594 lines
36 KiB
Plaintext
594 lines
36 KiB
Plaintext
1898
|
|
THE MONADOLOGY
|
|
by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
|
|
translated by Robert Latta
|
|
|
|
1. The Monad, of which we shall here speak, is nothing but a
|
|
simple substance, which enters into compounds. By 'simple' is meant
|
|
'without parts.' (Theod. 10.)
|
|
2. And there must be simple substances, since there are compounds;
|
|
for a compound is nothing but a collection or aggregatum of simple
|
|
things.
|
|
3. Now where there are no parts, there can be neither extension
|
|
nor form [figure] nor divisibility. These Monads are the real atoms of
|
|
nature and, in a word, the elements of things.
|
|
4. No dissolution of these elements need be feared, and there is
|
|
no conceivable way in which a simple substance can be destroyed by
|
|
natural means. (Theod. 89.)
|
|
5. For the same reason there is no conceivable way in which a simple
|
|
substance can come into being by natural means, since it cannot be
|
|
formed by the combination of parts [composition].
|
|
6. Thus it may be said that a Monad can only come into being or come
|
|
to an end all at once; that is to say, it can come into being only
|
|
by creation and come to an end only by annihilation, while that
|
|
which is compound comes into being or comes to an end by parts.
|
|
7. Further, there is no way of explaining how a Monad can be altered
|
|
in quality or internally changed by any other created thing; since
|
|
it is impossible to change the place of anything in it or to
|
|
conceive in it any internal motion which could be produced,
|
|
directed, increased or diminished therein, although all this is
|
|
possible in the case of compounds, in which there are changes among
|
|
the parts. The Monads have no windows, through which anything could
|
|
come in or go out. Accidents cannot separate themselves from
|
|
substances nor go about outside of them, as the 'sensible species'
|
|
of the Scholastics used to do. Thus neither substance nor accident can
|
|
come into a Monad from outside.
|
|
8. Yet the Monads must have some qualities, otherwise they would not
|
|
even be existing things. And if simple substances did not differ in
|
|
quality, there would be absolutely no means of perceiving any change
|
|
in things. For what is in the compound can come only from the simple
|
|
elements it contains, and the Monads, if they had no qualities,
|
|
would be indistinguishable from one another, since they do not
|
|
differ in quantity. Consequently, space being a plenum, each part of
|
|
space would always receive, in any motion, exactly the equivalent of
|
|
what it already had, and no one state of things would be discernible
|
|
from another.
|
|
9. Indeed, each Monad must be different from every other. For in
|
|
nature there are never two beings which are perfectly alike and in
|
|
which it is not possible to find an internal difference, or at least a
|
|
difference founded upon an intrinsic quality [denomination].
|
|
10. I assume also as admitted that every created being, and
|
|
consequently the created Monad, is subject to change, and further that
|
|
this change is continuous in each.
|
|
11. It follows from what has just been said, that the natural
|
|
changes of the Monads come from an internal principle, since an
|
|
external cause can have no influence upon their inner being. (Theod.
|
|
396, 400.)
|
|
12. But, besides the principle of the change, there must be a
|
|
particular series of changes [un detail de ce qui change], which
|
|
constitutes, so to speak, the specific nature and variety of the
|
|
simple substances.
|
|
13. This particular series of changes should involve a
|
|
multiplicity in the unit [unite] or in that which is simple. For, as
|
|
every natural change takes place gradually, something changes and
|
|
something remains unchanged; and consequently a simple substance
|
|
must be affected and related in many ways, although it has no parts.
|
|
14. The passing condition, which involves and represents a
|
|
multiplicity in the unit [unite] or in the simple substance, is
|
|
nothing but what is called Perception, which is to be distinguished
|
|
from Apperception or Consciousness, as will afterwards appear. In this
|
|
matter the Cartesian view is extremely defective, for it treats as
|
|
non-existent those perceptions of which we are not consciously
|
|
aware. This has also led them to believe that minds [esprits] alone
|
|
are Monads, and that there are no souls of animals nor other
|
|
Entelechies. Thus, like the crowd, they have failed to distinguish
|
|
between a prolonged unconsciousness and absolute death, which has made
|
|
them fall again into the Scholastic prejudice of souls entirely
|
|
separate [from bodies], and has even confirmed ill-balanced minds in
|
|
the opinion that souls are mortal.
|
|
15. The activity of the internal principle which produces change
|
|
or passage from one perception to another may be called Appetition. It
|
|
is true that desire [l'appetit] cannot always fully attain to the
|
|
whole perception at which it aims, but it always obtains some of it
|
|
and attains to new perceptions.
|
|
16. We have in ourselves experience of a multiplicity in simple
|
|
substance, when we find that the least thought of which we are
|
|
conscious involves variety in its object. Thus all those who admit
|
|
that the soul is a simple substance should admit this multiplicity
|
|
in the Monad; and M. Bayle ought not to have found any difficulty in
|
|
this, as he has done in his Dictionary, article 'Rorarius.'
|
|
17. Moreover, it must be confessed that perception and that which
|
|
depends upon it are inexplicable on mechanical grounds, that is to
|
|
say, by means of figures and motions. And supposing there were a
|
|
machine, so constructed as to think, feel, and have perception, it
|
|
might be conceived as increased in size, while keeping the same
|
|
proportions, so that one might go into it as into a mill. That being
|
|
so, we should, on examining its interior, find only parts which work
|
|
one upon another, and never anything by which to explain a perception.
|
|
Thus it is in a simple substance, and not in a compound or in a
|
|
machine, that perception must be sought for. Further, nothing but this
|
|
(namely, perceptions and their changes) can be found in a simple
|
|
substance. It is also in this alone that all the internal activities
|
|
of simple substances can consist. (Theod. Pref. [E. 474; G. vi. 37].)
|
|
18. All simple substances or created Monads might be called
|
|
Entelechies, for they have in them a certain perfection (echousi to
|
|
enteles); they have a certain self-sufficiency (autarkeia) which makes
|
|
them the sources of their internal activities and, so to speak,
|
|
incorporeal automata. (Theod. 87.)
|
|
19. If we are to give the name of Soul to everything which has
|
|
perceptions and desires [appetits] in the general sense which I have
|
|
explained, then all simple substances or created Monads might be
|
|
called souls; but as feeling [le sentiment] is something more than a
|
|
bare perception, I think it right that the general name of Monads or
|
|
Entelechies should suffice for simple substances which have perception
|
|
only, and that the name of Souls should be given only to those in
|
|
which perception is more distinct, and is accompanied by memory.
|
|
20. For we experience in ourselves a condition in which we
|
|
remember nothing and have no distinguishable perception; as when we
|
|
fall into a swoon or when we are overcome with a profound dreamless
|
|
sleep. In this state the soul does not perceptibly differ from a
|
|
bare Monad; but as this state is not lasting, and the soul comes out
|
|
of it, the soul is something more than a bare Monad. (Theod. 64.)
|
|
21. And it does not follow that in this state the simple substance
|
|
is without any perception. That, indeed, cannot be, for the reasons
|
|
already given; for it cannot perish, and it cannot continue to exist
|
|
without being affected in some way, and this affection is nothing
|
|
but its perception. But when there is a great multitude of little
|
|
perceptions, in which there is nothing distinct, one is stunned; as
|
|
when one turns continuously round in the same way several times in
|
|
succession, whence comes a giddiness which may make us swoon, and
|
|
which keeps us from distinguishing anything. Death can for a time
|
|
put animals into this condition.
|
|
22. And as every present state of a simple substance is naturally
|
|
a consequence of its preceding state, in such a way that its present
|
|
is big with its future; (Theod. 350.)
|
|
23. And as, on waking from stupor, we are conscious of our
|
|
perceptions, we must have had perceptions immediately before we awoke,
|
|
although we were not at all conscious of them; for one perception
|
|
can in a natural way come only from another perception, as a motion
|
|
can in a natural way come only from a motion. (Theod. 401-403.)
|
|
24. It thus appears that if we had in our perceptions nothing marked
|
|
and, so to speak, striking and highly-flavoured, we should always be
|
|
in a state of stupor. And this is the state in which the bare Monads
|
|
are.
|
|
25. We see also that nature has given heightened perceptions to
|
|
animals, from the care she has taken to provide them with organs,
|
|
which collect numerous rays of light, or numerous undulations of the
|
|
air, in order, by uniting them, to make them have greater effect.
|
|
Something similar to this takes place in smell, in taste and in touch,
|
|
and perhaps in a number of other senses, which are unknown to us.
|
|
And I will explain presently how that which takes place in the soul
|
|
represents what happens in the bodily organs.
|
|
26. Memory provides the soul with a kind of consecutiveness, which
|
|
resembles [imite] reason, but which is to be distinguished from it.
|
|
Thus we see that when animals have a perception of something which
|
|
strikes them and of which they have formerly had a similar perception,
|
|
they are led, by means of representation in their memory, to expect
|
|
what was combined with the thing in this previous perception, and they
|
|
come to have feelings similar to those they had on the former
|
|
occasion. For instance, when a stick is shown to dogs, they remember
|
|
the pain it has caused them, and howl and run away. (Theod. Discours
|
|
de la Conformite, &c., ss. 65.)
|
|
27. And the strength of the mental image which impresses and moves
|
|
them comes either from the magnitude or the number of the preceding
|
|
perceptions. For often a strong impression produces all at once the
|
|
same effect as a long-formed habit, or as many and oft-repeated
|
|
ordinary perceptions.
|
|
28. In so far as the concatenation of their perceptions is due to
|
|
the principle of memory alone, men act like the lower animals,
|
|
resembling the empirical physicians, whose methods are those of mere
|
|
practice without theory. Indeed, in three-fourths of our actions we
|
|
are nothing but empirics. For instance, when we expect that there will
|
|
be daylight to-morrow, we do so empirically, because it has always
|
|
so happened until now. It is only the astronomer who thinks it on
|
|
rational grounds.
|
|
29. But it is the knowledge of necessary and eternal truths that
|
|
distinguishes us from the mere animals and gives us Reason and the
|
|
sciences, raising us to the knowledge of ourselves and of God. And
|
|
it is this in us that is called the rational soul or mind [esprit].
|
|
30. It is also through the knowledge of necessary truths, and
|
|
through their abstract expression, that we rise to acts of
|
|
reflexion, which make us think of what is called I, and observe that
|
|
this or that is within us: and thus, thinking of ourselves, we think
|
|
of being, of substance, of the simple and the compound, of the
|
|
immaterial, and of God Himself, conceiving that what is limited in
|
|
us is in Him without limits. And these acts of reflexion furnish the
|
|
chief objects of our reasonings. (Theod. Pref. [E. 469; G. vi. 27].)
|
|
31. Our reasonings are grounded upon two great principles, that of
|
|
contradiction, in virtue of which we judge false that which involves a
|
|
contradiction, and true that which is opposed or contradictory to
|
|
the false; (Theod. 44, 169.)
|
|
32. And that of sufficient reason, in virtue of which we hold that
|
|
there can be no fact real or existing, no statement true, unless there
|
|
be a sufficient reason, why it should be so and not otherwise,
|
|
although these reasons usually cannot be known by us. (Theod. 44,
|
|
196.)
|
|
33. There are also two kinds of truths, those of reasoning and those
|
|
of fact. Truths of reasoning are necessary and their opposite is
|
|
impossible: truths of fact are contingent and their opposite is
|
|
possible. When a truth is necessary, its reason can be found by
|
|
analysis, resolving it into more simple ideas and truths, until we
|
|
come to those which are primary. (Theod. 170, 174, 189, 280-282,
|
|
367. Abrege, Object. 3.)
|
|
34. It is thus that in Mathematics speculative Theorems and
|
|
practical Canons are reduced by analysis to Definitions, Axioms and
|
|
Postulates.
|
|
35. In short, there are simple ideas, of which no definition can
|
|
be given; there are also axioms and postulates, in a word, primary
|
|
principles, which cannot be proved, and indeed have no need of
|
|
proof; and these are identical propositions, whose opposite involves
|
|
an express contradiction. (Theod. 36, 37, 44, 45, 49, 52, 121-122,
|
|
337, 340-344.)
|
|
36. But there must also be a sufficient reason for contingent truths
|
|
or truths of fact, that is to say, for the sequence or connexion of
|
|
the things which are dispersed throughout the universe of created
|
|
beings, in which the analyzing into particular reasons might go on
|
|
into endless detail, because of the immense variety of things in
|
|
nature and the infinite division of bodies. There is an infinity of
|
|
present and past forms and motions which go to make up the efficient
|
|
cause of my present writing; and there is an infinity of minute
|
|
tendencies and dispositions of my soul, which go to make its final
|
|
cause.
|
|
37. And as all this detail again involves other prior or more
|
|
detailed contingent things, each of which still needs a similar
|
|
analysis to yield its reason, we are no further forward: and the
|
|
sufficient or final reason must be outside of the sequence or series
|
|
of particular contingent things, however infinite this series may be.
|
|
38. Thus the final reason of things must be in a necessary
|
|
substance, in which the variety of particular changes exists only
|
|
eminently, as in its source; and this substance we call God. (Theod.
|
|
7.)
|
|
39. Now as this substance is a sufficient reason of all this variety
|
|
of particulars, which are also connected together throughout; there is
|
|
only one God, and this God is sufficient.
|
|
40. We may also hold that this supreme substance, which is unique,
|
|
universal and necessary, nothing outside of it being independent of
|
|
it,- this substance, which is a pure sequence of possible being,
|
|
must be illimitable and must contain as much reality as is possible.
|
|
41. Whence it follows that God is absolutely perfect; for perfection
|
|
is nothing but amount of positive reality, in the strict sense,
|
|
leaving out of account the limits or bounds in things which are
|
|
limited. And where there are no bounds, that is to say in God,
|
|
perfection is absolutely infinite. (Theod. 22, Pref. [E. 469 a; G. vi.
|
|
27].)
|
|
42. It follows also that created beings derive their perfections
|
|
from the influence of God, but that their imperfections come from
|
|
their own nature, which is incapable of being without limits. For it
|
|
is in this that they differ from God. An instance of this original
|
|
imperfection of created beings may be seen in the natural inertia of
|
|
bodies. (Theod. 20, 27-30, 153, 167, 377 sqq.)
|
|
43. It is farther true that in God there is not only the source of
|
|
existences but also that of essences, in so far as they are real, that
|
|
is to say, the source of what is real in the possible. For the
|
|
understanding of God is the region of eternal truths or of the ideas
|
|
on which they depend, and without Him there would be nothing real in
|
|
the possibilities of things, and not only would there be nothing in
|
|
existence, but nothing would even be possible. (Theod. 20.)
|
|
44. For if there is a reality in essences or possibilities, or
|
|
rather in eternal truths, this reality must needs be founded in
|
|
something existing and actual, and consequently in the existence of
|
|
the necessary Being, in whom essence involves existence, or in whom to
|
|
be possible is to be actual. (Theod. 184-189, 335.)
|
|
45. Thus God alone (or the necessary Being) has this prerogative
|
|
that He must necessarily exist, if He is possible. And as nothing
|
|
can interfere with the possibility of that which involves no limits,
|
|
no negation and consequently no contradiction, this [His
|
|
possibility] is sufficient of itself to make known the existence of
|
|
God a priori. We have thus proved it, through the reality of eternal
|
|
truths. But a little while ago we proved it also a posteriori, since
|
|
there exist contingent beings, which can have their final or
|
|
sufficient reason only in the necessary Being, which has the reason of
|
|
its existence in itself.
|
|
46. We must not, however, imagine, as some do, that eternal
|
|
truths, being dependent on God, are arbitrary and depend on His
|
|
will, as Descartes, and afterwards M. Poiret, appear to have held.
|
|
That is true only of contingent truths, of which the principle is
|
|
fitness [convenance] or choice of the best, whereas necessary truths
|
|
depend solely on His understanding and are its inner object. (Theod.
|
|
180-184, 185, 335, 351, 380.)
|
|
47. Thus God alone is the primary unity or original simple
|
|
substance, of which all created or derivative Monads are products
|
|
and have their birth, so to speak, through continual fulgurations of
|
|
the Divinity from moment to moment, limited by the receptivity of
|
|
the created being, of whose essence it is to have limits. (Theod.
|
|
382-391, 398, 395.)
|
|
48. In God there is Power, which is the source of all, also
|
|
Knowledge, whose content is the variety of the ideas, and finally
|
|
Will, which makes changes or products according to the principle of
|
|
the best. (Theod. 7, 149, 150.) These characteristics correspond to
|
|
what in the created Monads forms the ground or basis, to the faculty
|
|
of Perception and to the faculty of Appetition. But in God these
|
|
attributes are absolutely infinite or perfect; and in the created
|
|
Monads or the Entelechies (or perfectihabiae, as Hermolaus Barbarus
|
|
translated the word) there are only imitations of these attributes,
|
|
according to the degree of perfection of the Monad. (Theod. 87.)
|
|
49. A created thing is said to act outwardly in so far as it has
|
|
perfection, and to suffer [or be passive, patir] in relation to
|
|
another, in so far as it is imperfect. Thus activity [action] is
|
|
attributed to a Monad, in so far as it has distinct perceptions, and
|
|
passivity [passion] in so far as its perceptions are confused. (Theod.
|
|
32, 66, 386.)
|
|
50. And one created thing is more perfect than another, in this,
|
|
that there is found in the more perfect that which serves to explain a
|
|
priori what takes place in the less perfect, and it is on this account
|
|
that the former is said to act upon the latter.
|
|
51. But in simple substances the influence of one Monad upon another
|
|
is only ideal, and it can have its effect only through the mediation
|
|
of God, in so far as in the ideas of God any Monad rightly claims that
|
|
God, in regulating the others from the beginning of things, should
|
|
have regard to it. For since one created Monad cannot have any
|
|
physical influence upon the inner being of another, it is only by this
|
|
means that the one can be dependent upon the other. (Theod. 9, 54, 65,
|
|
66, 201. Abrege, Object. 3.)
|
|
52. Accordingly, among created things, activities and passivities
|
|
are mutual. For God, comparing two simple substances, finds in each
|
|
reasons which oblige Him to adapt the other to it, and consequently
|
|
what is active in certain respects is passive from another point of
|
|
view; active in so far as what we distinctly know in it serves to
|
|
explain [rendre raison de] what takes place in another, and passive in
|
|
so far as the explanation [raison] of what takes place in it is to
|
|
be found in that which is distinctly known in another. (Theod. 66.)
|
|
53. Now, as in the Ideas of God there is an infinite number of
|
|
possible universes, and as only one of them can be actual, there
|
|
must be a sufficient reason for the choice of God, which leads Him
|
|
to decide upon one rather than another. (Theod. 8, 10, 44, 173, 196
|
|
sqq., 225, 414-416.)
|
|
54. And this reason can be found only in the fitness [convenance],
|
|
or in the degrees of perfection, that these worlds possess, since each
|
|
possible thing has the right to aspire to existence in proportion to
|
|
the amount of perfection it contains in germ. (Theod. 74, 167, 350,
|
|
201, 130, 352, 345 sqq., 354.)
|
|
55. Thus the actual existence of the best that wisdom makes known to
|
|
God is due to this, that His goodness makes Him choose it, and His
|
|
power makes Him produce it. (Theod. 8, 78, 80, 84, 119, 204, 206, 208.
|
|
Abrege, Object. 1 and 8.)
|
|
56. Now this connexion or adaptation of all created things to each
|
|
and of each to all, means that each simple substance has relations
|
|
which express all the others, and, consequently, that it is a
|
|
perpetual living mirror of the universe. (Theod. 130, 360.)
|
|
57. And as the same town, looked at from various sides, appears
|
|
quite different and becomes as it were numerous in aspects
|
|
[perspectivement]; even so, as a result of the infinite number of
|
|
simple substances, it is as if there were so many different universes,
|
|
which, nevertheless are nothing but aspects [perspectives] of a single
|
|
universe, according to the special point of view of each Monad.
|
|
(Theod. 147.)
|
|
58. And by this means there is obtained as great variety as
|
|
possible, along with the greatest possible order; that is to say, it
|
|
is the way to get as much perfection as possible. (Theod. 120, 124,
|
|
241 sqq., 214, 243, 275.)
|
|
59. Besides, no hypothesis but this (which I venture to call proved)
|
|
fittingly exalts the greatness of God; and this Monsieur Bayle
|
|
recognized when, in his Dictionary (article Rorarius), he raised
|
|
objections to it, in which indeed he was inclined to think that I
|
|
was attributing too much to God- more than it is possible to
|
|
attribute. But he was unable to give any reason which could show the
|
|
impossibility of this universal harmony, according to which every
|
|
substance exactly expresses all others through the relations it has
|
|
with them.
|
|
60. Further, in what I have just said there may be seen the
|
|
reasons a priori why things could not be otherwise than they are.
|
|
For God in regulating the whole has had regard to each part, and in
|
|
particular to each Monad, whose nature being to represent, nothing can
|
|
confine it to the representing of only one part of things; though it
|
|
is true that this representation is merely confused as regards the
|
|
variety of particular things [le detail] in the whole universe, and
|
|
can be distinct only as regards a small part of things, namely,
|
|
those which are either nearest or greatest in relation to each of
|
|
the Monads; otherwise each Monad would be a deity. It is not as
|
|
regards their object, but as regards the different ways in which
|
|
they have knowledge of their object, that the Monads are limited. In a
|
|
confused way they all strive after [vont a] the infinite, the whole;
|
|
but they are limited and differentiated through the degrees of their
|
|
distinct perceptions.
|
|
61. And compounds are in this respect analogous with [symbolisent
|
|
avec] simple substances. For all is a plenum (and thus all matter is
|
|
connected together) and in the plenum every motion has an effect
|
|
upon distant bodies in proportion to their distance, so that each body
|
|
not only is affected by those which are in contact with it and in some
|
|
way feels the effect of everything that happens to them, but also is
|
|
mediately affected by bodies adjoining those with which it itself is
|
|
in immediate contact. Wherefore it follows that this
|
|
inter-communication of things extends to any distance, however
|
|
great. And consequently every body feels the effect of all that
|
|
takes place in the universe, so that he who sees all might read in
|
|
each what is happening everywhere, and even what has happened or shall
|
|
happen, observing in the present that which is far off as well in time
|
|
as in place: sympnoia panta, as Hippocrates said. But a soul can
|
|
read in itself only that which is there represented distinctly; it
|
|
cannot all at once unroll everything that is enfolded in it, for its
|
|
complexity is infinite.
|
|
62. Thus, although each created Monad represents the whole universe,
|
|
it represents more distinctly the body which specially pertains to it,
|
|
and of which it is the entelechy; and as this body expresses the whole
|
|
universe through the connexion of all matter in the plenum, the soul
|
|
also represents the whole universe in representing this body, which
|
|
belongs to it in a special way. (Theod. 400.)
|
|
63. The body belonging to a Monad (which is its entelechy or its
|
|
soul) constitutes along with the entelechy what may be called a living
|
|
being, and along with the soul what is called an animal. Now this body
|
|
of living being or of an animal is always organic; for, as every Monad
|
|
is, in its own way, a mirror of the universe, and as the universe is
|
|
ruled according to a perfect order, there must also be order in that
|
|
which represents it, i.e. in the perceptions of the soul, and
|
|
consequently there must be order in the body, through which the
|
|
universe is represented in the soul. (Theod. 403.)
|
|
64. Thus the organic body of each living being is a kind of divine
|
|
machine or natural automaton, which infinitely surpasses all
|
|
artificial automata. For a machine made by the skill of man is not a
|
|
machine in each of its parts. For instance, the tooth of a brass wheel
|
|
has parts or fragments which for us are not artificial products, and
|
|
which do not have the special characteristics of the machine, for they
|
|
give no indication of the use for which the wheel was intended. But
|
|
the machines of nature, namely, living bodies, are still machines in
|
|
their smallest parts ad infinitum. It is this that constitutes the
|
|
difference between nature and art, that is to say, between the
|
|
divine art and ours. (Theod. 134, 146, 194, 403.)
|
|
65. And the Author of nature has been able to employ this divine and
|
|
infinitely wonderful power of art, because each portion of matter is
|
|
not only infinitely divisible, as the ancients observed, but is also
|
|
actually subdivided without end, each part into further parts, of
|
|
which each has some motion of its own; otherwise it would be
|
|
impossible for each portion of matter to express the whole universe.
|
|
(Theod. Prelim., Disc. de la Conform. 70, and 195.)
|
|
66. Whence it appears that in the smallest particle of matter
|
|
there is a world of creatures, living beings, animals, entelechies,
|
|
souls.
|
|
67. Each portion of matter may be conceived as like a garden full of
|
|
plants and like a pond full of fishes. But each branch of every plant,
|
|
each member of every animal, each drop of its liquid parts is also
|
|
some such garden or pond.
|
|
68. And though the earth and the air which are between the plants of
|
|
the garden, or the water which is between the fish of the pond, be
|
|
neither plant nor fish; yet they also contain plants and fishes, but
|
|
mostly so minute as to be imperceptible to us.
|
|
69. Thus there is nothing fallow, nothing sterile, nothing dead in
|
|
the universe, no chaos, no confusion save in appearance, somewhat as
|
|
it might appear to be in a pond at a distance, in which one would
|
|
see a confused movement and, as it were, a swarming of fish in the
|
|
pond, without separately distinguishing the fish themselves. (Theod.
|
|
Pref. [E. 475 b; 477 b; G. vi. 40, 44].)
|
|
70. Hence it appears that each living body has a dominant entelechy,
|
|
which in an animal is the soul; but the members of this living body
|
|
are full of other living beings, plants, animals, each of which has
|
|
also its dominant entelechy or soul.
|
|
71. But it must not be imagined, as has been done by some who have
|
|
misunderstood my thought, that each soul has a quantity or portion
|
|
of matter belonging exclusively to itself or attached to it for
|
|
ever, and that it consequently owns other inferior living beings,
|
|
which are devoted for ever to its service. For all bodies are in a
|
|
perpetual flux like rivers, and parts are entering into them and
|
|
passing out of them continually.
|
|
72. Thus the soul changes its body only by degrees, little by
|
|
little, so that it is never all at once deprived of all its organs;
|
|
and there is often metamorphosis in animals, but never
|
|
metempsychosis or transmigration of souls; nor are there souls
|
|
entirely separate [from bodies] nor unembodied spirits [genies sans
|
|
corps]. God alone is completely without body. (Theod. 90, 124.)
|
|
73. It also follows from this that there never is absolute birth
|
|
[generation] nor complete death, in the strict sense, consisting in
|
|
the separation of the soul from the body. What we call births
|
|
[generations] are developments and growths, while what we call
|
|
deaths are envelopments and diminutions.
|
|
74. Philosophers have been much perplexed about the origin of forms,
|
|
entelechies, or souls; but nowadays it has become known, through
|
|
careful studies of plants, insects, and animals, that the organic
|
|
bodies of nature are never products of chaos or putrefaction, but
|
|
always come from seeds, in which there was undoubtedly some
|
|
preformation; and it is held that not only the organic body was
|
|
already there before conception, but also a soul in this body, and, in
|
|
short, the animal itself; and that by means of conception this
|
|
animal has merely been prepared for the great transformation
|
|
involved in its becoming an animal of another kind. Something like
|
|
this is indeed seen apart from birth [generation], as when worms
|
|
become flies and caterpillars become butterflies. (Theod. 86, 89.
|
|
Pref. [E. 475 b; G. vi. 40 sqq.]; 90, 187, 188, 403, 86, 397.)
|
|
75. The animals, of which some are raised by means of conception
|
|
to the rank of larger animals, may be called spermatic, but those
|
|
among them which are not so raised but remain in their own kind
|
|
(that is, the majority) are born, multiply, and are destroyed like the
|
|
large animals, and it is only a few chosen ones [elus] that pass to
|
|
a greater theatre.
|
|
76. But this is only half of the truth, and accordingly I hold
|
|
that if an animal never comes into being by natural means
|
|
[naturellement], no more does it come to an end by natural means;
|
|
and that not only will there be no birth [generation], but also no
|
|
complete destruction or death in the strict sense. And these
|
|
reasonings, made a posteriori and drawn from experience are in perfect
|
|
agreement with my principles deduced a priori, as above. (Theod. 90.)
|
|
77. Thus it may be said that not only the soul (mirror of an
|
|
indestructible universe) is indestructible, but also the animal
|
|
itself, though its mechanism [machine] may often perish in part and
|
|
take off or put on an organic slough [des depouilles organiques].
|
|
78. These principles have given me a way of explaining naturally the
|
|
union or rather the mutual agreement [conformite] of the soul and
|
|
the organic body. The soul follows its own laws, and the body likewise
|
|
follows its own laws; and they agree with each other in virtue of
|
|
the pre-established harmony between all substances, since they are all
|
|
representations of one and the same universe. (Pref. [E. 475 a; G. vi.
|
|
39]; Theod. 340, 352, 353, 358.)
|
|
79. Souls act according to the laws of final causes through
|
|
appetitions, ends, and means. Bodies act according to the laws of
|
|
efficient causes or motions. And the two realms, that of efficient
|
|
causes and that of final causes, are in harmony with one another.
|
|
80. Descartes recognized that souls cannot impart any force to
|
|
bodies, because there is always the same quantity of force in
|
|
matter. Nevertheless he was of opinion that the soul could change
|
|
the direction of bodies. But that is because in his time it was not
|
|
known that there is a law of nature which affirms also the
|
|
conservation of the same total direction in matter. Had Descartes
|
|
noticed this he would have come upon my system of pre-established
|
|
harmony. (Pref. [E. 477 a; G. vi. 44]; Theod. 22, 59, 60, 61, 63,
|
|
66, 345, 346 sqq., 354, 355.)
|
|
81. According to this system bodies act as if (to suppose the
|
|
impossible) there were no souls, and souls act as if there were no
|
|
bodies, and both act as if each influenced the other.
|
|
82. As regards minds [esprits] or rational souls, though I find that
|
|
what I have just been saying is true of all living beings and
|
|
animals (namely that animals and souls come into being when the
|
|
world begins and no more come to an end that the world does), yet
|
|
there is this peculiarity in rational animals, that their spermatic
|
|
animalcules, so long as they are only spermatic, have merely
|
|
ordinary or sensuous [sensitive] souls; but when those which are
|
|
chosen [elus], so to speak, attain to human nature through an actual
|
|
conception, their sensuous souls are raised to the rank of reason
|
|
and to the prerogative of minds [esprits]. (Theod. 91, 397.)
|
|
83. Among other differences which exist between ordinary souls and
|
|
minds [esprits], some of which differences I have already noted, there
|
|
is also this: that souls in general are living mirrors or images of
|
|
the universe of created things, but that minds are also images of
|
|
the Deity or Author of nature Himself, capable of knowing the system
|
|
of the universe, and to some extent of imitating it through
|
|
architectonic ensamples [echantillons], each mind being like a small
|
|
divinity in its own sphere. (Theod. 147.)
|
|
84. It is this that enables spirits [or minds- esprits] to enter
|
|
into a kind of fellowship with God, and brings it about that in
|
|
relation to them He is not only what an inventor is to his machine
|
|
(which is the relation of God to other created things), but also
|
|
what a prince is to his subjects, and, indeed, what a father is to his
|
|
children.
|
|
85. Whence it is easy to conclude that the totality [assemblage]
|
|
of all spirits [esprits] must compose the City of God, that is to say,
|
|
the most perfect State that is possible, under the most perfect of
|
|
Monarchs. (Theod. 146; Abrege, Object. 2.)
|
|
86. This City of God, this truly universal monarchy, is a moral
|
|
world in the natural world, and is the most exalted and most divine
|
|
among the works of God; and it is in it that the glory of God really
|
|
consists, for He would have no glory were not His greatness and His
|
|
goodness known and admired by spirits [esprits]. It is also in
|
|
relation to this divine City that God specially has goodness, while
|
|
His wisdom and His power are manifested everywhere. (Theod. 146;
|
|
Abrege, Object. 2.)
|
|
87. As we have shown above that there is a perfect harmony between
|
|
the two realms in nature, one of efficient, and the other of final
|
|
causes, we should here notice also another harmony between the
|
|
physical realm of nature and the moral realm of grace, that is to say,
|
|
between God, considered as Architect of the mechanism [machine] of the
|
|
universe and God considered as Monarch of the divine City of spirits
|
|
[esprits]. (Theod. 62, 74, 118, 248, 112, 130, 247.)
|
|
88. A result of this harmony is that things lead to grace by the
|
|
very ways of nature, and that this globe, for instance, must be
|
|
destroyed and renewed by natural means at the very time when the
|
|
government of spirits requires it, for the punishment of some and
|
|
the reward of others. (Theod. 18 sqq., 110, 244, 245, 340.)
|
|
89. It may also be said that God as Architect satisfies in all
|
|
respects God as Lawgiver, and thus that sins must bear their penalty
|
|
with them, through the order of nature, and even in virtue of the
|
|
mechanical structure of things; and similarly that noble actions
|
|
will attain their rewards by ways which, on the bodily side, are
|
|
mechanical, although this cannot and ought not always to happen
|
|
immediately.
|
|
90. Finally, under this perfect government no good action would be
|
|
unrewarded and no bad one unpunished, and all should issue in the
|
|
well-being of the good, that is to say, of those who are not
|
|
malcontents in this great state, but who trust in Providence, after
|
|
having done their duty, and who love and imitate, as is meet, the
|
|
Author of all good, finding pleasure in the contemplation of His
|
|
perfections, as is the way of genuine 'pure love,' which takes
|
|
pleasure in the happiness of the beloved. This it is which leads
|
|
wise and virtuous people to devote their energies to everything
|
|
which appears in harmony with the presumptive or antecedent will of
|
|
God, and yet makes them content with what God actually brings to
|
|
pass by His secret, consequent and positive [decisive] will,
|
|
recognizing that if we could sufficiently understand the order of
|
|
the universe, we should find that it exceeds all the desires of the
|
|
wisest men, and that it is impossible to make it better than it is,
|
|
not only as a whole and in general but also for ourselves in
|
|
particular, if we are attached, as we ought to be, to the Author of
|
|
all, not only as to the architect and efficient cause of our being,
|
|
but as to our master and to the final cause, which ought to be the
|
|
whole aim of our will, and which can alone make our happiness. (Theod.
|
|
134, 278. Pref. [E. 469; G. vi. 27, 28].)
|
|
|
|
THE END
|