326 lines
19 KiB
Plaintext
326 lines
19 KiB
Plaintext
|
|
At any rate, this whole train of thought brings to mind Peter Marshall's
|
|
recent compendium, _Demanding_the_Impossible:_A_History_of_Anarchism_ --
|
|
London: Fontana Press, 1992 (ISBN 0 00 686245 4). An informative and
|
|
vastly entertaining read, recommended for anyone with an anti-authority
|
|
bent, it logs anarchistic thought from the Tao to the Sex Pistols (700+
|
|
pages).
|
|
|
|
Marshall labels these old-guard classical liberals "anarcho-capitalists"
|
|
-- a superior term to right-wing anarchist, for reasons Marshall gives
|
|
in summation of this short chapter (Chomsky gets his on section in the
|
|
chapter called Modern Libertarians). Capital is what they really seek
|
|
to liberate, not people.
|
|
|
|
For your enjoyment, I present the relevant chapter from Marshall's book.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
Chapter 36: The New Right and Anarcho-capitalism
|
|
|
|
Anarcho-capitalism has recently had a considerable vogue in the West
|
|
where it has helped put the role of the State back on the political
|
|
agenda. It has become a major ideological challenge to the dominant
|
|
liberalism which sees a role for government in the protection of
|
|
property. The anarcho-capitalists would like to dismantle government
|
|
and allow complete _laissez-faire_ in the economy. Its adherents
|
|
propose that all public services be turned over to private
|
|
entrepreneurs, even public spaces like town halls, streets and parks.
|
|
Free market capitalism, they insist, is hindered not enhanced by the
|
|
State.
|
|
|
|
Anarcho-capitalists share Adam Smith's confidence that somehow private
|
|
interest will translate itself into public good rather than public
|
|
squalor. They are convinced that the 'natural laws' of economics can do
|
|
without the support of positive man-made laws. The 'invisible hand' of
|
|
the market will be enough to bring social order.
|
|
|
|
Anarcho-capitalism has recently had the greatest impact in the United
|
|
States, where the Libertarian Party has taken it up as the house
|
|
ideology, and where Republicans like Ronald Reagan wanted to be
|
|
remembered for cutting taxation and for getting 'the government off
|
|
peoples' backs'. In the United Kingdom, neo-Conservatives argue that
|
|
'there is no such thing as society' and wish to 'roll back the frontiers
|
|
of the State' -- a view adopted evangelically, in theory if not always
|
|
in practice, by Margaret Thatcher, Prime Minister from 1979 to 1990.
|
|
State socialism is attacked not so much because it is egalitarian but
|
|
because it seeks to accrue more powers for the State to exercise
|
|
centrally.
|
|
|
|
The phenomenon of anarcho-capitalism is not however new. With the
|
|
demise of Benjamin Tucker's journal _Liberty_ in 1907, American
|
|
individualist anarchism lost its principal voice; but its strain of
|
|
libertarianism continued to re-emerge occassionally in the offerings of
|
|
isolated thinkers. The young essayist Randolph Bourne, writing outside
|
|
the anarchist movement, distinguished between society and the State,
|
|
invented the famous slogan 'War is the Health of the State', and drew
|
|
out the authoritarian and conformist dangers of the 'herd'.[1]
|
|
|
|
FRANZ OPPENHEIMER's view of the State as 'the organization of the
|
|
political means' and as the 'systematization of the predatory process
|
|
over a given territory' influenced libertarians and conservatives alike
|
|
in the twenties.[2] The Jeffersonian liberal ALBERT JAY NOCK reached
|
|
anarchist conclusions in _Our_Enemy_The_State_ (1935) at the time of the
|
|
New Deal. A conservative of the _laissez-faire_ school, he foresaw 'a
|
|
steady progress in collectivism running into a military despotism of a
|
|
severe type'.[3] It would involve steadily-increasing centralization,
|
|
bureaucracy, and political control of the market. The resulting
|
|
State-managed economy would be so inefficient and corrupt that it would
|
|
need forced labor to keep it going.
|
|
|
|
Nock's warning did not go unheeded. FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK spelt out in
|
|
_The_Road_to_Serfdom_ (1944) the dangers of collectivism. In his
|
|
restatement of classic liberalism in _The_Constitution_of_Liberty_
|
|
(1960), he rejected the notion of social justice and argued that the
|
|
market creates spontaneous social order. But while he wished to reduce
|
|
coercion to a minimum, he accepted the need for the coercion of a
|
|
minimal State to prohibit coercive acts by private parties through law
|
|
enforcement. He also accepted taxation and compulsory military service.
|
|
While a harsh critic of egalitarianism and of government intervention in
|
|
the economy, he was ready to countenance a degree of welfare provision
|
|
which cannot be adequately provided by the market. His views have had
|
|
an important influence on neo-Conservatives, especially those on the
|
|
right wing of the Conservative Party in Britain.
|
|
|
|
Anarcho-capitalists like David Friedman and Murray Rothbard go much
|
|
further. In some ways, their position appears to be a revival of the
|
|
principles of the Old Right against the New Deal which sought government
|
|
interference in the economy, but they are not only motivated by a
|
|
nostalgia for a thoroughly free market but are aggressively
|
|
anti-authoritarian. Where Tucker called anarchism 'consistent
|
|
Manchesterism', that is taking the nineteenth-century _laissez-faire_
|
|
school of economists to their logical conclusion, anarcho-capitalists
|
|
might be called consistent Lockeans.
|
|
|
|
Following Locke, classic liberals argue that the principals task of
|
|
government is to protect the natural rights to life, liberty and
|
|
property because a 'state of nature' where there is no common law the
|
|
enjoyment of such rights would be uncertain and inconvenient. The
|
|
anarch-capitalists also ask, like Locke in his _Second_Treatise_, 'If
|
|
Man in the state of Nature be so free as has been said, if he be
|
|
absolute lord of his own person and possessions, equal to the greatest
|
|
and subject to nobody, why will he part with his freedom?'[4] Unlike
|
|
Locke, however, the anarch-capitalists do not find such a state of
|
|
nature without a common judge inconvenient or uncertain. They maintain
|
|
that even the minimal State is unnecessary since the defence of person
|
|
and property can be carried out by private protection agencies.
|
|
|
|
DAVID FRIEDMAN sees such agencies as both brokers of mini-social
|
|
contracts and producers of 'laws' which conform to the market demand for
|
|
rules to regulate commerce. Each person would be free to subscribe to a
|
|
protective association of his choice, since 'Protection from coercion is
|
|
an economic good'.[5] Apart from adumbrating _The_Machinery_of_Freedom_
|
|
(1973), Friedman has populated Hayek's defence of capitalism as the best
|
|
antidote to the serfdom of collectivism and the State.
|
|
|
|
The writings of AYN RAND, a refugee from the Soviet Union, best
|
|
represent the intellectual background to the new right-wing
|
|
libertarianism in the United States. In her
|
|
_The_Virtue_of_Selfishness:_ A_New_Concept_of_Egoism_ (1964), she
|
|
attempted a philosophical defence of egoism while in her novels she
|
|
portrayed a superior individual fighting the forces of collectivism,
|
|
particularly in the form of the State. Her superior individual, driven
|
|
by a Nietzschean will to power, appears in the guise of a capitalist
|
|
entrepreneur who is presented as the source of all wealth and creator of
|
|
all progress. Rand claimed that she had a direct knowledge of objective
|
|
reality, and her 'Objectivist' movement had a considerable vogue in the
|
|
sixties. Like most anarch-capitalists, she is convinced of the truth of
|
|
her own views, which to others appear mere dogma. She remains a minimal
|
|
statist rather than a strict anarchist.
|
|
|
|
Amongst anarch-capitalist apologists, the economist MURRAY ROTHBARD is
|
|
probably most aware of the anarchist tradition. He was originally
|
|
regarded as an extreme right-wing Republican, but went on to edit la
|
|
Boetie's libertarian classic _Of_Voluntary_Servitude_ and now calls
|
|
himself an anarchist. 'If you wish to know how the libertarians regard
|
|
the State and any of its acts," he wrote in _For_A_New_Liberty:_
|
|
_The_Libertarian_Manifesto_ (1973), 'simply think of the State as a
|
|
criminal band, and all the libertarian attitudes will logically fall
|
|
into place.' He reduces the libertarian creed to one central axiom,
|
|
'that no man or group of men may aggress against the person or property
|
|
of anyone else'.[6] Neither the State nor any private party therefore
|
|
can initiate or threaten the use of force against any person for any
|
|
purpose. Free individuals should regulate their affairs and dispose of
|
|
their property only by voluntary agreement based on contractual
|
|
obligation.
|
|
|
|
Rejecting the State as a 'protection' with an illegitimate claim on the
|
|
monopoly of force, Rothbard would like to see it dissolved, as would
|
|
Friedman, into social and market arrangements. He proposes that
|
|
disputes over violations of persons and property may be settled
|
|
voluntarily by arbitration firms whose decisions are enforceable by
|
|
private protection agencies.
|
|
|
|
Rothbard described an anarchist society where 'there is no legal
|
|
possibility for coercive aggression against the person or property of
|
|
any individual'. But where Tucker recognized no inherent right to
|
|
property, Rothbard insists on the need for a 'basic libertarian code of
|
|
the inviolate right of person and property'.[7] In addition, for all his
|
|
commitment to a Stateless society, Rothbard is willing to engage in
|
|
conventional politics. He helped found the Libertarian Party in the USA
|
|
which wants to abolish the entire federal regulatory apparatus as well
|
|
as social security, welfare, public education, and taxation. Accepting
|
|
Bourne's view that war is the health of the State, the Party wants the
|
|
United States to withdraw from the United Nations, end its foreign
|
|
commitments, and reduce its military forces to those required for
|
|
minimal defence.
|
|
|
|
Rothbard argued at the 1977 Libertarian Party Congress that to become a
|
|
true libertarian it was necessary to be 'born again', not once ut twice,
|
|
in a baptism of reason as well as of will. Since in his view
|
|
libertarianism is the only creed compatible with the nature of man and
|
|
the world, he is convinced that it will win because it is true.
|
|
Whatever the workers and bureaucrats might think or want, Statism will
|
|
collapse of its own contradictions and the free market will prevail
|
|
throughout the world.
|
|
|
|
However libertarian in appearance, there are some real difficulties in
|
|
the anarch-capitalists' position. If laws and courts are replaced by
|
|
arbitrary firms, why should an individual accept their verdict? And
|
|
since he 'buys' justice, what assurances are there that the verdicts
|
|
would be fair and impartial? If the verdicts are enforced by private
|
|
protection agencies, it would seem likely, as ROBERT NOZICK has pointed
|
|
out, that a dominant protective agency (the one offering the most
|
|
powerful and comprehensive protection) would eventually emerge through
|
|
free competition.[8] A _de_facto_ territorial monopoly would thus result
|
|
from the competition among protection agencies which would then
|
|
constitute a proto-State. The only difference between the
|
|
'ultraminimal' State of a dominant protection agency and a minimal State
|
|
would be that its services would be available only to those who buy
|
|
them.
|
|
|
|
Nozick's work _State,_Anarchy_and_Utopia_ (1974) is widely regarded as
|
|
one of the most important works in contemporary political philosophy.
|
|
Inspired in part by individual anarchist arguments, especially those of
|
|
Spooner and Tucker, and replying to the libertarian view of Rothbard and
|
|
Rand, he calls for a minimal State to oversee private protection
|
|
agencies to ensure contracts are kept by property-owning individuals.
|
|
He insists however that a man ruled by others against his will, whose
|
|
life and property are under their control, is no less a slave because he
|
|
has the vote and periodically may 'choose' his masters.
|
|
|
|
Nozick has helped to make libertarian and anarchist theory acceptable in
|
|
academic circles. But in the end he opts for a nightwatchman State in
|
|
order to protect the individual's rights to life, liberty and property.
|
|
In his 'framework for utopia', he proposes a society of independent
|
|
city-States organized according to their inhabitants' preferences. He
|
|
defends capitalism under the theory of just entitlement, arguing that
|
|
just acquisitions and just transfers made in the absence of force or
|
|
fraud legitimize the distribution of wealth resulting from capitalist
|
|
exchange. However poorly a person may fare in the exercise of human
|
|
liberty, there is no moral reason to correct market forces by
|
|
redistributing wealth. The acceptable maxim of capitalism for Nozick is
|
|
therefore: 'From each as they choose, to each as they are chosen'.[9]
|
|
|
|
Nozick joins a group of American philosophers like JOHN HOSPERS and ERIC
|
|
MACK who adopt 'minarchy' rather than anarchy. They call for a minimal
|
|
State, restricting the scope of the modern state to Locke's 'common
|
|
judge with authority' to make laws (for the protection of property), to
|
|
punish thieves and malefactors, and to defend the nation against foreign
|
|
aggression.[10] They are right-wing libertarians rather than anarchists
|
|
in the tradition of Jefferson, insisting 'that government is best which
|
|
governs least'.
|
|
|
|
A more thorough-going philosophical defence of anarchism has been put
|
|
forward by ROBERT PAUL WOLFF. He rejects the political legitimacy of
|
|
the State on a neo-Kantian principle of moral autonomy. he assumes that
|
|
in so far as people are rational and are to act they must be autonomous.
|
|
The autonomous man who determines his own acts refuses to be ruled and
|
|
denies all claims to political authority: 'For the autonomous man, there
|
|
is no such thing, strictly speaking, as a command.'[11] Wolff does not
|
|
however see any immediate implications for his philosophical anarchism
|
|
and ethical individualism. In his 'Utopian Glimpses of a World Without
|
|
States' in _A_Defense_of_Anarchism_ (1970), he maintains that a high
|
|
order of social co-ordination in a society in which no one claims
|
|
legitimate authority would only be possible after its members had
|
|
achieved a high level of moral and intellectual development. Indeed,
|
|
rather than offering a defence of anarchism as a political theory, he
|
|
seems more concerned with elaborating a form of moral and political
|
|
scepticism.[12]
|
|
|
|
Wolff's practical proposals are also problematic. He recommends a form
|
|
of 'instant direct democracy' based on a system of 'voting machines' in
|
|
every home linked to a computer in Washington. Each Bill would then be
|
|
voted on by all the people after it had been discussed by their
|
|
representatives in a national assembly. But such a system could easily
|
|
lead to representatives manipulating their votes as they do in existing
|
|
parliamentary democracies. There is also a big difference, recognized
|
|
in part by Wolff, between the passive role of listener and the active
|
|
role of participant in a debate. The kind of direct democracy practiced
|
|
in ancient Athens, which actively involved all the citizens, would
|
|
appear to be preferable to television viewers being merely able to
|
|
register their response to decisions made by an elected elite. Wolff's
|
|
proposal would turn citizenship into little more than a spectator-sport.
|
|
He allows no meaningful debate or collective discussion of ends.
|
|
|
|
Although he recommends extreme economic decentralization, Wolff alines
|
|
himself with the anarcho-capitalists and right-libertarians by wanting
|
|
to retain private property and the market to co-ordinate human behavior.
|
|
Again, he suggests that the army could be run on the basis of voluntary
|
|
commitment and submission to orders but this would seem little different
|
|
from existing forms of voluntary conscription.
|
|
|
|
In the utopias of the anarcho-capitalists, there is little reason to
|
|
believe that the rich and powerful will not continue to exploit and
|
|
oppress the powerless and poor as they do at present. It is difficult
|
|
to imagine that protective services could impose their ideas of fair
|
|
procedure without resorting to coercion. With the free market
|
|
encouraging selfishness, there is no assurance that 'public goods' like
|
|
sanitation and clean water would be provided for all. Indeed, the
|
|
anarcho-capitalists deny the very existence of collective interests and
|
|
responsibilities. They reject the rich communitarian tradition of the
|
|
ancient Greek _polis_ in favor of the most limited form of possessive
|
|
individualism. In their drive for self-interest, they have no
|
|
conception of the general good or public interest. In his relationship
|
|
with society, the anarcho-capitalist stands alone, an egoistic and
|
|
calculating consumer; society is considered to be nothing more than a
|
|
loose collection of autonomous individuals.
|
|
|
|
The anarcho-capitalist definition of freedom is entirely negative. It
|
|
calls for the absence of coercion but cannot guarantee the positive
|
|
freedom of individual autonomy and independence. Nor does it recognize
|
|
the equal right of all to the means of subsistence. Hayek speaks on
|
|
behalf of the anarcho-capitalist when he warns: 'Above all we must
|
|
recognize that we may be free and yet miserable.'[13] Others go even
|
|
further to insist that liberty and bread are not synonymous and that we
|
|
have 'the liberty to die of hunger'.[14] In the name of freedom, the
|
|
anarcho-capitalists would like to turn public spaces into private
|
|
property, but freedom does not flourish behind high fences protected by
|
|
private companies but expands in the open air when it is enjoyed by all.
|
|
|
|
Anarcho-capitalists are against the State simply because they are
|
|
capitalists first and foremost. Their critique of the State ultimately
|
|
rests on a liberal interpretation of liberty as the inviolable rights to
|
|
and of private property. They are not concerned with the social
|
|
consequences of capitalism for the weak, powerless and ignorant. Their
|
|
claim that all would benefit from a free exchange in the market is by no
|
|
means certain; any unfettered market system would most likely sponsor a
|
|
reversion to an unequal society with defence associations perpetuating
|
|
exploitation and privilege. If anything, anarcho-capitalism is merely a
|
|
free-for-all in which only the rich and cunning would benefit. It is
|
|
tailor-made for 'rugged individualists' who do not care about the damage
|
|
to others or to the environment which they leave in their wake. The
|
|
forces of the market cannot provide genuine conditions for freedom any
|
|
more than the powers of the State. The victims of both are equally
|
|
enslaved, alienated and oppressed.
|
|
|
|
As such, anarcho-capitalism overlooks the egalitarian implications of
|
|
traditional individualist anarchists like Spooner and Tucker. In fact,
|
|
few anarchists would accept 'anarcho-capitalists' into the anarchist
|
|
camp since they do not share a concern for economic equality and social
|
|
justice. Their self-interested, calculating market men would be
|
|
incapable of practising voluntary co-operation and mutual aid.
|
|
Anarcho-capitalists, even if they do reject the State, might therefore
|
|
best be called right-wing libertarians rather than anarchists.[15]
|
|
|
|
eof
|
|
|
|
[ ... glad to see you actually made it all the way... ;)]
|
|
|
|
|
|
--
|
|
"Don't HATE the media... | K.K.Campbell
|
|
beCOME the media!" --*-- <zodiac@zooid.guild.org>
|
|
- J. Biafra | . . . . cum grano salis
|
|
|