchism may indeed denote little more than a "collection of
|
|
individuals, no more and no less." Even anarcho-communism, although
|
|
it is by far the most preferable of adjectival modifications of the
|
|
libertarian ideal, nonetheless retains a structural vagueness that
|
|
tells us nothing about the institutions necessary to expedite a
|
|
communistic distribution of goods. It spells out a broad goal, a
|
|
desideratum=D1one, alas, terribly tarnished by the association of
|
|
"communism" with Bolshevism and the state=D1but its public sphere
|
|
and forms of institutional association remain unclear at best and
|
|
susceptible to a totalitarian onus at work.
|
|
|
|
I wish to propose that the democratic and potentially practicable
|
|
dimension of the libertarian goal be expressed as Communalism, a
|
|
term that, unlike political terms that once stood unequivocally for
|
|
radical social change, has not been historically sullied by abuse.
|
|
Even ordinary dictionary definitions of Communalism, I submit,
|
|
capture to a great degree the vision of a "Commune of communes"
|
|
that is being lost by current Anglo-American trends that celebrate
|
|
anarchy variously as "chaos," as a mystical "oneness" with "nature,"
|
|
as self-fulfillment or as "ecstasy," but above all as personalist
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 7. The association of "chaos," "nomadism=D3 and "cultural
|
|
terrorism with "ontological anarchy" (as though the bourgeoisie had
|
|
not turned such antics into an =D2ecstasy industry" in the United
|
|
states) is fully explicated in Hakim Bey's (aka Peter Lamborn
|
|
Wilson) T.A.Z: The Temporary Autonomous Zone (New York:
|
|
Autonomedia, 1985). The Yuppie Whole Earth Review celebrates this
|
|
pamphlet as the most influential and widely read "manifesto" of
|
|
America's countercultural youth, noting with approval that it is
|
|
happily free of conventional anarchist attacks upon capitalism. This
|
|
kind of detritus from the 1960s is echoed in one form or another by
|
|
most American anarchist newssheets that pander to youth who have
|
|
not yet "had their fun before it is time to grow up" (a comment I
|
|
heard years later from Parisian student activists of '68) and become
|
|
real estate agents and accountants.
|
|
|
|
For an "ecstatic experience," visitors to New York's Lower East Side
|
|
(near St. Mark's Place) can dine, I am told, at Anarchy Cafe. This
|
|
establishment offers fine dining from an expensive menu, a
|
|
reproduction of the famous mural The Fourth Estate on the wall,
|
|
perhaps to aid in digestion, and a maitre d' to greet Yuppie
|
|
customers. l cannot attest to whether the writings of Guy Debord,
|
|
Raoul Vaneigem, Fredy Perlman and Hakim Bey are on sale there or
|
|
whether copies of Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, The Fifth
|
|
Estate and Demolition Derby are available for perusal, but happily
|
|
there are enough exotic bookstores nearby at which to buy them.
|
|
|
|
Communalism is defined as "a theory or system of government [sic!]
|
|
in which virtually autonomous [sic!] local communities are loosely in
|
|
a federation." No English dictionary is very sophisticated politically.
|
|
This use of the terms "government" and "autonomous" does not
|
|
commit us to an acceptance of the state and parochialism, let alone
|
|
individualism. Further, federation is often synonymous with
|
|
confederation, the term I regard as more consistent with the
|
|
libertarian tradition. What is remarkable about this (as yet)
|
|
unsullied term is its extraordinary proximity to libertarian
|
|
municipalism, the political dimension of social ecology that I have
|
|
advanced at length elsewhere.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 8. Quoted from The American Heritage Dictionary of the
|
|
English Language (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1978
|
|
|
|
In Communalism, libertarians have an available word that they can
|
|
enrich as much by experience as by theory. Most significantly, the
|
|
word can express not only what we are against, but also what we are
|
|
for, namely the democratic dimension of libertarian thought and a
|
|
libertarian form of society. It is a word that is meant for a practice
|
|
that can tear down the ghetto walls that are increasingly
|
|
imprisoning anarchism in cultural exotica and psychological
|
|
introversion. It stands in explicit opposition to the suffocating
|
|
individualism that sits so comfortably side-by-side with bourgeois
|
|
self-centeredness and a moral relativism that renders any social
|
|
action irrelevant, indeed, institutionally meaningless.
|
|
|
|
Anarchism is on the retreat today. If we fail to elaborate the
|
|
democratic dimension of anarchism, we will miss the opportunity
|
|
not only to form a vital movement, but to prepare people for a
|
|
revolutionary social praxis in the future. Alas, we are witnessing
|
|
the appalling desiccation of a great tradition, such that n
|
|
Situationists, nihilists, primitivists, antirationalists,
|
|
anticivilizationists and avowed "chaotics" are closeting themselves
|
|
in their egos, reducing anything resembling public political activity
|
|
to juvenile antics.
|
|
|
|
None of which is to deny the importance of a libertarian culture, one
|
|
that is aesthetic, playful and broadly imaginative. The anarchists of
|
|
the last century and part of the present one justifiably took pride in
|
|
the fact that many innovative artists, particularly painters and
|
|
novelists, aligned themselves with anarchic views of reality and
|
|
morality. But behavior that verges on a mystification of criminality,
|
|
asociality, intellectual incoherence, anti-intellectualism and
|
|
disorder for its own sake is simply lumpen. It feeds on the dregs of
|
|
capitalism itself. However much such behavior invokes the "rights"
|
|
of the ego as it dissolves the political into the personal or inflates
|
|
the personal into a transcendental category, it is a priori in the
|
|
sense that has no origins outside the mind to even potentially
|
|
support it. As Bakunin and Kropotkin argued repeatedly, individuality
|
|
has never existed apart from society and the individual's own
|
|
evolution has been coextensive with social evolution. To speak of
|
|
"The Individual" apart from its social roots and social involvements
|
|
is as meaningless as to speak of a society that contains no people or
|
|
institutions.
|
|
|
|
Merely to exist, institutions must have form, as I argued some thirty
|
|
years ago in my essay "The Forms of Freedom," lest freedom itself=D1
|
|
individual as well as social=D1 lose its definability. Institutions must
|
|
be rendered functional, not abstracted into Kantian categories that
|
|
float in a rarefied academic air. They must have the tangibility of
|
|
structure, however offensive a term like structure may be to
|
|
individualist libertarians: concretely, they must have the means,
|
|
policies and experimental praxis to arrive at decisions. Unless
|
|
everyone is to be so psychologically homogeneous and society's
|
|
interests so uniform in character that dissent is simply
|
|
meaningless, there must be room for conflicting proposals,
|
|
discussion, rational explication and majority decisions=D1in short,
|
|
democracy.
|
|
|
|
Like it or not, such a democracy, if it is libertarian, will be
|
|
Communalist and institutionalized in such a way that it is face-
|
|
face, direct and grassroots, a democracy that advances our ideas
|
|
beyond negative liberty to positive liberty. A Communalist
|
|
democracy would oblige us to develop a public sphere=D1and in the
|
|
Athenian meaning of the term, a politics=D1that grows in tension and
|
|
ultimately in a decisive conflict with the state. Confederal,
|
|
antihierarchical and collectivist, based on the municipal
|
|
management of the means of life rather than their control by vested
|
|
interests (such as workers' control, private control and, more
|
|
dangerously, state control), it may justly be regarded as the
|
|
processual actualization of the libertarian ideal as a daily praxis.
|
|
|
|
The fact that a Communalist politics entails participation in
|
|
municipal elections=D1based, to be sure, on an unyielding program that
|
|
demands the formation of popular assemblies and their
|
|
confederation=D1does not mean that entry into existing village, town
|
|
and city councils involves participation in state organs, any more
|
|
than establishing an anarchosyndicalist union in a privately owned
|
|
factory involves participation in capitalist forms of production. One
|
|
need only turn to the French Revolution of 1789-94 to see how
|
|
seemingly state institutions, like the municipal "districts"
|
|
established under the monarchy in 1789 to expedite elections to the
|
|
Estates General, were transformed four years later into largely
|
|
revolutionary bodies, or "sections," that nearly gave rise to the
|
|
"Commune of communes." Their movement for a sectional democracy
|
|
was defeated during the insurrection of June 2, 1793=D1not at the
|
|
hands of the monarchy, but by the treachery of the Jacobins.
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 9. I should emphasize that I am not counterposing a
|
|
communalist democracy to such enterprises as cooperatives,
|
|
people's clinics, communes, and the like. But there should be no
|
|
illusion that such enterprises are more than exercises in popular
|
|
control and ways of bringing people together in a highly atomized
|
|
society. No food cooperative can replace giant retail food markets
|
|
under capitalism and no clinic can replace hospital complexes, any
|
|
more than a craft shop can replace factories or plants. I should
|
|
observe that the Spanish anarchists, almost from their inception,
|
|
took full note of the limits of the cooperativist movement in the
|
|
1880s, when such movements were in fact more feasible than they
|
|
are today, and they significantly separated themselves from
|
|
cooperativism programmatically.
|
|
|
|
Capitalism will not generously provide us the popular democratic
|
|
institutions we need. Its control over society today is ubiquitous,
|
|
not only in what little remains of the public sphere but in the minds
|
|
of many self-styled radicals. A revolutionary people must either
|
|
assert their control over institutions that are basic to their public
|
|
lives=D1which Bakunin correctly perceived to be their municipal
|
|
councils=D1 or else they will have no choice but to withdraw into their
|
|
private lives, as is already happening on an epidemic scale today. It
|
|
would be ironic indeed if an individualist anarchism and its various
|
|
mutations, from the academic and transcendentally moral to the
|
|
chaotic and the lumpen, in the course of rejecting democracy even
|
|
for "a minority of one," were to further raise the walls of dogma
|
|
that are steadily growing around the libertarian ideal, and if,
|
|
wittingly or not, anarchism were to turn into another narcissistic
|
|
cult that snugly fits into an alienated, commodified, introverted and
|
|
egocentric society.
|
|
|
|
=D1September 18, 1
|
|
|
|
(Footnote 10. For Bakunin, the people "have a healthy, practical
|
|
common sense when it comes to communal affairs They are fairly
|
|
well informed and know how to select from their midst the most
|
|
capable officials. This is why municipal elections always best
|
|
reflect the real attitude and will of the people." Bakunin on Anarchy,
|
|
Sam Dolgoff, ed (New York: Alfred & Knopf. 1972; republished by
|
|
Black Rose Books: Montreal), p. 223.1 have omitted the queasy
|
|
interpolations that Dolgoff inserted to "modify" Bakunin's meaning.
|
|
It may be well to note that anarchism in the last century was more
|
|
plastic and flexible than it is today.
|
|
|
|
|