1024 lines
58 KiB
Plaintext
1024 lines
58 KiB
Plaintext
Between Anarchism and Libertarianism: Defining a New Movement
|
|
by Jeff Draughn.
|
|
Transcriber's note (TN): italics are represented by a ! before the word.
|
|
|
|
Introduction
|
|
|
|
The following essay has been written to address an increasingly
|
|
common phenomenon which has emerged in recent years. With the
|
|
gradual rise of the new Libertarian Party in the public eye, there is a
|
|
curious tendency to equate the Libertarians to anarchists, or to
|
|
describe their agenda as being anarchistic in some fashion. As the
|
|
Libertarians' profile widens, it is likely that this comparison will also
|
|
increase, !but !should !it? Is this !really an appropriate comparison?
|
|
No. This essay will try to present documentation comparing the
|
|
"classical" anarchists, the founders of the movement who operated in
|
|
Nineteenth Century Europe, and their advocates today, with the
|
|
founder of the Libertarian philosophy. Upon careful examination,
|
|
their differences should seem obvious.
|
|
Prior to beginning this effort, a few points should be addressed.
|
|
First, during the course of this paper, numerous passages will be
|
|
included to illustrate the philosophies of various individuals, in their
|
|
own words. The final section, in particular, will include several
|
|
sizable passages from the works of Michael Bakunin, the father of
|
|
anarchist political philosophy. Due to his eloquent, flamboyant style,
|
|
his excerpts will be rather lengthy, but, where appropriate, they have
|
|
been reproduced with very minimal doctoring. In his case, it is the
|
|
author's opinion that much of Bakunin's rhetorical gifts would be lost
|
|
should these samples be "cut up" excessively. Fortunately, the
|
|
passages from the works of Ayn Rand are not terribly lengthy,
|
|
considering that she seemed to have a much greater gift for
|
|
succinctness then Bakunin.
|
|
Please note, as well, that most of the passages do not use gender
|
|
inclusive language. The tradition, in 1850 as well as 1970, was to use
|
|
the word "man" as a metaphor for all members of humanity. Rather
|
|
than including a (sic) at every transgression, the author asks that the
|
|
reader pardon the use of the metaphor where it appears.
|
|
It is also only fair to state from the beginning the bias of the
|
|
author. While the purpose of the essay is simply to illuminate the
|
|
differences between these two groups, the author is far and away more
|
|
sympathetic to the anarchists then to the Libertarians, and wherever
|
|
this may be apparent in the presentation, it is not meant to be
|
|
concealed. The chief objective, nonetheless, is expositional, not
|
|
polemical. The anarchists would not wish to be mistaken for
|
|
Libertarians, and the Libertarians would not wish to be mistaken for
|
|
anarchists. The goal is to help eliminate such mistakes.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
I. Mapping the Political Landscape
|
|
|
|
The political philosophy of anarchism is a peculiar beast,
|
|
historically misunderstood and often misrepresented, either
|
|
consciously or inadvertently. To best understand it, one must divine
|
|
some workable method of comparing it to other political philosophies,
|
|
but unfortunately the tradition system, the !linear !graph, seems
|
|
conspicuously inadequate. The linear graph, or the so-called
|
|
"political spectrum," allegedly displays the entirety of political
|
|
options along a single line, from left to right, stretching out from a
|
|
central point representing "moderate." From there it leads to
|
|
"liberalism" on the left, until it reaches to "radical liberalism" and
|
|
"communism," which is the extreme left "fringe." To the right it
|
|
leads to "conservatism," and finally to a reactionary conservatism"
|
|
and "fascism," which is the extreme right "fringe." (See Fig. 1).
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fig.1 - Traditional image of political spectrum [Transcriber's note:
|
|
linear representation]
|
|
|
|
Communism - Liberalism - Moderate - Conservative - Fascism
|
|
<<-------------------------------------------------------------->>
|
|
|
|
|
|
This image offers little in the way of understanding the
|
|
differences between the "left" and the "right." Indeed, if we compare
|
|
the Nazi government of 1930's Germany, which is widely considered
|
|
a good case study in fascism, and compare it with the Bolshevik
|
|
government of the Soviet Union, widely regarded as a good case
|
|
study in communism, the obvious totalitarian nature of both political
|
|
systems may lead us to believe that the two are virtually the same
|
|
system. And if fascism and communism are nearly identical, why are
|
|
they so "extremely" separate on the spectrum? Are they actually the
|
|
same ideology in practice, distinguishable only by the rhetoric
|
|
employed by the resident "Ministry of Truth?" That would suggest
|
|
that this linear graph is actually a circle, and that fascism and
|
|
communism are actually on roughly the same point on the spectrum.
|
|
(Fig.2 - common modification of traditional image.) [Transcriber's
|
|
Note: Author's Fig. 2 shows the endpoints of Fig. 1 closing into a
|
|
circle, making a circular representation, whereby Communism and
|
|
Fascism coincide.] Perhaps fascism and communism are just
|
|
buzzwords for a single system, totalitarianism. That would seem
|
|
consistent in that liberalism and conservatism are at opposite poles,
|
|
but is the polar opposite of totalitarianism something labeled
|
|
"moderate?" What is the shared ideology of moderates? If
|
|
totalitarianism endorses a society almost totally controlled by a strong
|
|
central government, shouldn't its opposite philosophy endorse a
|
|
society almost completely !absent of strong central government?
|
|
Surely moderates (in our society at least) do not endorse a society
|
|
without government, which is essentially an !anarchist position. Then
|
|
where does anarchism fit on this spectrum? And where does
|
|
"libertarianism," as endorsed by the newly formed (U.S.) Libertarian
|
|
Party, fit on this spectrum?
|
|
To answer these questions we must, in short, reject the tradition
|
|
linear" image, and even the "circular" image of the political spectrum,
|
|
and examine a new image. For the purposes of this essay, a two-
|
|
dimensional alternative, borrowed from the good people of !Utne
|
|
!Reader, will be used. (endnote l) This alternative spectrum takes as
|
|
its objective "foundation," its standard, its "yardstick" with which to
|
|
gauge various ideologies, two primary questions: the question of
|
|
property ownership, and the question of State control. The graph is
|
|
composed of two axes, one (left- right) representing the variations of
|
|
systems of property ownership, the other (top-bottom) representing
|
|
the variations of State control over society. (See Fig. 3 - the
|
|
Property/State" Axis)
|
|
|
|
|
|
Decentralism
|
|
S ("Small" or "No Government")
|
|
t
|
|
a Collectivism Privitism
|
|
t (Community Ownership) (Individual Ownership)
|
|
e
|
|
Centralism
|
|
("Big Government")
|
|
|
|
P r o p e r t y--->
|
|
|
|
|
|
The "property" axis varies from total collectivization of property
|
|
(community control of land and the "means of production") to total
|
|
privatization of property (individual ownership of land and the
|
|
"means of production"). The "State" axis varies from total control or
|
|
eminence of State government (totalitarianism, or !centrism ) to total
|
|
absence or extremely minimal State government (decentralism ). Once
|
|
these two linear spectrums are combined into a two- dimensional
|
|
graph, the task of differentiating various political ideologies (at least
|
|
the so-called "extreme" ones) becomes much easier.
|
|
It also allows us to assign specific meanings to specific terms,
|
|
terms whose traditional definitions have been all but buried in decades
|
|
after decades of contradictory usage. It can't be denied that many
|
|
political terms ("liberal" and "conservative," for example) simply do
|
|
not have the same strict denotations today that they may have had a
|
|
century or two ago. Their meanings have changed, evolved, and, in
|
|
the content of historical analysis, it becomes necessary to clarify their
|
|
specific meanings if we insist upon using them. Fortunately,
|
|
clarifying the terms "liberalism" and "conservatism" is unnecessary to
|
|
this particular essay, but others are indeed necessary. For the course
|
|
of this paper, we will assign certain descriptors to designate poles of
|
|
the "landscape" graph. For instance, the term "socialistic" will be
|
|
used to describe individuals or doctrines advocating collectivism, or
|
|
the abolition of private property. (See Fig. 4 - Descriptive Labels)
|
|
|
|
"Libertarian"
|
|
S ("Small" or "No Government")
|
|
t
|
|
a "Socialistic" "Capitalistic"
|
|
t (Community Ownership) (Individual Ownership)
|
|
e
|
|
"Authoritarian"
|
|
("Big Government")
|
|
|
|
P r o p e r t y--->
|
|
|
|
|
|
"Capitalistic" will be used to describe those who defend the right to
|
|
private property. "Authoritarian" will describe those who advocate a
|
|
strong State, a powerful central government. And "libertarian" will
|
|
describe advocates of minimal or nonexistent government power.
|
|
Certainly these denotations are not necessarily consistent with all their
|
|
historical uses, but such consistency is an impossibility, and these
|
|
definitions are not totally divorced from contemporary usage, as shall
|
|
be seen.
|
|
With our terms now defined, certain ideologies may be pin-
|
|
pointed on the graph. In particular, the ideologies of Communism,
|
|
Fascism, Libertarianism, and Anarchism can be designated. These
|
|
four political philosophies are particularly important (on this graph at
|
|
least) because they represent the "corners." By asking how these
|
|
ideologies stand on the issues of property and centralism, we can
|
|
place them on the graph. (See Fig. 5 - The graphic locations of the
|
|
four ideologies)
|
|
|
|
ANARCHISM "Libertarian" LIBERTARIANISM
|
|
S ("Small" or "No Government")
|
|
t
|
|
a "Socialistic" "Capitalistic"
|
|
t (Community Ownership) (Individual Ownership)
|
|
e
|
|
"Authoritarian"
|
|
COMMUNISM ("Big Government") FASCISM
|
|
|
|
P r o p e r t y--->
|
|
|
|
For example, Communism, as described by Karl Marx, endorses the
|
|
usurpation of all property and factories by a strong State, or
|
|
"collectivism plus centralism." It covers the bottom left corner.
|
|
Fascism, as practiced by Hitler (in spite of the "socialism" in the
|
|
NAZI acronym), Mussolini, and most modern "banana republics,"
|
|
has a flourishing privately owned industrial complex operating in
|
|
collusion with a strong autocratic military regime. Although these
|
|
industries are often subordinate to the will of the State, typically
|
|
making weapons and such to keep the mother armies supplied, these
|
|
corporations are well paid for the goods they produce, and the
|
|
industries themselves are owned by individuals, not the government.
|
|
(endnote 2) In other words, fascism is "capitalism plus centralism."
|
|
Anarchism endorses a collective, community ownership of property
|
|
and the means of production, and its advocates have often called
|
|
themselves "libertarian communists" or "stateless socialists," usually
|
|
to try to differentiate themselves from the Marxists. Clearly,
|
|
"collectivism plus decentralism."
|
|
Finally, this essay will try to clarify that the newly formed
|
|
Libertarian Party endorses a position of "privatism plus
|
|
decentralism," the forth and last corner of the graph. Not very much
|
|
is known about this renegade "third party," but enough is known
|
|
about them and one of their ideological role models, Ayn Rand, to
|
|
discern that they believe in the absolute sanctity of private property,
|
|
the moral soundness of capitalism, and the minimalization of the
|
|
State.
|
|
Today, there is a tendency to associate the Libertarians with
|
|
anarchism. This is not terribly surprising. The anarchists of the
|
|
Nineteenth Century were using the term "libertarian" to describe
|
|
themselves for a long time, and modern anarchists, such as Murray
|
|
Bookchin, continue to use the term. (endnote 3) And, in a political
|
|
sense, the two seem complimentary. For instance, they both are
|
|
staunch advocates of civil rights. For the most part, both groups
|
|
oppose government censorship of rap music, pornographic magazines
|
|
and Ray Bradbury novels. They both oppose prohibition of the use or
|
|
sale of marijuana. They both oppose government regulations of
|
|
firearms. Neither believes the State should have the authority to
|
|
decide which god should be prayed to in schools, or which sexual
|
|
positions are and are not morally permissible. However, under
|
|
scrutiny, the distinction between anarchists and Libertarians in
|
|
regards to the property question is substantial, and in this light these
|
|
two groups are clearly incompatible. To mistake them for one other is
|
|
obfuscatory, and does neither of them any service.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
II. Toward a Definition of Anarchism
|
|
|
|
To begin this comparison, we are required to come to some
|
|
consensus as to the actual meaning of the term "anarchism," if for no
|
|
other reason to determine if its placement on the above "landscape"
|
|
graph is indeed accurate. A good starting point is the new
|
|
HarperCollins Dictionary of Philosophy which, interestingly enough,
|
|
has two definitions, a "positive connotation" and a "negative
|
|
connotation:"
|
|
|
|
"Anarchism is the social ideology that refuses to accept an
|
|
authoritarian ruling government It holds that individuals should
|
|
organize themselves in any way they wish in order to fulfill their
|
|
needs and ideals In this sense anarchism is not to be identified with
|
|
nihilism but can be seen to have similarities with political
|
|
libertarianism . . .
|
|
"Anarchism is the belief that denies any respect for law and
|
|
order and actively engages in the promotion of chaos through the
|
|
destruction of society. It advocates the use of individual terrorism as a
|
|
means toward advancing the cause of social and political
|
|
disorganization."
|
|
|
|
This is a fairly balanced description, although the "positive"
|
|
definition-is thin at best. Please note that anarchism is compared to
|
|
"political libertarianism." It is unfortunate that this dictionary did not
|
|
include a political definition for "libertarianism." The "negative"
|
|
definition of anarchism essentially captures the mythical paranoid
|
|
connotation that has been used for over a hundred years. If one bears
|
|
the word used today, this will almost certainly be its intended
|
|
meaning.
|
|
We can learn almost as much about the word's meaning by
|
|
looking at its origins: "from Greek, prefix !a, not, the want of, the
|
|
absence of, the lack of, + !archos, a ruler, director, chief, person in
|
|
charge, commander. The Greek words !anarchos, !anarchia meant
|
|
having no government--being without a government." (endnote 4).
|
|
The strict, original meaning of anarchism was not "no government"
|
|
!per !se. Rather, it was "no leader, no ruler." The denotation
|
|
suggests a condition of non-hierarchy, and this condition of "no one
|
|
in charge" was considered synonymous with "lack of government."
|
|
This is significant, in that many anarchists, past and present, have
|
|
insisted that anarchism is primarily a movement against hierarchy
|
|
rather than anti-government. Throughout the Nineteenth Century, as
|
|
anarchist philosophy was being carved by such notables as Mikhail
|
|
Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin, the focus of their philosophy tended to
|
|
have three primary targets: 1) the State, 2) the bourgeois, and 3) the
|
|
Church. Among them there was a solid consensus that these three
|
|
collective institutions should be abolished in whole, and these were
|
|
the topics of most of their writings. However, the overarching theory
|
|
was to forge a society of "liberty, fraternity, equality" for all men and
|
|
women. Although the term was probably never used, theirs was a
|
|
philosophy against hierarchy against any inequality of power or
|
|
privileges between individuals. Bakunin spoke of this when he said,
|
|
"Do you want to make it impossible for anyone to oppress his fellow-
|
|
man? Then make sure that no one shall possess power." (endnote 5).
|
|
While it has always been a latent part of the "revolutionary project,"
|
|
only recently has this broader concept of anti-hierarchy arisen for
|
|
more specific scrutiny. Nonetheless, the root of this is plainly visible
|
|
in the Greek roots of the word "anarchy."
|
|
Every anarchist who wrote about the theory had to offer their
|
|
definition, as it was so poorly understood. One of the clearest was
|
|
offered by Kropotkin in his pamphlet !Anarchist !Communism, !Its
|
|
!Basis !and !Principles, in which he defines anarchism as "the no-
|
|
government system of socialism....
|
|
|
|
"In common with all socialists, the anarchists hold that the
|
|
private ownership of land, capital, and machinery has had its time;
|
|
that it is condemned to disappear: and that all requisites for
|
|
production must, and will, become the common property of society,
|
|
and be managed in common by the producers of wealth. And...they
|
|
maintain that the ideal of the political organization of society is a
|
|
condition of things where the functions of government are reduced to
|
|
minimum....(and) that the ultimate aim of society is the reduction of
|
|
the functions of government to nil--that is, to a society without
|
|
government, to an-archy." (endnote 6)
|
|
|
|
What is interesting about this exposition is that Kropotkin first
|
|
explains the socialist, collectivist tenets of anarchism, and then
|
|
explains the political tenets. In spite of the obvious image of
|
|
anarchism being !primarily an anti-government philosophy, Kropotkin
|
|
elaborates on the anti-State facets only after establishing the
|
|
relationship of anarchism to socialism.
|
|
This is echoed throughout the literature. Bakunin repeated refers
|
|
to himself as a socialist, but did renounce "Communism:" "I am not a
|
|
Communist because Communism unites all the forces of society in the
|
|
state and becomes absorbed in it; because it inevitably leads to
|
|
concentration of all property in the hands of the state, while I seek the
|
|
abolition of the state." (endnote 7) Bakunin had obviously seen fit to
|
|
let the Marxists have the word "communist," as long as he had the
|
|
word "anarchist." At this point, Bakunin saw "communism" as
|
|
synonymous with "state socialism" and "anarchism" as synonymous
|
|
with "stateless socialism." These are the terms accepted in this essay.
|
|
Yet, less than fifty years later, Kropotkin was attempting to "take
|
|
back" the term "communist" as his own.
|
|
A Twentieth Century anarchist, Rudolf Rocker, accepted the
|
|
socialist definition of the philosophy. In defining anarchism he writes,
|
|
"Common to all Anarchists is the desire to free society of all political
|
|
and social coercive institutions which stand in the way of the
|
|
development of a free humanity." Rocker sees this realization only in
|
|
actualizing the Liberalist and Socialist traditions of the French
|
|
Revolution. Convinced that the gallant but "pre-eminently political"
|
|
concepts of Liberalism and Democracy were "shipwrecked on the
|
|
realities of the capitalist economic form," Rocker asserts . . .
|
|
|
|
"In common with founders of Socialism, Anarchist demand the
|
|
abolition of all economic monopolies and the common ownership of
|
|
the soil and all other means of production, the use of which must be
|
|
available to all without distinction. . . .(T)he Anarchists represent the
|
|
viewpoint that the war against capitalism must be at the same time a
|
|
war against all institutions of political power, for in history economic
|
|
exploitation has always gone hand in hand with political ant social
|
|
oppression. The exploitation of man by man and the domination of
|
|
man over man are inseparable, and each is the condition of the other."
|
|
(endnote 8)
|
|
|
|
A more contemporary scholar, Noam Chomsky, head of the
|
|
Linguistics Department at MIT, has described himself as a "derivative
|
|
fellow traveler" of anarchist thought, and has endorsed the socialist
|
|
definition, stating, "I would prefer to think of it as the libertarian left,
|
|
and. . . can be conceived as a kind of voluntary socialism. . . in the
|
|
tradition of Bakunin and Kropotkin and others." (endnote 9) Note
|
|
that Chomsky uses the "libertarian" label to differentiate the
|
|
anarchists from "non- libertarian" Marxists, who advocate an
|
|
"involuntary socialism."
|
|
While even Chomsky is quick to admit that anarchist thought
|
|
covers "quite a range of ideas," it is apparent that a strong socialist
|
|
motif runs through much of the anarchist literature, including the
|
|
literature of most of its lauded pioneers. With this established, a
|
|
glance at the Libertarian Party agenda is required for us to make a
|
|
genuine comparison.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
III. Modern Libertarianism and Ayn Rand
|
|
|
|
Information on the Libertarian Party is, unfortunately, rather
|
|
scarce. While allegedly the "third-largest and fastest-growing"
|
|
political party in the United States, their material is still not readily
|
|
accessible in the Tallahassee, FL area, and their toll-free telephone
|
|
number was constantly busy prior to the 1992 Presidential elections.
|
|
However, a short, one-page pamphlet entitled "Understanding the
|
|
Libertarian Philosophy" was fortunately available. (A copy is
|
|
enclosed with this essay) [TN: another day]. This pamphlet, written
|
|
by Joseph E. Knight, Libertarian Party Field Organizer, is a succinct
|
|
attempt at clarifying the core ideology, if not the specific
|
|
programmatic platform, of the Party. Of course, not much can be said
|
|
in one page, no matter how small the type. However, there are certain
|
|
tell-tale "fingerprints" in Mr. Knight's brief account, which may tie it
|
|
to a larger and more accessible body of work, with which we may fill
|
|
in some conceptual gaps.
|
|
It has been rumored, though no written proof is available to the
|
|
author of this essay, that the Libertarian Party is heavily influenced by
|
|
the Objectivist movement, of which Ayn Rand has emerged as the
|
|
chief spokesperson. Ayn Rand died in 1982, but she left behind a
|
|
substantial body of literature, both fictional and expositional, most of
|
|
which can be sampled at any local bookstore or library. If the
|
|
Libertarians really are influenced by Rand's work, then an
|
|
understanding of Rand's objectivism would serve well to clarify the
|
|
Libertarian "world view." But is there a connection?
|
|
The theme of Knight's pamphlet is primarily the "proper role of
|
|
government in a free society." An explication of the pamphlet is
|
|
unnecessary, as the pamphlet is included with this essay and should be
|
|
examined by the reader [TN: Write: The Libertarian Party, 1528
|
|
Pennsylvania Ave., Washington, D.C., 20003, or call (202) 543-1988
|
|
or (800) 682-1776]. What follows is a comparison of certain
|
|
particularly important passages of the pamphlet and certain pertinent
|
|
statements from the writings of Ayn Rand:
|
|
|
|
"Government is the use of force. To govern means to control.
|
|
The use of force is implicit in the definition of control.... [Therefore,]
|
|
the question becomes, "What is the proper use of force in a free
|
|
society?"
|
|
"[A] government holds a legal monopoly on the we of physical
|
|
force... The nature of governmental action is: coercive action."
|
|
(endnote 10)
|
|
|
|
Note the similarity of these two definitions. The latter was taken
|
|
from a transcript of a lecture given by Rand in 1961, and later
|
|
published as an essay entitled "America's Persecuted Minority: Big
|
|
Business." Consider another example:
|
|
|
|
"Libertarians are, by definition, those who oppose the initiation
|
|
of force. . . . Opposition to the INITIATION of force (the NON-
|
|
COERCION PRINCIPLE) is the essence of libertarian philosophy."
|
|
"The basic Principle of the Objectivist ethics is: no man may
|
|
INITIATE "he use of physical force against others." (endnote 11)
|
|
|
|
Again, please note the striking similarity of language. Samples
|
|
are bountiful:
|
|
|
|
" freedom is the absense of the initiation of force. "
|
|
"Freedom. . . has only one meaning: the absence of physical
|
|
coercion." (endnote 12)
|
|
|
|
"The proper role of government (force) in a free society then, is
|
|
to defend and/or retaliate against those who initiate force."
|
|
"The only proper purpose of government is to protect man 's
|
|
rights, which means: to protect him from physical violence. A proper
|
|
government is only a policeman, acting as an agent of man's self-
|
|
defense, and, as such, may resort to force only against those who start
|
|
the use of force. " (endnote 13)
|
|
|
|
"In a free society, you have property rights.... In a free society,
|
|
you have personal rights.... Property rights and personal rights are
|
|
really the same. Personal rights are based on property rights because
|
|
you own your life, your body, and your mind."
|
|
"The right to life is the source of all rights--and the right to
|
|
property is their only implementation. without property rights, no
|
|
other rights are possible." (endnote 14)
|
|
|
|
All the uncited passages above are taken from Mr. Knight's
|
|
pamphlet. All of the cited passages are taken from various essays
|
|
authored by Ayn Rand. When compared, these paired excerpts read
|
|
like paraphrases of each other. Note the similar language, the
|
|
repetition of key phrases ("initiation of force," "coercion"), and
|
|
particularly the shared emphasis on !property !rights. This list could
|
|
continue, but the point is made. Almost all of the concepts expressed
|
|
in this pamphlet were originally expressed, albeit in fragments, by
|
|
Ayn Rand, the founder of Objectivism, between twenty to thirty years
|
|
ago. It therefore seems reasonable to suggest that, if the "Libertarian
|
|
Philosophy" as defined by the Party Field Organizer, is borrowed
|
|
almost verbatim from the writings of Ayn Rand, then the Libertarian
|
|
Party probably shares other ideas with Rand on topics not elaborated
|
|
on in this specific pamphlet. Thus, by comparing Rand's ideas to the
|
|
ideas of the Nineteenth and Twentieth Century anarchists, we may be
|
|
able to derive a semi-accurate assessment of the differences between
|
|
the modern Libertarians and the anarchists.
|
|
Please note. The comparison of Knight to Rand was not an
|
|
effort to criticize the Libertarians by suggesting their ideas aren't
|
|
"original," or that they're "expropriating" Rand's concepts
|
|
improperly, or even that they may be concealing the relationship of
|
|
their platform to Objectivism. On the contrary, it is unknown to the
|
|
author, due to factors previously mentioned, whether the Libertarians
|
|
conceal or proudly acknowledge this relationship. The sole purpose of
|
|
the comparison was to establish the mere existence of this
|
|
relationship, as no other sources were available.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
IV. Between Ayn Rand and Anarchism
|
|
|
|
In placing the Objectivist/Libertarians on the "landscape" graph,
|
|
we must find their answer to the two premier questions: What about
|
|
property, and what about the State? The answer, for the most part,
|
|
has already been given. In economic terms, Rand has never been
|
|
subtle in her beliefs; they are obvious at a glance. Among her
|
|
publications are such titles as !Capitalism: !The !Unknown !Ideal, and
|
|
!The !Virtue !of !Selfishness. Many of these texts are compilations of
|
|
essays whose titles include: "Notes on the History of American Free
|
|
Enterprise," "The New Fascism: Rule by Consensus," and the above
|
|
mentioned "America's Persecuted Minority: Big Business." (endnote
|
|
15) She has described herself as a "!radical !for !capitalism," and
|
|
describes her Objectivist movement as trying to supply "that
|
|
philosophical base which capitalism did not have and without which it
|
|
was doomed to perish. . ." (endnote 16) Rand has elaborated at
|
|
length on capitalist theory:
|
|
|
|
"[TN:italics until word 'owned'] Capitalism is a social system
|
|
based on the recognition of individual rights, including property
|
|
rights, in which all property is privately owned...The !moral
|
|
justification of capitalism lies in the fact that it is the only system
|
|
consonant with man's rational nature, that it protects man's survival
|
|
!qua man, and that its ruling principle is justice.'' (endnote 17)
|
|
While the Libertarian pamphlet never mentions the word
|
|
"capitalism" per se, their avowed "commitment to free enterprise" and
|
|
the equation of personal rights with property rights is perfectly in
|
|
sync with Rand's theories, and strongly connote an advocacy of
|
|
capitalism.
|
|
With the "property question" clearly answered, what about the
|
|
State? "When I say 'capitalism,' I mean a full, pure, uncontrolled,
|
|
unregulated laissez-faire capitalism--with a separation of state and
|
|
economics. " (endnote 18) The single legitimate role of tbe State,
|
|
then, is to protect citizens from the "initiators of force," either by
|
|
"defensive" or "retaliatory force." Both Rand and Knight
|
|
acknowledge a "proper role" of the State, but give it only one
|
|
function: Coercive force, controlled by an "objective" code of law,
|
|
defending citizens and property from any transgressors.Thus, on these
|
|
terms, Objectivism/Libertarianism would appear to fit the definition
|
|
of "privatism plus decentralism," or "libertarian capitalism," as
|
|
delineated by the top-right corner of the "landscape" graph.
|
|
On this basis, the differences between anarchism and
|
|
Objectivism seem rather obvious: While both groups endorse a society
|
|
with minimal State power (although both Rand and Knight admit the
|
|
State has a "proper role," albeit limited, in contrast to the anarchist's
|
|
desire for !complete elimination of the State), in an economic sense
|
|
they are diametrical opposites. Rand sees capitalism as being theonly
|
|
!just system for society, while the anarchists (or, at least, the anarcho-
|
|
communists) see capitalism as enslavement. The anarchists endorse a
|
|
system of socialism sans State, while Rand sees "socialism" as being
|
|
institutionalized theft and tyranny.
|
|
These skewed visions can be partially attributed to a confusion
|
|
over definitions, that age-old problem which we are even now
|
|
struggling to remedy. For instance, Rand doesn't use the same general
|
|
definition of socialism as theNineteenth Century anarchists like
|
|
Bakunin or Kropotkin. Indeed, she takes theBolshevik and Nazi
|
|
"socialist" systems at face value, fully accepting their terms,defined
|
|
by the realities of their policies. The result is her equation of
|
|
"socialism, "communism," and "fascism" as all being identical in
|
|
essence, all three of which she encompasses under a single new term,
|
|
"statism." "Government control of a country's economy. . . rests on
|
|
the basic principle of !statism, the principle that man's life belongs to
|
|
the state." (endnote 19) Rand's term, "statism," is synonymous with
|
|
the general descriptor, "authoritarian" or "centralist," which we use
|
|
with the "landscape" graph. Rand, however, describes socialism in a
|
|
!strictly authoritarian sense. "A statist system--whether of a
|
|
communist, fascist, Nazi, socialist or 'welfare' type--is based on the .
|
|
. . government's unlimited power, which means: on the rule of brute
|
|
force." (endnote 20) She did admit that fascism differed from
|
|
socialism in that, under a fascist system, "citizens retain the
|
|
responsibilities of owning property," while under socialism they do
|
|
not. However, she thought this difference was insignificant because,
|
|
in spite of private ownership, "the government holds total power over
|
|
its use and disposal." (endnote 21) However, she apparently had no
|
|
concept of a non-statist socialism.
|
|
Which is not to say she was an anarchist, or that she was totally
|
|
ignorant of anarchism. She once wrote that, "Anarchy, as a political
|
|
concept, is a naive floating abstraction: . . . a society without an
|
|
organized government would be at the mercy of the first criminal who
|
|
came along and who would precipitate it into the chaos of gang
|
|
warfare." (endnote 22) Still, while she addresses "anarchy," she does
|
|
not repudiate it as a system of stateless socialism, only as a state of
|
|
lawlessness and "gang warfare," a society of land-owning individuals
|
|
without the "policeman" that is government, a scene reminiscent of
|
|
present-day Somalia [TN:this essay pre-dates the U.S. Invasion of
|
|
Somalia]. She never indulges in a systematic critique of anarchist
|
|
thought. This isn't too surprising, since anarchism, by its nature, has
|
|
been an historically repressed movement. While the ideology of "State
|
|
socialism" received pronounced attention and credibility in some
|
|
scholarly circles after the Bolshevik Revolution put a large geographic
|
|
fraction of the globe under its doctrine, anarchism has never had such
|
|
a massive successful project to put it in the intellectual "limelight."
|
|
Therefore, as its proponents are buried in the "dustbin of history," its
|
|
primary tenets are increasingly forgotten and/or misunderstood. It is
|
|
therefore, expected that Rand would see socialism strictly in the terms
|
|
of Marx, Lenin, and Stalin, who "won," at least temporarily.
|
|
Consider, too, that Rand was born to a wealthy family in St.
|
|
Petersburg in 1905, and she was forced to flee to the Crimea with her
|
|
family at the age of twelve. It is not unreasonable to suspect that she
|
|
had an axe to grind with the Russian Communists, who "stole" her
|
|
family's land and possessions. Nonetheless, she denounced absolute
|
|
statelessness, and she denounced, invariably, any restriction to
|
|
individual ownership of land. It would be foolish to hypothesize that
|
|
the combination of these two tenets would have had any appeal to her.
|
|
It likely would have been double anathema.
|
|
It is interesting that she also condemned "libertarians," or at
|
|
least some group to whom she attributed that label. In 1971, she
|
|
wrote
|
|
|
|
"For the record, I shall repeat what I have said many times
|
|
before: I do not join or endorse any political group or movement.
|
|
More specifically, I disapprove of, disagree with and have no
|
|
connection with, the latest aberration of some conservatives, the so-
|
|
called "hippies of the right," who attempt to snare the younger of my
|
|
readers by claiming simultaneously to be followers of my philosophy
|
|
ant advocates of anarchism. Anyone offering such a combination
|
|
confesses his inability to understand either." (endnote 23)
|
|
|
|
One of her colleagues, Harry Binswanger, elaborated on this in
|
|
1981,
|
|
|
|
"[T]he 'libertarians' are tying capitalism to the whim-
|
|
worshipping subjectivism and chaos of anarchy. To cooperate with
|
|
[this] group is to betray capitalism, reason, and one's own future."
|
|
(endnote 23)
|
|
|
|
Are the "libertarians" of 1971 and 1981, whom Rand and
|
|
Binswanger so viscerally condemn, the same Libertarians who
|
|
produced the pamphlet explaining the "libertarian philosophy,"
|
|
utilizing so many of Rand's ideas? Was Andre Marrou a "hippy of the
|
|
right," advocating a mix of capitalism and anarchy? What would Ayn
|
|
Rand think of the '92 Libertarian Party?
|
|
Knight's pamphlet explicitly mimics Rand's repeated assertions
|
|
of the need of some government, so the Libertarians don't sound like
|
|
"anarchists" of any brand. The line seems pretty clearly drawn. Still,
|
|
regardless of what Rand would think of a political party trying to get
|
|
into office to help implement some of her ideals, the fact remains that
|
|
the Libertarians are obviously influenced by her work, and so she is a
|
|
convenient lens with which to examine them.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
V. Society, Individualism, and Inheritance
|
|
|
|
To better understand the differences between the anarchists and
|
|
the Objectivists/Libertarians, it is necessary to dig deeper than simply
|
|
their "soundbites" on the proper role of the State and their bandying
|
|
of the terms "socialism" and "capitalism." While our "landscape"
|
|
graph can accurately contrast different ideologies on the basis of these
|
|
two important issues, it cannot help us understand the !philosophical
|
|
foundation of these political and economic positions. That is a much
|
|
more complicated process, and an adequate appraisal of the
|
|
philosophies of anarchism and Objectivism cannot be made in merely
|
|
a few typed pages. But it may be possible to highlight certain
|
|
particulars that most clearly contrast each other, thereby granting us a
|
|
glimpse of the root differences between these two schools of thought.
|
|
The most glaring example of this is the concepts of
|
|
individualism and society. Individualism is the keystone of Objectivist
|
|
philosophy, and it pervades all other conclusions. "[E]very man . . .
|
|
must exist for his own sake, neither sacrificing himself to others nor
|
|
sacrificing others to himself. The pursuit of his own rational self-
|
|
interest and of his own happiness is the highest moral purpose of his
|
|
life." (endnote 25) Rand's image of humanity is rooted in the
|
|
"classical liberal" view, in the tradition of John Locke, which sees all
|
|
people as absolute individual entities, whose only effect on one
|
|
another is comparable to "billiard balls" randomly colliding and
|
|
altering the otherwise linear course of their independent lives.
|
|
Attempting to coexist among each other, people are forced, by
|
|
overcrowding or whatever, to enter into a Rousseau-esque "social
|
|
contract," a State, which guarantees security to all its citizens at the
|
|
price of a "little" sacrificed freedom. The goal of individuals now is
|
|
to reap the fruits of their labor, with their rightfully purchased land,
|
|
and try to keep the State's tax of liberty" to an unobtrusive minimum.
|
|
To Ayn Rand, there are no rights but individual rights, and "a group .
|
|
. . has no rights other than the individual rights of its members."
|
|
(endnote 26)
|
|
Bakunin addressed these issues a century earlier, dismissing
|
|
Rousseau's "social contract" as a "terrible nonsense," "a pernicious
|
|
fiction." He defined humanity more broadly. "Man is not only the
|
|
most individual being on earth, but also the most social." (endnote
|
|
27) Neither of these qualities can be ignored or dismissed. Bakunin
|
|
described every human being as being the product of an environment,
|
|
both natural and social, and as such, unable to escape the social
|
|
element of their existence. "Man does not choose society; on the
|
|
contrary, he is the product of the latter." (endnote 28) Through
|
|
education, the values of a society or community are transferred to the
|
|
next generation, thus all original ideas and concepts are produced on
|
|
the foundation of what society has transmitted to its members.
|
|
Here we see the starkest contrast between Objectivism and
|
|
anarchism. Rand denies the value of society:
|
|
|
|
"Mankind is not an entity, an organism, or a coral bush. The
|
|
entity involved in production and trade is !man. It is with the study of
|
|
man--not of the loose aggregate known as 'community'--that any
|
|
science of the humanities has to begin....
|
|
"A great deal may be learned about society by studying man: but
|
|
this process cannot be reversed: nothing can be learned about man by
|
|
studying society- -by studying the inter-relationships of entities one
|
|
has never identified or defined." (endnote 27)
|
|
|
|
[TN: endnotes 28-29 missing, suggesting author's deletion of some
|
|
material]
|
|
|
|
Rand's repudiation of the importance of society is echoed
|
|
repeatedly:
|
|
|
|
"Man gains enormous values from dealing with other men;
|
|
living in a human society is his proper way of life--but only on certain
|
|
conditions. Man is not a lone wolf and he is not a social animal. He is
|
|
a contractual animal." (endnote 30)
|
|
|
|
In Rand's paradigm, "society" is merely a bundle of individuals
|
|
who interact with one another when convenience requires it.
|
|
Cooperation takes place on the basis of strict mutual self-interest, and
|
|
typically on a "contractual" basis, such as employment. "Culture" is
|
|
merely the sum total of ideas among a mass of individuals whose
|
|
general acceptance is dominant over other "dissident" ideas. These
|
|
definitions are dry and stoic only because the truly important !unit of
|
|
human society is the isolate human being, whose "creative faculty
|
|
cannot be given or received, shared or borrowed." (endnote 31)
|
|
Bakunin offers an elaborate renunciation of this image:
|
|
|
|
"[E]verything that lives, does so under the categorical condition
|
|
of decisively interfering in the life of someone else....
|
|
The worse it is for those who are so ignorant of the natural and
|
|
social law of human solidarity that they deem possible or even
|
|
desirable the absolute independence of individuals in regard to one
|
|
another. To will it is to will the disappearance of society.... All men,
|
|
even the most intelligent and strongest are at every instant of their
|
|
lives the producers and the product. Freedom itself, the freedom of
|
|
every man, is the ever-renewed effect of the great mass of physical.
|
|
intellectual, and moral influonces to which this man is subjected by
|
|
the people surrounding him and the environment in which he was
|
|
born and in which he passed his whole life.
|
|
To wish to escape this influence in the name of some . . . self-
|
|
sufficient and absolutely egoistical freedom. is to aim toward non-
|
|
being.
|
|
To do away with this reciprocal influence is tantamount to
|
|
death. And in demanding the freedom of the masses we do not intend
|
|
to do away with natural influences to which man is subjected by
|
|
individuals and groups. All we want is to do away with is factitious.
|
|
legitimized influences. to do away with the !priviledges in exerting
|
|
influence." (endnote 32)
|
|
|
|
What does Bakunin mean by "privileges of influence?" He
|
|
means, in general, !hierarchies !of !power, and in specific, the
|
|
political leaders who control the State, the ministers who control the
|
|
Church, and of course, the capitalists who own and thereby control all
|
|
capital, land, and the means of production. The premier issue that
|
|
Bakunin addresses in his work, which Rand explicitly denies in hers,
|
|
is that of !economic !exploitation. Rand does not believe exploitation
|
|
is possible in "free trade" capitalism, so long as there is no !physical
|
|
!force involved in the process. She is explicit:
|
|
|
|
"!Freedom, in a political context, means freedom from
|
|
government coercion. It does !not mean freedom from the landlord, or
|
|
freedom from the employer, or freedom from the laws of nature
|
|
which do not provide men with automatic prosperity. It means
|
|
freedom from the coercive power of the state--and nothing else!"
|
|
(endnote 33)
|
|
|
|
Note the juxtaposition of "landlord," "employer," and the
|
|
"laws of nature," the implication being that !all !three are an
|
|
inevitability. And again, please note the sole emphasis on !active
|
|
physical force. "What is the basic, the essential, the crucial principle
|
|
that differentiates freedom from slavery? It is the principle of
|
|
voluntary action !versus physical coercion or compulsion." (endnote
|
|
34) Rand's assumption is that, so long as there are no chains around
|
|
one's ankles and no state requiring labor by threat of punishment,
|
|
then labor is optional and workers are free.
|
|
|
|
"A right cannot be violated except by physical force. One man
|
|
cannot deprive another of his life nor enslave him, Whenever a man
|
|
is made to act without his own free, personal, individual, !voluntary
|
|
consent-- his right has been violated." (endnote 35)
|
|
|
|
To the anarchists, this is preposterous. Once a State has been
|
|
established, and most of the country's capital privatized, the threat of
|
|
physical force is no longer necessary to coerce workers into accepting
|
|
jobs, even with low pay and poor conditions. To use Rand's tern,
|
|
"initial force" has !already !taken !place, by those who now have
|
|
capital against those who do not. Bakunin described the conditions
|
|
which make "voluntary" labor and illusion:
|
|
|
|
"Juridically they are equal; but economically the worker is the
|
|
serf of the capitalist . . . thereby the worker sells his person ant his
|
|
liberty for a given time. The worker is in the position of a serf
|
|
because this terrible threat of starvation which daily hangs over his
|
|
head and over his family, will force him to accept any conditions
|
|
imposed by the gainful calculations of the capitalist, the industrialist,
|
|
the employer.... The worker always has the !right to leave his
|
|
employer, but has he the means to do so? No, he does it in order to
|
|
sell himself to another employer. He is driven to it by the same
|
|
hunger which forces him to sell himself to the first employer.
|
|
"Thus the "worker's liberty . . . is only a theoretical freedom.
|
|
lacking any means for its possible realization. ant consequently it is
|
|
only a fictitious liberty. an utter falsehood. The truth is that the whole
|
|
life of the worker is simply a continuous and dismaying succession of
|
|
terms of serfdom--"voluntary from the juridical point of view but
|
|
compulsory from an economic sense--broken up by momentarily brief
|
|
interludes of freedom accompanied by starvation; in other words, it is
|
|
real slavery" (endnote 36)
|
|
|
|
Rand sees an actual "equality of opportunity" in existence, at
|
|
least in American society, and she paints a picture of labor sans
|
|
exploitation, i.e. individual labor, production by individual hands
|
|
utilizing resources gained from private property. For example, "Man
|
|
has to work and produce in order to support his life. He has to
|
|
support his life by his own effort and by the guidance of his own
|
|
mind." Also, "without property rights, no other rights are possible.
|
|
Since man has to sustain his life by his own effort, the man who has
|
|
no right to the product of his effort has no means to sustain his life.
|
|
The man who produces while others dispose of his product, is a
|
|
slave." (endnote 37) Interestingly, Bakunin would likely agree with
|
|
this latter statement, that laborers who produce goods for the benefit
|
|
of others are "slaves," or, in fact, "serfs." Bakunin, however,
|
|
suggested that this was the standard condition in most of
|
|
industrialist/capitalist Europe. Bakunin wrote of the numerous ironies
|
|
inherent in the capitalist system. For instance, in spite of all their
|
|
labor, "the masses !will !never !come !to !own !property," and
|
|
therefore "their labor does not emancipate and ennoble them, for, all
|
|
their labor not withstanding, they are condemned to remain eternally
|
|
without property...." In reality, labor is not a measure of property
|
|
ownership, for the common worker is perpetually unable to save
|
|
enough money to purchase property. Indeed, Bakunin saw the very
|
|
opposite as being true. "We see that the richest property owners . . .
|
|
are precisely those who work the least or who do not work at all."
|
|
Actually, he clarifies this by saying that the wealthy classes do, in
|
|
fact, work, but not the "productive labor" of the proletariat masses.
|
|
Rather, theirs is a different kind of work, the "labor of exploitation,"
|
|
the business of trade and investment, the "labor" of increasing private
|
|
capital with the products of other's "productive" labor.
|
|
|
|
"It is evident to anyone who is not blind about this matter that
|
|
productive labor creates wealth and yields the producers only misery,
|
|
and it is only non-productive, exploiting labor that yields property....
|
|
!What !is !property, !what !is !capital !in !their !present !form? For
|
|
the capitalist and the property owner they mean the power and the
|
|
right, guaranteed by the State, to live without working. And since
|
|
neither property nor capital produces anything when not fertilized by
|
|
labor--that means the power and the right to live by exploiting the
|
|
work of someone else. The right to exploit the work of those who
|
|
possess neither property nor capital and who thus are forced to sell
|
|
their productive power to the lucky owners of both.
|
|
"Hence it follows that so long as property and capital exist on
|
|
the one hand. and labor on the other hand, the first constituting the
|
|
bourgeois class and the other the proletariat, the worker will be the
|
|
slave and the bourgeois the master." (endnote 38)
|
|
|
|
If economic exploitation is inevitable so long as some "lucky
|
|
owners" possess the means necessary to live fruitful lives, what is this
|
|
"luck" attributable to? Why do some "individuals" have an advantage
|
|
over others? "[W]hat is it that separates property and capital from
|
|
labor? What distinguishes the classes economically and politically
|
|
from one another, what destroys equality and perpetuates inequality,
|
|
the privilege of the few and the slavery of the many? It is the right of
|
|
inheritance." (endnote 39) To Bakunin, this is a lynchpin. The right
|
|
of inheritance is the factor which allows massive concentrations of
|
|
property and capital to accumulate, not in the hands of isolate
|
|
individuals, as Rand would endorse, but rather, along family lines,
|
|
constituting a !transgenerational gathering of wealth, granting each
|
|
lucky recipient the legal right to acquire more wealth by way of
|
|
luxurious "exploitative labor," and exempting him/her from gritty,
|
|
menial "productive labor." Bakunin saw this as nothing less than "the
|
|
very basis of the !juridical !family and the !State," and thus the
|
|
abolition of inheritance was imperative to establishing a genuine
|
|
Stateless society. In fact,
|
|
|
|
"The only thing that the State can and must do . . . is gradually
|
|
to modify the right of inheritance so as to achieve its complete
|
|
abolition as soon as possible. . . . We claim that this right will
|
|
necessarily have to be abolished because as long as !inheritance lasts,
|
|
there will be !hereditary economic inequality--not the natural
|
|
inequality of individuals, but the artificial inequality of classes--which
|
|
will necessarily continue to be expressed in hereditary inequality of
|
|
the development and cultivation of intelligence and will remain the
|
|
source and sanction of all political and social inequality." (endnote
|
|
40)
|
|
|
|
While Bakunin had no problem with !sentimental !inheritance,
|
|
that is, "objects of slight value which . . . have personal meaning."
|
|
His concern was for any "substantial [capital] inheritance" which
|
|
would allow heirs the "possibility of living without working."
|
|
(endnote 41) All other property would be collectivized by the
|
|
community, and made available to all its members and "productive
|
|
associations." This would probably constitute "theft" in the
|
|
Objectivist paradigm, but Bakunin examines its justice:
|
|
|
|
"Will this abolition be !just?
|
|
"A man, we are told, has acquired through his labor several tens
|
|
or hundreds of thousands of francs, 8 million, and he will not have
|
|
the right to leave them as an inheritance to his children! Is this not an
|
|
attack on natural right, is this not unjust plunder?
|
|
"[I]t has been proven 8 thousand times that an isolated worker
|
|
cannot produce much more than what he consumes. We challenge any
|
|
real worker, any worker who does not enjoy a single privilege, to
|
|
amass tens or hundreds of thousands of francs, or millions! That
|
|
would be quite impossible. Therefore, if some individuals in present-
|
|
day society do acquire such great sums, it is not by their labor that
|
|
they do so but by their privilege, that is, by a juridically legalized
|
|
injustice. And since a person inevitably takes from others whatever he
|
|
does not gain from his own, we have the right to say that all such
|
|
profits are thefts of collective labor, committed by a few privileged
|
|
individuals with the sanction of the State and under its protection."
|
|
(endnote 42)
|
|
|
|
In other words, if a thief died and willed his "ill-gotten gain" to
|
|
his children, would the children have a right to the stolen property?
|
|
Not legally. So if "property is theft," to borrow Proudhon's quip, and
|
|
the fruit of exploited labor is simply legal theft, then the only factor
|
|
giving the children of a deceased capitalist a right to inherit the
|
|
"booty" is the law, the State. As Bakunin wrote, "Ghosts should not
|
|
rule and oppress this world, which belongs only to the living."
|
|
What is Ayn Rand's response to this? Unfortunately, she has no
|
|
response. The Ayn Rand Lexicon, an alphabetized glossary of
|
|
quotations of Rand on myriad topics, published after her death, has no
|
|
entry on inheritance rights, and nowhere, in all of her elaborate and
|
|
occasionally repetitious descriptions of the virtue of property does she
|
|
mention the issue of inheritance, neither to endorse it nor condemn it.
|
|
But what would she say? If she were consistent to her doctrine of
|
|
individualism and independent achievement, she would logically
|
|
condemn it. After all, if an individual were to be given an abundance
|
|
of land from a deceased parent, then they would have an advantage
|
|
over their neighbors, an advantage which they did nothing directly to
|
|
earn. They would be reaping the fruits of collective labor, to a limited
|
|
degree, that is, the collective labor of numerous ancestors, whose
|
|
horde of property grows along familial lines, giving each generation
|
|
an even greater advantage. There is nothing "independent" or
|
|
"individual" about investing a !parents "hard-eared" money.
|
|
However, if she condemned inheritance, then, considering her
|
|
background, she would be severely violating her own past, and
|
|
likewise, her self-interest. While her theories may be flawed, she was
|
|
no idiot. The fact that she never mentioned the topic of inheritance
|
|
suggests, not that it never crossed her mind, but rather, that she had
|
|
no serious ideological problems with it. If she properly saw it as a
|
|
violation of the Objectivist ideal, she would likely have devoted an
|
|
entire essay to condemning it. Instead it is conspicuously absent from
|
|
her tenets. We therefore do not know how she would have responded
|
|
to Bakunin's program. But it would have been intriguing, no doubt.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
VI. Conclusion
|
|
|
|
There has, of late, been a profound confusion in the minds of
|
|
many, who have mistakenly described the Libertarian Party as being
|
|
"anarchist." It has been the aim of this essay to clarify the specific
|
|
nature of this erroneous comparison.
|
|
This confusion, however, is interesting, in and of itself. It is
|
|
rooted in this society's general acceptance, as an objective reality, the
|
|
presence of a fairly powerful state. We, the American public, have
|
|
been lulled into accepting an image of politics wherein we see our
|
|
options only as "moderate democracy," "extremist dictatorship," or
|
|
"chaotic anarchy." Government, to the average American, is a bit like
|
|
the porridge that Goldilocks sampled in the house of the three bears:
|
|
"too much government," "not enough government," or "just the right
|
|
amount of government." "We're losing the ability to differentiate
|
|
between politics and economics, and what different governments
|
|
really stand for. This is not simply sad, it's dangerous.
|
|
The Libertarian Party is seen as anarchistic only because,
|
|
today any group which advocates a drastic reduction in State power of
|
|
any kind, regardless of economic policy, is interpreted as "anarchist."
|
|
This would not have happened a century ago, in Europe or America.
|
|
These subtleties were much more clearly understood and delineated.
|
|
They knew the difference between anarchism, (State) communism,
|
|
and Libertarian (laissez-faire) capitalism. The differences were
|
|
important back then. Now we are out of practice, and it is difficult to
|
|
distinguish them. It is the sincere wish of the author that the
|
|
"landscape" graph will help facilitate the !reattunement necessary to
|
|
recognize the genuine positions of present and future
|
|
political/economic groups. The author has personally found this graph
|
|
invaluable in that regard.
|
|
Bakunin once wrote that, "[L]iberty without socialism is
|
|
privilege and injustice, and that socialism without liberty is slavery
|
|
and brutality." (endnote 43) It has been the goal of the author to
|
|
illustrate that, in Bakunin's words, the Libertarian Party represents
|
|
"liberty without socialism," and therefore, "privilege and injustice."
|
|
The final assessment is ultimately yours.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Endnotes
|
|
1. Utne Reader, No. 48; Nov./Dec. 1991. The center fold for
|
|
this issue included a multi-colored display entitled "The American
|
|
Political Landscape: An Alternative View." No specific authors were
|
|
cited. It should be noted that the version presented in this essay has
|
|
been substantially modified and expanded, and all modifications are
|
|
strictly the product of the author.
|
|
2. More often than not, the industrial complex of a fascist state
|
|
is often composed of foreign corporations. This is particularly the
|
|
case in most "Third World" nations, where the relationship to foreign
|
|
investors and domestic fascism is seen as having "imperialististic" or
|
|
"colonialistic" implications.
|
|
3. Bookchin, Murray; The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence
|
|
and Dissolution of Hierarchy, N.Y: Black Rose, Rev. 1991, p. !liv.
|
|
Bookchin refers to his theory of Social Ecology as "Libertarian
|
|
Municipalism."
|
|
4. Angeles, Peter A.; The HarperCollins Dictionary of
|
|
Philosophy, Second Edition, N.Y: HarperPerennial, 1992, pp. 11-12.
|
|
5. Maximoff, G. P. (Ed.); The Political Philosophy of Bakunin:
|
|
Scientific Anarchism, N.Y: Free Press, l953, p. 271.
|
|
6. Baldwin, Roger N.(Ed.); Kropotkin's Revolutionary
|
|
Pamphlets, N.Y: Benjamin Blom, 1927, p. 46.
|
|
7. Rocker, Rudolf; !Anarco-Syndicalism, London: Phoenix
|
|
Press, 1938, pp. l4- 15.
|
|
8. Ibid., p. 18.
|
|
9. Chomsky, Noam; !Radical !Priorities, Montreal, Canada:
|
|
Black Rose, 1981, p.245
|
|
10. Rand, Ayn; !Capitism. !The !Unknown !Ideal, N.Y: Signet
|
|
1946, p.46.
|
|
11. Binswanger, Harry (Ed.); !The !Ayn !Rand !Lexicon:
|
|
!Objectivism !from !A !to !Z, N.Y: Meridian, 1986, p.363.
|
|
12. Rand, op. cit.
|
|
13. Binswanger, op. cit., 190
|
|
14. Ibid., p. 388.
|
|
15. All of these essays are published in Rand, op. cit.
|
|
16. Binswanger, op. cit., p. 95.
|
|
17. Rand, op.cit., pp. 19-20.
|
|
18. Binswanger, op. cit., p. 57.
|
|
19. Rand, op. cit., p. 192.
|
|
20. Binswanger, op. cit., p. 475.
|
|
21. Ibid., p. 163.
|
|
22. Ibid.,p.21.
|
|
23. Ibid., p. 253.
|
|
24. Ibid., p. 254.
|
|
25. Ibid., p. 344.
|
|
26. Ibid.,p.218.
|
|
27. Lehning, Arther (Ed.); !Michael !Bakunin: !Selected
|
|
!Writings, London: Jonathan Cape, 1973.
|
|
28. Maximoff, op. cit., p. 157
|
|
29. Binswanger, op. cit., pp. 218-9.
|
|
30. Ibid., p. 214.
|
|
31. Ibid.,p.218.
|
|
32. Maximoff, op. cit., pp. 167-8.
|
|
33. Rand, op. cit.. p. 192.
|
|
34. Ibid., p. 46.
|
|
35. Binswanger, op. cit., p. 215
|
|
36. Maximoff, op. cit., p. 188.
|
|
37. Binswanger, op. cit., pp. 388-9.
|
|
38. Maximoff, op. cit., pp. 179-81.
|
|
39. Cutler, Robert M. (Ed.); !From !Out !of !the !Dustbin
|
|
!Bakunin's !Basic !Writing's 1869-1871, Ann Arbor: Ardis, 1985, p.
|
|
126.
|
|
40. Lehning, op. cit., p. 109.
|
|
41. Cutler, op. cit., p. 127.
|
|
42. Ibid., p. 129.
|
|
43. Lehning, op. cit., p. 110.
|
|
|
|
|