434 lines
21 KiB
Plaintext
434 lines
21 KiB
Plaintext
POWER AND CONSENT
|
|
|
|
REDUCTIONISM, DIALECTICS AND CONSENT THEORY
|
|
|
|
by DOUGLAS NEWDICK
|
|
|
|
|
|
1.0 Introduction
|
|
|
|
Advocates of consent theory are aware that their theory is controversial to
|
|
some degree and naturally enough this leads to a thorough defence of the
|
|
theory in any exposition. This is not unusual. What is peculiar is the
|
|
quality of that defence; the arguments that are countered are only those
|
|
ones which offer the least challenge to the thesis. These advocates of
|
|
consent theory defend their theory from counter-arguments that share the
|
|
same fundamental presuppositions, ie objections from within the liberal
|
|
democratic tradition, more radical criticisms are usually ignored or
|
|
relegated to footnotes. While there is something to be said for not trying
|
|
to defend one's theoretical basis all the time, much can be learned by
|
|
defending particular explanations from criticisms based in different
|
|
paradigms. In this essay I will explore some more radical arguments against
|
|
consent theory than those it is usually defended from. Specifically I will
|
|
attempt to show that the reductionistic and individualistic basis of
|
|
consent theory is false and/or obscures more than it reveals and that a
|
|
dialectical or non-reductionist picture can make sense of the problems that
|
|
have persistently plagued consent theories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2.0 Why Consent theory?
|
|
|
|
2.1
|
|
The basic appeal of consent theories of political obligation is that they
|
|
are in harmony with the avowed ideals, aims and bases of liberal democratic
|
|
theory. For a theory that places high value on freedom and the autonomous
|
|
action of individuals the most obvious basis for legitimate political
|
|
authority is some form of voluntary, self-assumed obligation. Consent
|
|
theory fits the bill. More specifically, some consent theorists think that
|
|
any other theory of political obligation is inconsistent with liberal
|
|
democratic theory:liberalism assumes that normal adults have the capability
|
|
for personal self-determination and that it is, therefore, appropriate to
|
|
ascribe to them a right of personal self-determination. This right includes
|
|
the right of political self-determination. From this it follows that no one
|
|
can authority, including political authority, over any normal adult without
|
|
the consent of those under such authority. (Beran, 1987, p 34)
|
|
|
|
2.2
|
|
Consent theorists appeal to consent to explain political obligation,
|
|
because they think that the notion of political obligation is troublesome
|
|
and highly contested, whereas the practice of promising giving rise to
|
|
obligation is as uncontroversial a notion as one can hope to find.
|
|
Therefore if we base our account of political obligation on consent, which
|
|
is modeled on the practice of promising, political obligation becomes
|
|
non-problematic. Pitkin (1972, pp 74-75) argues that the reason consent
|
|
theorists find political obligation troublesome and the practice of
|
|
promising not so, springs from their liberal picture of human nature. Thus
|
|
contractual theories of the state, including consent theories, flow
|
|
naturally from the liberal conception of human nature or the state of
|
|
nature.
|
|
[the liberal] picture of man in the abstract is of a man fully grown,
|
|
complete with his own private needs, interests, feelings, desires, beliefs
|
|
and values...Given man as such a separate, self-contained unit, it does
|
|
indeed seem strange that he might have obligations not of his own choosing
|
|
(ibid)1
|
|
|
|
2.3
|
|
Thus consent theory has strong ties with the methodology and ontology of
|
|
reductionism and individualism, which are essential to liberalism.2
|
|
Reductionism is a methodology that attempts to give explanations of the
|
|
properties of higher level entities, eg societies or cells, in terms of the
|
|
units, eg individuals or molecules, of which they are composed.
|
|
Reductionism is the thesis that parts are ontologically prior to the wholes
|
|
that they make up, the parts and their properties exist before (either
|
|
temporally or logically) the whole (Lewontin, et al, pp 5-6).3
|
|
Individualism is the manifestation of reductionism in the domain of
|
|
politics and political philosophy. The properties of societies and states
|
|
are to be explained by the properties of the individuals that make them up,
|
|
and these individuals are ontologically prior to states and societies.
|
|
|
|
Consent theory is obviously an example of this methodology; a property of a
|
|
complex whole, the state, is to be explained by properties, such as
|
|
consent, of the units which make up the whole, ie individuals.4
|
|
|
|
|
|
3.0 Features of Consent Theory
|
|
|
|
|
|
A consent theory of political obligation must have certain features if it
|
|
is to be a plausible and consistent consent theory.
|
|
|
|
3.1
|
|
Firstly the theory must rely on actual consent rather than hypothetical
|
|
consent. An appeal to hypothetical consent as the basis for political
|
|
obligation seems implausible. The intuitions that lead philosophers to
|
|
consent theory (eg that political obligation must be self-assumed) are
|
|
inconsistent with hypothetical consent. Hypothetical consent also requires
|
|
some extremely implausible metaphysics or psychology. Instead of placing
|
|
political obligation on an uncontroversial basis, hypothetical consent
|
|
derives it from a highly contentious one.
|
|
|
|
3.2
|
|
A consent theory must make dissent possible. If it comes out of a theory
|
|
that all the people under a state's de facto authority have consented to a
|
|
political obligation to that state, and there is no possible way of not
|
|
consenting, we should be mighty suspicious. It would seem that in these
|
|
cases we do not have consent, because consent is supposed to be the
|
|
voluntary assumption of obligation and it seems odd to describe an action
|
|
that it is impossible not to perform as being voluntary.
|
|
|
|
3.3
|
|
It should also be the case that political obligation is owed by an
|
|
individual to the state if and only if that individual has consented. That
|
|
is to say that it cannot be the case that individual X owes political
|
|
obligation to the state in virtue of an action performed by individual Y,
|
|
such as is the case in theories of original consent or majority consent. If
|
|
this is not the case then we have abandoned one of the main reasons for
|
|
choosing consent in the first place, ie that political obligation be
|
|
self-assumed.5
|
|
|
|
3.4
|
|
A consent theorist should not assume that any or some states are
|
|
legitimate, and build their theory upon this assumption. To do this is to
|
|
beg the question, because the point of the exercise is to see whether and
|
|
to what extent existing states are legitimate.
|
|
|
|
3.5
|
|
Beran's (1987) membership version of consent theory appears to meet these
|
|
conditions, and at the least comes closer to meeting them than any other
|
|
consent theory I have encountered. Therefore I will use it as my model for
|
|
purposes of discussion.
|
|
|
|
|
|
4.0 Problems for Consent Theory
|
|
|
|
Traditionally there have been a family of related arguments that consent
|
|
theories have had problems dealing with. They are all centrally concerned
|
|
with the question: When does the form of consent not give rise to
|
|
obligation? In Beran's language, what are the conditions that prevent
|
|
consent from coming off?
|
|
4.1
|
|
In the most obvious and uncontroversial example, it is obvious that an
|
|
action cannot count as consent if the consenter was threatened with
|
|
physical violence if they did not comply. Similarly if you consent because
|
|
I am likely (and able) to make life hell for you if you don't, then the
|
|
consent does not "come off".
|
|
|
|
4.2
|
|
According to Beran (1987, p 6) "An attempt to promise comes off only if the
|
|
attempted act is free, informed and competent." He then lists some
|
|
defeating conditions that if present prevent a promise from coming off. The
|
|
problematic examples come in here, firstly one might wonder whether these
|
|
are all of the necessary conditions and secondly it is less than clear as
|
|
to what counts as "free".
|
|
|
|
4.3
|
|
A problem for consent theory is the case of the happy slave. We assume that
|
|
a state that has the consent of its citizens is a legitimate political
|
|
authority, yet what if the citizenry includes a class of slaves, and these
|
|
slaves have apparently happily consented to be slaves? They have not been
|
|
coerced into this position nor have they been coerced into consenting.
|
|
Perhaps they have been brought up in the expectation of being slaves and
|
|
are content with their lot. Is the fact of their consent (freely, fully
|
|
informed and competently given) a sufficient condition for the legitimacy
|
|
of their state? Many liberals (not to mention others) would like to say
|
|
that it is not. How could consent theory deal with this problem?6
|
|
|
|
4.4
|
|
Beran (ibid) addresses criticism from Woozley, who argues that the high
|
|
cost of emigration, both economic and personal, coupled with the likelihood
|
|
that potential emigrants will have nowhere to go, makes people unfree to
|
|
dissent, therefore the citizens are not consenting freely (quoted in ibid
|
|
pp 95-108)
|
|
|
|
Woozley's argument seems to take this form:
|
|
1. Consent must be free.
|
|
2. For an action to be free, one must be free to do X and free to do not-X.
|
|
3. The high cost of emigration means that one is not free to dissent.
|
|
Therefore, 4. Membership does not count as consent.
|
|
|
|
Beran seems to be making two plausible replies to this argument, both
|
|
involve a rejection of premise 2. Under one interpretation he is stating
|
|
that for an action X to be free one merely needs to be free to do X, one
|
|
does not need to be free to do not-X. Under another interpretation Beran's
|
|
position is that freedom is not being prevented from satisfying one's
|
|
desires. Thus if one does not desire to do X then being prevented from
|
|
doing X does not make one unfree.7 Both of these replies are fraught with
|
|
problems.
|
|
|
|
The first interpretation runs the risk of violating the constraint 3.2, but
|
|
even if it does not there are other problems. The main point worth making
|
|
here is that one should avoid conflating "free to choose X" with "choosing
|
|
X freely". The first is compatible with a high degree of constraint, the
|
|
second is not. The statement that "A is free to X" considers only A's
|
|
relation to the action X, not to not-X or any other action. When talking
|
|
about consent, we are interested in A's relation to other courses of
|
|
action. The fact that consent is free in this sense is surely far less
|
|
important than the fact that the citizens are unfree in respect to other
|
|
actions. What becomes interesting then is the options which one is unfree
|
|
to choose, why one is unfree to choose them and the source(s) of that
|
|
unfreedom.
|
|
|
|
With the second interpretation of Beran we run into the problem Berlin
|
|
(1958) calls "the retreat to the inner citadel". If freedom is not having
|
|
one's desires frustrated, then the best, surest, option is to reduce one's
|
|
desires. This is surely bizarre. Similarly, there are the problems of
|
|
socialisation and/or brainwashing. We should say that someone who has been
|
|
conditioned, whose desires have been tampered with (say by Skinnerian or
|
|
Clockwork Orange style techniques), has had their freedom reduced, but we
|
|
cannot if we identify freedom with the lack of frustration of desires. If
|
|
we believe that such brain-washing interfere with freedom or consent, what
|
|
are we to say about socialisation pressures that might bring about the same
|
|
results?
|
|
|
|
|
|
5.0 Consent and Power
|
|
|
|
5.1
|
|
These problems are all getting at the same issue: How free does the act of
|
|
consent have to be to count as an instance of consent? All commentators
|
|
agree that if one is coerced into consenting by threat of sanctions, then
|
|
the consent does not come off. These cases roughly follow this schema:
|
|
|
|
1. A wants B to do X.
|
|
2. A threatens B with harm unless B does X.
|
|
3. B does X because of the threat.
|
|
|
|
(Beran, 1987, p 100)
|
|
|
|
5.2
|
|
There is an interesting parallel here with the notion of power:
|
|
|
|
A causes B to do something that B would otherwise not do.
|
|
|
|
(Lukes, 1974)
|
|
Therefore it is obvious that coercion is a case of the exercise of power
|
|
(not surprisingly). Most of Beran's other defeating conditions (Beran,
|
|
1987, p 6) involve the successful exercise of power by someone over the
|
|
consenter (eg "undue influence", "deception" (ibid)). We should note that
|
|
in the cases that are problematic for Beran and other consent theorists
|
|
(such as outlined in 4. above), it seems that what makes us unlikely to
|
|
think that consent has come off is the exercise of power over the
|
|
consenter. The question then becomes how prevalent is the exercise of power
|
|
in society?
|
|
|
|
5.3
|
|
Lukes (1974) offers some analytical tools that might help us answer this
|
|
question. His discussion of two-dimensional power and three-dimensional
|
|
power offer some insight as to how pervasive may be:
|
|
is it not the...most insidious exercise of power to prevent people, to
|
|
whatever degree, from having grievances by shaping their perceptions,
|
|
cognitions, and preferences in such a way that they accept their role in
|
|
the existing order of things...because they can see or imagine no
|
|
alternative to it...? (Lukes, 1974, p 24)
|
|
|
|
5.4
|
|
Herman and Chomsky (1988) give a concrete example of a structural
|
|
arrangement that has these effects. They argue that the structure of the
|
|
mass media in the USA results in a vast amount of political information
|
|
never reaching the public, and a large number of political options are
|
|
never presented to the public. Therefore the public are political actors
|
|
who are largely acting from a position of ignorance.
|
|
|
|
5.5
|
|
Here I think the reductionism of liberalism defeats us because of its
|
|
concentration upon the individual, and seeing consent as a property of the
|
|
individual. The structural elements of power within which individuals make
|
|
their decisions are invisible to individualism. Autonomy, freedom etc. are
|
|
(reified) properties of individual agents, in the individualistic
|
|
framework. However this ignores the power structures that constrain
|
|
decision making (and belief/desire and knowledge formation) by agents. If
|
|
the institutions of state and society are set up in such a way as to
|
|
preclude certain options from ever being aired or taught in the public
|
|
arena (as Herman and Chomsky (1988) have shown to be the case in the USA,
|
|
at least), then those options are unavailable to the populace and we can no
|
|
longer give an account of freedom or autonomy that looks to the individual
|
|
alone.
|
|
|
|
|
|
6.0 Consent, Reductionism and Dialectics
|
|
6.1
|
|
In opposition to liberalism's reductionistic account of society, I think a
|
|
dialectical account is inherently more plausible and gives a better
|
|
understanding of the problems associated with consent theory.
|
|
|
|
Reductionist explanation attempts to derive the properties of wholes from
|
|
intrinsic properties of parts, properties that exist apart from and before
|
|
the parts are assembled into complex structures...Dialectical explanations,
|
|
on the contrary, do not abstract properties of parts in isolation from
|
|
their associations in wholes but see the properties of parts as arising out
|
|
of their associations. That is, according to the dialectical view, the
|
|
properties of parts and wholes codetermine each other. (Lewontin, et al,
|
|
1984, p 11)
|
|
|
|
Therefore individuals and society codetermine each other in an ongoing
|
|
process. "The properties of individual human beings do not exist in
|
|
isolation but arise as a consequence of social life, yet the nature of that
|
|
social life is a consequence of our being human" (ibid).
|
|
|
|
6.2
|
|
Consent, as a behaviour, is an outcome of a dialectical process between
|
|
individual and society. The process involves the wants, desires and beliefs
|
|
of the individual, the power structures of society which restrict and shape
|
|
their formation, and the power structures which restrict available options.
|
|
|
|
6.3
|
|
The liberal picture assumes that one can make a disjunctive list of the
|
|
defeating conditions for promises, and that if none of the conditions on
|
|
the list are present then the action is free. However as a
|
|
three-dimensional account of power and/or a dialectic account shows, all
|
|
such actions (decisions, promises, consent) are made within a power
|
|
structure and are influenced by that structure.
|
|
|
|
6.4
|
|
Liberalism reifies consent, it is labelled as a unitary behaviour with a
|
|
unitary cause. What a dialectic account shows us is that it is ridiculous
|
|
to talk of a general cause of that behaviour, because the putative cause of
|
|
that behaviour will depend upon where you look and your purposes in doing
|
|
so. One's choosing X over Y is caused by the making of a decision, it could
|
|
also be caused by someone obscuring option Z. Which of these causes gets
|
|
called the cause of choosing X depends on one's viewpoint and one's purpose
|
|
in searching for causes.8 A dialectic account sees consent as the result in
|
|
an ongoing process.
|
|
|
|
The consent of the happy slave and the consent of the brain-washed, can be
|
|
seen as the result of a dialectic process where the power structures
|
|
constrain and influence the decisions of the individual to an extreme.
|
|
|
|
6.5
|
|
>From this discussion it can be seen that individualism is false or at least
|
|
severely misleading. A non-reductionistic, dialectical, account of society,
|
|
power and consent is a more powerful and much more revealing way of looking
|
|
at these issues. Therefore the individualist consent theory can be seen to
|
|
rest on a false presupposition.
|
|
|
|
|
|
7.0 Conclusion
|
|
|
|
The consent theorists project fails because they do not realise the extent
|
|
to which our decisions are influenced (or caused) by power structures, and
|
|
because their reductionistic picture of the nature of society and the
|
|
individual is false. If I am correct, then the entire liberal project of
|
|
finding a basis or justification for legitimate political authority is
|
|
untenable. The question then must be asked: Why do liberals attempt to
|
|
derive authority in this way?
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
NOTES
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
BIBLIOGRAPHY
|
|
|
|
|
|
Beran, H., 1987, The Consent Theory of Political Obligation, Croom Helm.
|
|
|
|
Berlin, I., 1958, Two Concepts of Liberty, Oxford University Press.
|
|
|
|
Cohen, G. A., 1979, "Capitalism, Freedom and the Proletariat" in Ryan, A.
|
|
(ed.), The Idea of Freedom, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
|
|
|
|
-----, 1988, History, Labour and Freedom, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
|
|
|
|
Crosthwaite, J., 1987, "Feminist Criticisms of Liberalism", in Political
|
|
Science, Vol 39(2).
|
|
|
|
Greenawalt, K., 1987, "Promissory Obligation: The Theme of Social
|
|
Contract", reprinted in Raz (1990).
|
|
|
|
Herman, E., and Chomsky, N., 1988, Manufacturing Consent, Pantheon Books,
|
|
New York.
|
|
|
|
Herzog, D., 1989, Happy Slaves, University of Chicago Press.
|
|
|
|
Hirschmann, N., 1989, "Freedom, Recognition, and Obligation: A Feminist
|
|
Approach to Political Theory", in American Political Science Review, Vol
|
|
83(4).
|
|
|
|
Horton, J., 1992, Political Obligation, Humanities Press International.
|
|
|
|
Lewontin, R., et al, 1984, Not In Our Genes, Pantheon, New York.
|
|
|
|
Lukes, S., 1973, Individualism, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
|
|
|
|
-----, 1974, Power: A Radical View, Macmillan Press.
|
|
|
|
Pitkin, H., 1972, "Obligation and Consent", in Laslett, P., et al, 1972,
|
|
Philosophy, Politics and Society, Fourth Series, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
|
|
|
|
Raz, J. (ed), 1990, Authority, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
|
|
|
|
Simmons, A. J., 1979, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, Princeton
|
|
University Press, Princeton.
|
|
|
|
Wolff, R. P., 1976, In Defense of Anarchism, Harper & Row.
|
|
1 Note also Greenawalt (1987, p 269): "social contract theory [including
|
|
consent theory] is a reflection of a liberal conception of human nature
|
|
that emphasizes freedom and autonomy."
|
|
2 A number of authors have argued this. See Crosthwaite (1987), Hirschmann
|
|
(1989), Lukes (1973). Many Marxists regard reductionism and individualism
|
|
as important components of bourgeois ideology, and they also regard
|
|
liberalism as a manifestation of bourgeois ideology in the political/social
|
|
domain. See, eg Lewontin, et al (1984), Cohen (1988).
|
|
3 Lewontin, et al, continue: "and there is a chain of causation that runs
|
|
from the units to the whole." (ibid p 6)
|
|
The discussion of reductionism is in the context of biology and psychology,
|
|
but (and this is part of their point) could apply equally well to any part
|
|
of bourgeois intellectual studies. With consent theory a "hypothetical"
|
|
chain of causation runs from the individuals to society and the state
|
|
(rather than a posited actual causation as in biological determinism)
|
|
making the reductionist label even more accurate.
|
|
4 Similar to the case of biological determinism, consent theory involves
|
|
the reification of certain behaviours of individuals, ie the behaviours are
|
|
treated as objects located in the biology of individuals. Also the
|
|
properties of the whole are also reified, such as authority. The fallacy in
|
|
reification is in the assumption that if there is a term for a property,
|
|
that property exists, or that what is measured exists.
|
|
5 See Simmons (1979:71). Note also Greenawalt (1987) "neither the unanimous
|
|
agreement of those originally subject to the legal order nor the agreement
|
|
of most of one's fellow citizens can obligate an individual who has not
|
|
agreed." (p 275)
|
|
6 The consent theorist could of course OutSmart the objection by claiming
|
|
that in this hypothetical case the happy slave has consented and the state
|
|
is legitimate. They might add that, however, this hypothetical case is
|
|
wildly implausible and thus is not a serious problem.
|
|
7 There is another response that Beran seems to make that relies upon a
|
|
conflation of unfree with coerced. I regard this as highly implausible.
|
|
8 Compare the account of tuberculosis as caused by a bacillus, with the
|
|
account of tuberculosis caused by the appalling conditions of rampant
|
|
capitalism. (Lewontin, et al, 1984)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|