869 lines
47 KiB
Plaintext
869 lines
47 KiB
Plaintext
|
|
Computer underground Digest Tue Jun 20, 1995 Volume 7 : Issue 51
|
|
ISSN 1004-042X
|
|
|
|
Editors: Jim Thomas and Gordon Meyer (TK0JUT2@MVS.CSO.NIU.EDU
|
|
Archivist: Brendan Kehoe
|
|
Shadow Master: Stanton McCandlish
|
|
Field Agent Extraordinaire: David Smith
|
|
Shadow-Archivists: Dan Carosone / Paul Southworth
|
|
Ralph Sims / Jyrki Kuoppala
|
|
Ian Dickinson
|
|
Triviata: How many Spams have C&S Done since April '94?
|
|
|
|
CONTENTS, #7.51 (Tue, Jun 20, 1995)
|
|
|
|
File 1--Against Intellectual Property
|
|
File 2--Cu Digest Header Info (unchanged since 19 Apr, 1995)
|
|
|
|
CuD ADMINISTRATIVE, EDITORIAL, AND SUBSCRIPTION INFORMATION APPEARS IN
|
|
THE CONCLUDING FILE AT THE END OF EACH ISSUE.
|
|
|
|
---------------------------------------------------------------------
|
|
|
|
From: Brian Martin <b.martin@uow.edu.au>
|
|
Date: Tue, 30 May 1995 18.2.43 CDT
|
|
Subject: File 1--Against Intellectual Property
|
|
|
|
AGAINST INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
|
|
|
|
Brian Martin
|
|
Department of Science and Technology Studies
|
|
University of Wollongong, NSW 2522, Australia
|
|
email: b.martin@uow.edu.au
|
|
|
|
To appear in Philosophy and Social Action, Vol. 21, No. 3, July-September
|
|
1995
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
There is a strong case for opposing intellectual property. There are a number
|
|
of negative consequences of the ownership of information, such as retarding
|
|
of innovation and exploitation of poor countries. Most of the usual arguments
|
|
for intellectual property do not hold up under scrutiny. In particular, the
|
|
metaphor of the marketplace of ideas provides no justification for ownership
|
|
of ideas. The alternative to intellectual property is that intellectual
|
|
products not be owned, as in the case of everyday language. Strategies
|
|
against intellectual property include civil disobedience, promotion of
|
|
non-owned information, and fostering of a more cooperative society.
|
|
|
|
|
|
In 1980, a book entitled Documents on Australian Defence and Foreign Policy
|
|
1968-1975 was published by George Munster and Richard Walsh. It reproduced
|
|
many secret government memos, briefings and other documents concerning
|
|
Australian involvement in the Vietnam war, events leading up to the
|
|
Indonesian invasion of East Timor, and other issues. Exposure of this
|
|
material deeply embarrassed the Australian government. In an unprecedented
|
|
move, the government issued an interim injunction, citing both the Crimes Act
|
|
and the Copyright Act. The books, just put on sale, were impounded. Print
|
|
runs of two major newspapers with extracts from the book were also seized.
|
|
The Australian High Court ruled that the Crimes Act did not apply, but that
|
|
the material was protected by copyright held by the government. Later,
|
|
Munster and Walsh produced a book using summaries and short quotes in order
|
|
to present the information (Munster 1982).
|
|
|
|
This example is one of many that shows how copyright is used to protect the
|
|
interests of the powerful in the face of challengers, at the expense of free
|
|
speech. Yet copyright is standardly justified on the grounds that it promotes
|
|
creation and dissemination of ideas.
|
|
|
|
Copyright is one of four main types of intellectual property or, in other
|
|
words, ownership of information. The others are patents, trademarks and trade
|
|
secrets. Copyright covers the expression of ideas such as in writing, music
|
|
and pictures. Patents cover inventions, such as designs for objects or
|
|
industrial processes. Trademarks are symbols associated with a good, service
|
|
or company. Trade secrets cover confidential business information.
|
|
|
|
The type of property that is familiar to most people is physical objects.
|
|
People own clothes, cars, houses and land. When people own ideas, this is
|
|
called intellectual property. But there has always been a big problem with
|
|
owning ideas -- exclusive use or control of ideas doesn't make nearly as much
|
|
sense as it does applied to physical objects.
|
|
|
|
Many physical objects can only be used by one person at a time. If one person
|
|
wears a pair of shoes, no one else can wear them at the same time. (The
|
|
person who wears them often also owns them, but not always.) This is not true
|
|
of intellectual property. Ideas can be copied over and over, but the person
|
|
who had the original copy still has full use of it. Suppose you write a poem.
|
|
Even if a million other people have copies and read the poem, you can still
|
|
read the poem yourself. In other words, more than one person can use an idea
|
|
-- a poem, a mathematical formula, a tune -- without reducing other people's
|
|
use of the idea. Shoes and poems are fundamentally different in this respect.
|
|
|
|
Technological developments have made it cheaper and easier to make copies of
|
|
information. Printing was a great advance: it eliminated the need for hand
|
|
copying of documents. Photocopying and computers have made it even easier to
|
|
make copies of written documents. Photography and sound recordings have done
|
|
the same for visual and sound material. The ability to protect intellectual
|
|
property is being undermined by technology. Yet there is a strong push to
|
|
expand the scope of ownership of information.
|
|
|
|
This article outlines the case against intellectual property. I begin by
|
|
mentioning some of the problems arising from ownership of information. Then I
|
|
turn to weaknesses in the standard justifications for intellectual property.
|
|
Next is an overview of problems with the so-called "marketplace of ideas,"
|
|
which has important links with intellectual property. Finally, I outline some
|
|
alternatives to intellectual property and some possible strategies for moving
|
|
towards these alternatives.
|
|
|
|
SOME PROBLEMS WITH INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
|
|
|
|
Governments generate large quantities of information. They produce statistics
|
|
on population, figures on economic production and health, texts of laws and
|
|
regulations, and vast numbers of reports. The generation of this information
|
|
is paid for through taxation and, therefore, it might seem that it should be
|
|
available to any member of the public. But in some countries, some of this
|
|
information is turned over to corporations that then sell it to whoever can
|
|
pay. Publicly funded information is "privatised" and thus is not freely
|
|
available (Nelkin 1984).
|
|
|
|
When government-produced information is retained by the governments, things
|
|
may not be much better. As in the case of Documents on Australian Defence and
|
|
Foreign Policy illustrates, copyright is one technique used to keep
|
|
information away from the public.
|
|
|
|
The idea behind patents is that the fundamentals of an invention are made
|
|
public while the inventor for a limited time has the exclusive right to make,
|
|
use or sell the invention. But there are quite a few cases in which patents
|
|
have been used to suppress innovation (Dunford 1987). Companies may take out
|
|
a patent, or buy someone else's patent, in order to inhibit others from
|
|
applying the ideas. For example, from its beginning in 1875, the US company
|
|
AT&T collected patents in order to ensure its monopoly on telephones. It
|
|
slowed down the introduction of radio for some 20 years. In a similar
|
|
fashion, General Electric used control of patents to retard the introduction
|
|
of fluorescent lights, which were a threat to its market of incandescent
|
|
lights. Trade secrets are another way to suppress technological development.
|
|
Trade secrets are protected by law but, unlike patents, do not have to be
|
|
published openly.
|
|
|
|
One of the newest areas to be classified as intellectual property is
|
|
biological information. US courts have ruled that genetic sequences can be
|
|
patented, even when the sequences are found "in nature," so long as some
|
|
artificial means are involved in isolating them. This has led companies to
|
|
race to take out patents on numerous genetic codes. In some cases, patents
|
|
have been granted covering all transgenic forms of an entire species, such as
|
|
soybeans or cotton (Mestel 1994). One consequence is a severe inhibition on
|
|
research by non-patent holders. Another consequence is that transnational
|
|
corporations are patenting genetic materials found in Third World plants and
|
|
animals, so that some Third World peoples actually have to pay to use seeds
|
|
and other genetic materials that have been freely available to them for
|
|
centuries (Shiva and Holla-Bhar 1993).
|
|
|
|
More generally, intellectual property is one more way for rich countries to
|
|
extract wealth from poor countries. Given the enormous exploitation of poor
|
|
peoples built into the world trade system, it would only seem fair for ideas
|
|
produced in rich countries to be provided at no cost to poor countries. Yet
|
|
in the GATT negotiations, representatives of rich countries, especially the
|
|
US, have insisted on strengthening intellectual property rights. Surely there
|
|
is no better indication that intellectual property is primarily of value to
|
|
those who are already powerful and wealthy (Drahos 1995; Patel 1989).
|
|
|
|
The potential financial returns from intellectual property are said to
|
|
provide an incentive for individuals to create. In practice, though, most
|
|
creators do not actually gain much benefit from intellectual property.
|
|
Independent inventors are frequently ignored or exploited (Lancaster 1992).
|
|
When employees of corporations and governments have an idea worth protecting,
|
|
it is usually copyrighted or patented by the organisation, not the employee.
|
|
Since intellectual property can be sold, it is usually the rich and powerful
|
|
who benefit. The rich and powerful, it should be noted, seldom contribute
|
|
much intellectual labour to the creation of new ideas.
|
|
|
|
These problems -- privatisation of government information, suppression of
|
|
patents, ownership of genetic information and information not owned by the
|
|
true creator -- are symptoms of a deeper problem with the whole idea of
|
|
intellectual property. Unlike goods, there are no physical obstacles to
|
|
providing an abundance of ideas. (Indeed, the bigger problem may be an
|
|
oversupply of ideas.) Intellectual property is an attempt to create an
|
|
artificial scarcity in order to give rewards to a few at the expense of the
|
|
many. Intellectual property aggravates inequality. It fosters competitiveness
|
|
over information and ideas, whereas cooperation makes much more sense.
|
|
|
|
CRITIQUE OF STANDARD JUSTIFICATIONS
|
|
|
|
Edwin C. Hettinger (1989) has provided an insightful critique of the main
|
|
arguments used to justify intellectual property, so it is worthwhile
|
|
summarising his analysis. (See also Ricketson 1992). Hettinger begins by
|
|
noting the obvious argument against intellectual property, namely that
|
|
sharing intellectual objects still allows the original possessor to use them.
|
|
Therefore, the burden of proof should lie on those who argue for intellectual
|
|
property.
|
|
|
|
The first argument for intellectual property is that people are entitled to
|
|
the results of their labour. Hettinger's response is that not all the value
|
|
of intellectual products is due to labour. Nor is the value of intellectual
|
|
products due to the work of a single labourer, or any small group.
|
|
Intellectual products are social products.
|
|
|
|
Suppose you have written an essay or made an invention. Your intellectual
|
|
work does not exist in a social vacuum. It would not have been possible
|
|
without lots of earlier work -- both intellectual and nonintellectual -- by
|
|
many other people. This includes your teachers and parents. It includes the
|
|
earlier authors and inventors who have provided the foundation for your
|
|
contribution. It also includes the many people who have discussed and used
|
|
ideas and techniques, at both theoretical and practical levels, and provided
|
|
a cultural foundation for your contribution. It includes the people who have
|
|
built printing presses, laid telephone cables, built roads and buildings and
|
|
in many other ways have contributed to the "construction" of society. Many
|
|
other people could be mentioned. The point is that any piece of intellectual
|
|
work is always built on and inconceivable without the prior work of numerous
|
|
people.
|
|
|
|
Hettinger points out that the earlier contributors to the development of
|
|
ideas are not present. Today's contributor therefore cannot validly claim
|
|
full credit.
|
|
|
|
Is the market value of a piece of an intellectual product a reasonable
|
|
indicator of a person's contribution? Certainly not. As noted by Hettinger
|
|
and as will be discussed in the next section, markets only work once property
|
|
rights have been established, so it is circular to argue that the market can
|
|
be used to measure intellectual contributions. Hettinger summarises this
|
|
point in this fashion: "The notion that a laborer is naturally entitled as a
|
|
matter of right to receive the market value of her product is a myth. To what
|
|
extent individual laborers should be allowed to receive the market value of
|
|
their products is a question of social policy." (p. 39).
|
|
|
|
A related argument is that people have a right to possess and personally use
|
|
what they develop. Hettinger's response is that this doesn't show that they
|
|
deserve market values, nor that they should have a right to prevent others
|
|
from using the invention.
|
|
|
|
A second major argument for intellectual property is that people *deserve*
|
|
property rights because of their labour. This brings up the general issue of
|
|
what people deserve, a topic that has been analysed by philosophers. Their
|
|
usual conclusions go against what many people think is "common sense."
|
|
Hettinger says that a fitting reward for labour should be proportionate to
|
|
the person's effort, the risk taken and moral considerations. This sounds all
|
|
right -- but it is not proportionate to the value of the results of the
|
|
labour, whether assessed through markets or by other criteria. This is
|
|
because the value of intellectual work is affected by things not controlled
|
|
by the worker, including luck and natural talent. Hettinger says "A person
|
|
who is born with extraordinary natural talents, or who is extremely lucky,
|
|
*deserves* nothing on the basis of these characteristics" (p. 42).
|
|
|
|
A musical genius like Mozart may make enormous contributions to society. But
|
|
being born with enormous musical talents does not provide a justification for
|
|
owning rights to musical compositions or performances. Likewise, the labour
|
|
of developing a toy like Teenage Mutant Ninja Turtles that becomes incredibly
|
|
popular does not provide a justification for owning rights to all possible
|
|
uses of turtle symbols.
|
|
|
|
What about a situation where one person works hard at a task and a second
|
|
person with equal talent works less hard? Doesn't the first worker deserve
|
|
more reward? Perhaps so, but it is not obvious that property rights provide a
|
|
suitable mechanism for allocating rewards, especially since the market
|
|
disproportionately rewards the person who successfully claims property rights
|
|
for a discovery.
|
|
|
|
A third argument for intellectual property is that private property is a
|
|
means for promoting privacy and a means for personal autonomy. Hettinger
|
|
responds that privacy is protected by not revealing information, not by
|
|
owning it. Trade secrets cannot be defended on the grounds of privacy,
|
|
because corporations are not individuals. As for personal autonomy,
|
|
copyrights and patents aren't required for this.
|
|
|
|
A fourth argument is that rights in intellectual property are needed to
|
|
promote the creation of more ideas. Hettinger thinks that this is the only
|
|
argument for intellectual property that has a possibility of standing up to
|
|
critique. He is still somewhat sceptical, though. He notes that the whole
|
|
argument is built on a contradiction, namely that in order to promote the
|
|
development of ideas, it is necessary to reduce the freedom with which people
|
|
can use them.
|
|
|
|
This argument for intellectual property cannot be resolved without further
|
|
investigation. Hettinger says that there needs to be an investigation of how
|
|
long patents and copyrights should be granted, to determine an optimum period
|
|
for promoting intellectual work. It should be noted that although the scale
|
|
and pace of intellectual work has increased over the past few centuries, the
|
|
length of protection of intellectual property has not been reduced, as might
|
|
be expected, but greatly increased. The United States got along fine without
|
|
copyright for much of the 1800s. Where once copyrights were only for a period
|
|
of a few years, they now may be for the life of the author plus 50 years. In
|
|
many countries, chemicals and pharmaceuticals were not patentable until
|
|
recently (Patel 1989). This suggests that even if intellectual property can
|
|
be justified on the basis of fostering new ideas, this is not the driving
|
|
force behind the present system of copyrights and patents.
|
|
|
|
THE MARKETPLACE OF IDEAS
|
|
|
|
The idea of intellectual property has a number of connections with the
|
|
concept of the marketplace of ideas, a metaphor that is widely used in
|
|
discussions of free speech. To delve a bit more deeply into the claim that
|
|
intellectual property promotes development of new ideas, it is therefore
|
|
helpful to scrutinise the concept of the marketplace of ideas.
|
|
|
|
The image conveyed by the marketplace of ideas is that ideas compete for
|
|
acceptance in a market. As long as the competition is fair -- which means
|
|
that all ideas and contributors are permitted access to the marketplace --
|
|
then good ideas will win out over bad ones. Why? Because people will
|
|
recognise the truth and value of good ideas. On the other hand, if the market
|
|
is constrained, for example by some groups being excluded, then certain ideas
|
|
cannot be tested and examined and successful ideas may not be the best ideas.
|
|
|
|
Logically, there is no reason why a marketplace of ideas has to be a
|
|
marketplace of *owned* ideas: intellectual property cannot be strictly
|
|
justified by the marketplace of ideas. But because the marketplace metaphor
|
|
is an economic one, there is a strong tendency to link intellectual property
|
|
with the marketplace of ideas. As will be discussed later, there is indeed a
|
|
link between these two concepts, but not in the way their defenders usually
|
|
imagine.
|
|
|
|
There are plenty of practical examples of the failure of the marketplace of
|
|
ideas. Groups that are stigmatised or that lack power seldom have their
|
|
viewpoints presented. This includes ethnic minorities, prisoners, the
|
|
unemployed, manual workers and radical critics of the status quo, among many
|
|
others (McGaffey 1972). Even when such groups organise themselves to promote
|
|
their ideas, their views are often ignored while the media focus on their
|
|
protests, as in the case of peace movement rallies and marches (Gwyn 1966).
|
|
|
|
Demonstrably, good ideas do not always win out in the marketplace of ideas.
|
|
To take one example, it can hardly be argued that the point of view of
|
|
workers is inherently less worthy than that of employers. Yet there is an
|
|
enormous imbalance in the presentation of their respective viewpoints in the
|
|
media. One result is that quite a few ideas that happen to serve the
|
|
interests of employers at the expense of workers -- such as that the reason
|
|
people don't have jobs is because they aren't trying hard enough to find them
|
|
-- are widely accepted although they are rejected by virtually all informed
|
|
analysts.
|
|
|
|
There is a simple and fundamental reason for the failure of the marketplace
|
|
of ideas: inequality, especially economic inequality (Baker 1989; Hanson
|
|
1981). Perhaps in a group of people sitting in a room discussing an issue,
|
|
there is some prospect of a measured assessment of different ideas. But if
|
|
these same people are isolated in front of their television sets, and one of
|
|
them owns the television station, it is obvious that there is little basis
|
|
for testing of ideas. The reality is that powerful and rich groups can
|
|
promote their ideas with little chance of rebuttal from those with different
|
|
perspectives. Large corporations pay for advertisements and other forms of
|
|
marketing. Governments shape media agendas as well as directly regulating the
|
|
media. The mass media themselves are powerful enterprises -- whether owned by
|
|
government or industry -- that promote their own interests as well as those
|
|
of their advertisers (Bagdikian 1993).
|
|
|
|
In circumstances where participants are approximate equals, such as
|
|
intellectual discourse among peers in an academic discipline, then the
|
|
metaphor of competition of ideas has some value. But ownership of media or
|
|
ideas is hardly a prerequisite for such discourses. It is the equality of
|
|
power that is essential. When, to take one of many possible examples,
|
|
employees in corporations lack the freedom to speak openly without penalty
|
|
(Ewing 1977), they cannot be equal participants in discourse.
|
|
|
|
Some ideas are good -- in the sense of being valuable to society -- but are
|
|
unwelcome. Some are unwelcome to powerful groups, such as that governments
|
|
and corporations commit massive crimes (Ross 1995) or that there is a massive
|
|
trade in technologies of torture and repression that needs to be stopped
|
|
(Wright 1991). Others are challenging to much of the population, such as that
|
|
imprisonment does not reduce the crime rate or that financial rewards for
|
|
good work on the job or grades for good schoolwork are counterproductive
|
|
(Kohn 1993). (Needless to say, individuals might disagree with the examples
|
|
used here. The case does not rest on the examples themselves, but on the
|
|
existence of some important cases where unwelcome but socially valuable ideas
|
|
are marginalised.) The marketplace of ideas simply does not work to treat
|
|
such unwelcome ideas with the seriousness they deserve. The mass media try to
|
|
gain audiences by pleasing them, not by confronting them with challenging
|
|
ideas (Entman 1989).
|
|
|
|
The marketplace of ideas is often used to justify free speech. The argument
|
|
is that free speech is necessary in order for the marketplace of ideas to
|
|
operate: if some types of speech are curtailed, certain ideas will not be
|
|
available on the marketplace and thus the best ideas will not succeed. This
|
|
sounds plausible. But it is possible to reject the marketplace of ideas while
|
|
still defending free speech on the grounds that it is essential to human
|
|
liberty (Baker 1989). Conversely, defending free speech does not mean
|
|
supporting the mass media (Lichtenberg 1987).
|
|
|
|
If the marketplace of ideas doesn't work, what is the solution? The usual
|
|
view is that governments should intervene to ensure that all groups have fair
|
|
access to the media (McGaffey 1972). But this approach, based on promoting
|
|
equality of opportunity, ignores the fundamental problem of economic
|
|
inequality. Even if minority groups have some limited chance to present their
|
|
views in the mass media, this can hardly compensate for the massive power of
|
|
governments and corporations to promote their views. In addition, it retains
|
|
the role of the mass media as the central mechanism for disseminating ideas.
|
|
So-called reform proposals either retain the status quo or introduce
|
|
government censorship (Ingber 1984).
|
|
|
|
Underlying the market model is the idea of self-regulation: the "free market"
|
|
is supposed to operate without outside intervention and, indeed, to operate
|
|
best when outside intervention is minimised. In practice, even markets in
|
|
goods do not operate autonomously: the state is intimately involved in even
|
|
the freest of markets (Moran and Wright 1991). In the case of the marketplace
|
|
of ideas, the state is involved both in shaping the market and in making it
|
|
possible, for example by promoting and regulating the mass media. The world's
|
|
most powerful state, the US, has been the driving force behind the
|
|
establishment of a highly protectionist system of intellectual property,
|
|
using power politics at GATT, the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade
|
|
(Drahos 1995).
|
|
|
|
Courts may use the rhetoric of the marketplace of ideas but actually
|
|
interpret the law to support the status quo (Ingber 1984). For example,
|
|
speech is treated as free until it might actually have some consequences.
|
|
Then it is curtailed when it allegedly presents a "clear and present danger,"
|
|
such as when peace activists expose information supposedly threatening to
|
|
"national security" (Gleditsch 1987). But speech without action is pointless.
|
|
True liberty requires freedom to promote one's views in practice (Baker
|
|
1989). Powerful groups have the ability to do this. Courts only intervene
|
|
when others try to do the same.
|
|
|
|
As in the case of trade generally, a property-based "free market" serves the
|
|
interests of powerful producers. In the case of ideas, this includes not only
|
|
governments and corporations but also intellectuals and professionals linked
|
|
with universities, entertainment, journalism and the arts. Against such an
|
|
array of intellectual opinion, it is very difficult for other groups, such as
|
|
manual workers, to compete (Ginsberg 1986). The marketplace of ideas is a
|
|
biased and artificial market that mostly serves to fine-tune relations
|
|
between elites and provide them with legitimacy (Ingber 1984).
|
|
|
|
The implication of this analysis is that intellectual property cannot be
|
|
justified on the basis of the marketplace of ideas. The utilitarian argument
|
|
for intellectual property is that ownership is necessary to stimulate
|
|
production of new ideas, because of the financial incentive. This financial
|
|
incentive is supposed to come from the market, whose justification is the
|
|
marketplace of ideas. If, as critics argue, the marketplace of ideas is
|
|
flawed by the presence of economic inequality and, more fundamentally, is an
|
|
artificial creation that serves powerful producers of ideas and legitimates
|
|
the role of elites, then the case for intellectual property is unfounded.
|
|
Intellectual property can only serve to aggravate the inequality on which it
|
|
is built.
|
|
|
|
|
|
THE ALTERNATIVE
|
|
|
|
The alternative to intellectual property is straightforward: intellectual
|
|
products should not be owned. That means not owned by individuals,
|
|
corporations, governments, or the community as common property. It means that
|
|
ideas are available to be used by anyone who wants to.
|
|
|
|
One example of how this might operate is language, including the words,
|
|
sounds and meaning systems with which we communicate every day. Spoken
|
|
language is free for everyone to use. To allow any group to own language
|
|
raises the spectre of George Orwell's 1984. (Actually, corporations do
|
|
control bits of language through trademarks.)
|
|
|
|
Another example is scientific knowledge. Scientists do research and then
|
|
publish their results. A large fraction of scientific knowledge is public
|
|
knowledge (Ziman 1968). There are some areas of science that are not public,
|
|
such as classified military research. It is generally argued that the most
|
|
dynamic parts of science are those with the least secrecy. Open ideas can be
|
|
examined, challenged, modified and improved. To turn scientific knowledge
|
|
into a commodity on the market, as is happening with genetic engineering
|
|
(Mackenzie et al. 1990; Weiner 1986), arguably inhibits science.
|
|
|
|
Few scientists complain that they do not own the knowledge they produce.
|
|
Indeed, they are much more likely to complain when corporations or
|
|
governments try to control dissemination of the ideas. Most scientists
|
|
receive a salary from a government, corporation or university. Their
|
|
livelihoods do not depend on royalties from published work.
|
|
|
|
University scientists have the greatest freedom. The main reasons they do
|
|
research are for the intrinsic satisfaction of investigation and discovery --
|
|
a key motivation for many of the world's great scientists -- and for
|
|
recognition by their peers. To turn scientific knowledge into intellectual
|
|
property would dampen the enthusiasm of many scientists for their work.
|
|
|
|
Neither language nor scientific knowledge are ideal; indeed, they are often
|
|
used for harmful purposes. It is difficult to imagine, though, how turning
|
|
them into property could make them better.
|
|
|
|
The case of science shows that vigorous intellectual activity is quite
|
|
possible without intellectual property, and in fact that it may be vigorous
|
|
precisely because information is not owned. But there are lots of areas that,
|
|
unlike science, have long operated with intellectual property as a fact of
|
|
life. What would happen without ownership of information? Many objections
|
|
spring to mind. Here I'll deal with a few of them.
|
|
|
|
Plagiarism is a great fear in the minds of many intellectual workers. It is
|
|
often thought that intellectual property provides a protection against
|
|
plagiarism. After all, without copyright, why couldn't someone put their name
|
|
on your essay and publish it? Actually, copyright provides very little
|
|
protection against plagiarism and is not a good way to deal with it (Stearns
|
|
1992).
|
|
|
|
Plagiarism means using the ideas of others without adequate acknowledgement.
|
|
There are several types of plagiarism. One is plagiarism of ideas: someone
|
|
takes your original idea and, using different expression, presents it as
|
|
their own. Copyright provides no protection at all against this form of
|
|
plagiarism. Another type of plagiarism is word-for-word plagiarism, where
|
|
someone takes the words you've written -- a book, an essay, a few paragraphs
|
|
or even just a sentence -- and, with or without minor modifications, presents
|
|
them as their own. This sort of plagiarism *is* covered by copyright --
|
|
assuming that you hold the copyright. In many cases, copyright is held by the
|
|
publisher, not the author. In practice, plagiarism goes on all the time, in
|
|
various ways and degrees (Broad and Wade 1982; Mallon 1989; Posner 1988), and
|
|
copyright law is hardly ever used against it. The most effective challenge to
|
|
plagiarism is not legal action but publicity. At least among authors,
|
|
plagiarism is widely condemned. To be exposed as a plagiarist is more than
|
|
sufficient motivation for most writers to take care to avoid it.
|
|
|
|
There is an even more fundamental reason why copyright provides no protection
|
|
against plagiarism: the most common sort of plagiarism is built into social
|
|
hierarchies. Government and corporate reports are released under the names of
|
|
top bureaucrats who did not write them; politicians and university presidents
|
|
give speeches written by underlings. These are examples of a pervasive
|
|
misrepresentation of authorship in which powerful figures gain credit for the
|
|
work of subordinates (Martin 1994). Copyright, if it has any effect at all,
|
|
reinforces rather than challenges this sort of institutionalised plagiarism.
|
|
|
|
What about all the writers, inventors and others who depend for their
|
|
livelihood on royalties? First, it should be mentioned that only a very few
|
|
individuals make enough money from royalties to live on. Most of the rewards
|
|
from intellectual property go to a few big companies. But the question is
|
|
still a serious one for those intellectual workers who depend on royalties
|
|
and other payments related to intellectual property.
|
|
|
|
The alternative in this case is some reorganisation of the economic system.
|
|
Intellectual workers could receive a salary, just like most scientists do.
|
|
|
|
Getting rid of intellectual property would reduce the incomes of a few highly
|
|
successful creative individuals, such as author Agatha Christie, composer
|
|
Andrew Lloyd Webber and filmmaker Steven Spielberg. Publishers could reprint
|
|
Christie's novels without permission, theatre companies could put on Webber's
|
|
operas whenever they wished and Spielberg's films could be copied and
|
|
screened anywhere. Jurassic Park T-shirts, toys and trinkets could be
|
|
produced at will. This would reduce the income of and, to some extent, the
|
|
opportunities for artistic expression by these individuals. But there would
|
|
be economic resources released: there would be more money available for other
|
|
creators. Christie, Webber and Spielberg might be just as popular without
|
|
intellectual property to channel money to them and their family enterprises.
|
|
|
|
But what about the incentive to create? Without the possibility of wealth and
|
|
fame, what would stimulate creative individuals to produce works of genius?
|
|
Actually, most creators and innovators are motivated by their own intrinsic
|
|
interest, not by rewards. There is a large body of evidence showing, contrary
|
|
to popular opinion, that rewards actually reduce the quality of work (Kohn
|
|
1993). If the goal is better and more creative work, paying creators on a
|
|
piecework basis, such as through royalties, is counterproductive.
|
|
|
|
In a society without intellectual property, creativity is likely to thrive.
|
|
Most of the problems that are imagined to occur if there is no intellectual
|
|
property -- such as the exploitation of a small publisher that renounces
|
|
copyright -- are due to economic arrangements that maintain inequality. The
|
|
soundest foundation for a society without intellectual property is greater
|
|
economic and political equality. This means not just equality of opportunity,
|
|
but equality of outcomes. This does not mean uniformity and does not mean
|
|
levelling imposed from the top: it means freedom and diversity and a
|
|
situation where people can get what they need. There is not space to deal
|
|
fully with this issue here, but suffice it to say that there are strong
|
|
social and psychological arguments in favour of equality (Baker 1987; Deutsch
|
|
1985; Ryan 1981).
|
|
|
|
STRATEGIES FOR CHANGE
|
|
|
|
Challenging intellectual property is a daunting task. It is supported by many
|
|
powerful groups: the most powerful governments and the largest corporations.
|
|
The mass media seem fully behind intellectual property, partly because media
|
|
monopolies would be undercut if information were more freely copied and
|
|
partly because the most influential journalists depend on syndication rights
|
|
for their stories. Perhaps just as important is the support for intellectual
|
|
property from many small intellectual producers, including academics and
|
|
freelance writers. Although the monetary returns to these intellectuals are
|
|
seldom significant, they have been persuaded that they both need and deserve
|
|
their small royalties. This is similar to the way that small owners of goods
|
|
and land, such as homeowners, strongly defend the system of private property,
|
|
whose main beneficiaries are the very wealthy who own vast enterprises based
|
|
on many other people's labour.
|
|
|
|
Another problem in developing strategies is that it makes little sense to
|
|
challenge intellectual property in isolation. If we simply imagine
|
|
intellectual property being abolished but the rest of the economic system
|
|
unchanged, then many objections can be made. Challenging intellectual
|
|
property must involve the development of methods to support today's small
|
|
intellectual producers.
|
|
|
|
An obvious way to challenge intellectual property is simply to defy it by
|
|
reproducing protected works. From the point of view of intellectual property,
|
|
this is called "piracy." (This is a revealing term, considering that no such
|
|
language is used when, for example, a boss takes credit for a subordinate's
|
|
work or when a Third World intellectual is recruited to a First World
|
|
position (Verzola 1993).) This happens every day when people photocopy
|
|
copyrighted articles, tape copyrighted music, or duplicate copyrighted
|
|
software. It is precisely because illegal copying is so easy and so common
|
|
that big governments and corporations have mounted offensives to promote
|
|
intellectual property rights.
|
|
|
|
Unfortunately, illegal copying is not a very good strategy against
|
|
intellectual property, any more than stealing goods is a way to challenge
|
|
ownership of physical property. Theft of any sort implicitly accepts the
|
|
existing system of ownership. By trying to hide the copying and avoiding
|
|
penalties, the copiers appear to accept the legitimacy of the system.
|
|
|
|
Far more powerful than illicit copying is open refusal to cooperate with
|
|
intellectual property. The methods of nonviolent action can be used here,
|
|
including noncooperation, boycotts and setting up alternative institutions
|
|
(Sharp 1973). By being open about the challenge, there is a much greater
|
|
chance of focussing attention on the issues at stake and creating a dialogue.
|
|
By being principled in opposition, and being willing to accept penalties that
|
|
might be applied to civil disobedience to laws on intellectual property,
|
|
there is a much greater chance of winning over third parties (Herngren 1993).
|
|
If harsh penalties are applied to those who challenge intellectual property,
|
|
this is likely to produce a backlash of sympathy. If mass civil disobedience
|
|
to intellectual property laws were to occur, it would be impossible to stop.
|
|
|
|
Something like that is already occurring. Because photocopying of copyrighted
|
|
works is so common, there is seldom any attempt to enforce the law against
|
|
small violators -- to do so would alienate too many people. Copyright
|
|
authorities therefore seek other means of collecting revenues from
|
|
intellectual property, such as payments by institutions based on library
|
|
copies. There would be a much greater impact from a principled challenge to
|
|
intellectual property, especially if some prominent people took part.
|
|
|
|
Another important strategy is the promotion of non-owned information. A good
|
|
example is public domain software, which is computer software that is made
|
|
available free to anyone who wants it. The developers of "freeware" gain
|
|
satisfaction out of their intellectual work and out of providing a service to
|
|
other people.
|
|
|
|
A suitable alternative to copyright is shareright. A piece of freeware might
|
|
be accompanied by the notice, "You may reproduce this material if your
|
|
recipients may also reproduce it." This encourages copiers but refuses any of
|
|
them copyright.
|
|
|
|
Intellectual property gives the appearance of stopping unfair appropriation
|
|
of ideas although, as argued here, the reality is quite different. If
|
|
intellectual property is to be challenged, people need to be reassured that
|
|
misappropriation of ideas will not become a big problem. Therefore it is
|
|
important to develop principles to deal with credit for intellectual work --
|
|
even if credit is not rewarded financially. This would include guidelines for
|
|
not misrepresenting another person's work. So-called moral rights to be
|
|
recognised as the author of a work are relevant here.
|
|
|
|
More fundamentally, it needs to be recognised that intellectual work is
|
|
inevitably a collective process. No one has totally original ideas: ideas are
|
|
always built on the earlier contributions of others. Furthermore,
|
|
contributions to culture -- which makes ideas possible -- are not just
|
|
intellectual but also practical and material, including the rearing of
|
|
families and construction of buildings. Intellectual property is theft,
|
|
sometimes in part from an individual creator but always from society as a
|
|
whole.
|
|
|
|
In a more cooperative society, credit for ideas would not be such a
|
|
contentious matter. Today, there are vicious disputes between scientists over
|
|
who should gain credit for a discovery. This is because scientists' careers
|
|
and, more importantly, their reputations, depend on credit for ideas. In a
|
|
society with less hierarchy and greater equality, intrinsic motivation and
|
|
satisfaction would be the main returns from contributing to intellectual
|
|
developments. This is quite compatible with everything that is known about
|
|
human nature (Kohn 1990). The system of ownership encourages groups to put
|
|
special interests above general interests. Sharing information is undoubtedly
|
|
the most efficient way to allocate productive resources (Hahnel 1993). The
|
|
less there is to gain from credit for ideas, the more likely people are to
|
|
share ideas rather than worry about who deserves credit for them.
|
|
|
|
Finally, it should not be imagined that getting rid of intellectual property
|
|
is a solution to the link between information and inequality. Even without
|
|
intellectual property, information can be controlled by powerful groups.
|
|
National security elites use secrecy and spying to protect their operations.
|
|
Professions use specialised training, jargon and esoteric theories, as well
|
|
as licensing by the state, to make their work inaccessible to outsiders.
|
|
Corporations protect many of their ideas through secrecy rather than patents.
|
|
The law of defamation is used to punish free speech, especially criticisms of
|
|
powerful individuals. Intellectual property is only one technique of many by
|
|
which powerful groups control information in order to protect and expand
|
|
their positions and wealth. Challenging intellectual property is only one
|
|
part, though an important part, of challenging inequality.
|
|
|
|
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS: I thank Steve Fuller, Brian Rappert, Wendy Varney, Ian
|
|
Watson and a hostile referee for The Information Society for providing
|
|
helpful comments on a draft of this paper and Mary Cawte for tracking down
|
|
some information. Numerous other people, through their writings,
|
|
conversations and other activities, directly or indirectly helped make this
|
|
work possible.
|
|
|
|
REFERENCES
|
|
|
|
Bagdikian, Ben. 1993. The Media Monopoly. Boston: Beacon Press, 4th edition.
|
|
|
|
Baker, C. Edwin. 1989. Human Liberty and Freedom of Speech. New York: Oxford
|
|
University Press.
|
|
|
|
Baker, John. 1987. Arguing for Equality. London: Verso.
|
|
|
|
Broad, William, and Nicholas Wade. 1982. Betrayers of the Truth: Fraud and
|
|
Deceit in the Halls of Science. New York: Simon and Schuster.
|
|
|
|
Deutsch, Morton. 1985. Distributive Justice: A Social-psychological
|
|
Perspective. New Haven: Yale University Press.
|
|
|
|
Drahos, Peter. June 1995. "Global property rights in information: the story
|
|
of TRIPS at the GATT." Prometheus 13(1).
|
|
|
|
Dunford, Richard. 1987. "The suppression of technology as a strategy for
|
|
controlling resource dependence." Administrative Science Quarterly
|
|
32:512-525.
|
|
|
|
Entman, Robert M. 1989. Democracy without Citizens: Media and the Decay of
|
|
American Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
|
|
|
|
Ewing, David W. 1977. Freedom inside the Organization: Bringing Civil
|
|
Liberties to the Workplace. New York: Dutton.
|
|
|
|
Ginsberg, Benjamin. 1986. The Captive Public: How Mass Media Promotes State
|
|
Power. New York: Basic Books.
|
|
|
|
Gleditsch, Nils Petter. April 1987. "National security and freedom of
|
|
expression: the Scandinavian legal battles." Media Law & Practice 8:2-5.
|
|
|
|
Gwyn, Robert J. 1966. "Political dissent and the free market of ideas: an
|
|
eight-nation study." Gazette: International Journal of Mass Communication
|
|
Studies 12:187-200.
|
|
|
|
Hahnel, Robin. April 1993. "Cooperacion internacional, si! NAFTA, no!" Z
|
|
Magazine 6(4):47-52.
|
|
|
|
Hanson, Jim. 1981. "The political economy of free speech: a Marxist
|
|
critique." Humanity and Society 5(4):370-382.
|
|
|
|
Herngren, Per. 1993. Path of Resistance: The Practice of Civil Disobedience.
|
|
Philadelphia: New Society Publishers.
|
|
|
|
Hettinger, Edwin C. Winter 1989. "Justifying intellectual property."
|
|
Philosophy and Public Affairs 18(1):31-52.
|
|
|
|
Ingber, Stanley. February 1984. "The marketplace of ideas: a legitimizing
|
|
myth." Duke Law Journal 1984(1):1-91.
|
|
|
|
Kohn, Alfie. 1990. The Brighter Side of Human Nature: Altruism and Empathy in
|
|
Everyday Life. New York: Basic Books.
|
|
|
|
Kohn, Alfie. 1993. Punished by Rewards: The Trouble with Gold Stars,
|
|
Incentive Plans, A's, Praise, and other Bribes. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
|
|
|
|
Lancaster, Don. Winter 1992. "The case against patents." Whole Earth Review
|
|
77:86-87.
|
|
|
|
Lichtenberg, Judith. Fall 1987. "Foundations and limits of freedom of the
|
|
press." Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(4):329-355.
|
|
|
|
Mackenzie, Michael, Peter Keating, and Albert Cambrosio. Winter 1990.
|
|
"Patents and free scientific information in biotechnology: making monoclonal
|
|
antibodies proprietary." Science, Technology, & Human Values 15(1):65-83.
|
|
|
|
Mallon, Thomas. 1989. Stolen Words: Forays into the Origins and Ravages of
|
|
Plagiarism. New York: Ticknor and Fields.
|
|
|
|
Martin, Brian. Fall 1994. "Plagiarism: a misplaced emphasis." Journal of
|
|
Information Ethics 3(2):36-47.
|
|
|
|
McGaffey, Ruth. March 1972. "A critical look at the 'marketplace of ideas'."
|
|
Speech Teacher 21(2):115-122.
|
|
|
|
Mestel, Rosie. 19 February 1994. "Rich pickings for cotton's pioneers." New
|
|
Scientist 141:13-14,
|
|
|
|
Moran, Michael, and Maurice Wright (eds.). 1991. The Market and the State:
|
|
Studies in Interdependence. London: Macmillan.
|
|
|
|
Munster, George. 1982. Secrets of State: A Detailed Assessment of the Book
|
|
They Banned. Australia: Walsh & Munster.
|
|
|
|
Nelkin, Dorothy. 1984. Science as Intellectual Property: Who Controls
|
|
Research? New York: Macmillan.
|
|
|
|
Patel, Surendra J. 6 May 1989. "Intellectual property rights in the Uruguay
|
|
Round: a disaster for the South?" Economic and Political Weekly
|
|
24(18):978-993.
|
|
|
|
Posner, Ari. 18 April 1988. "The culture of plagiarism." The New
|
|
Republic:19-24.
|
|
|
|
Ricketson, Sam. June 1992. "New wine into old bottles: technological change
|
|
and intellectual property rights." Prometheus 10(1):53-82.
|
|
|
|
Ross, Jeffrey Ian (ed.). 1995. Controlling State Crime: An Introduction. New
|
|
York: Garland.
|
|
|
|
Ryan, William. 1981. Equality. New York: Pantheon.
|
|
|
|
Sharp, Gene. 1973. The Politics of Nonviolent Action. Boston: Porter Sargent.
|
|
|
|
Shiva, Vandana, and Radha Holla-Bhar. 1993. "Intellectual piracy and the neem
|
|
tree." Ecologist 23(6):223-227.
|
|
|
|
Stearns, Laurie. March 1992. "Copy wrong: plagiarism, process, property, and
|
|
the law." California Law Review 80(2):513-553.
|
|
|
|
Verzola, Roberto. January-February 1993. "The 'piracy' of intellectuals and
|
|
intellectual property." Third World Resurgence 29/30:57-58.
|
|
|
|
Weiner, Charles. February-March 1986. "Universities, professors, and patents:
|
|
a continuing controversy." Technology Review:33-43.
|
|
|
|
Wright, Steve. July-December 1991. "The new technologies of political
|
|
repression: a case for arms control?" Philosophy and Social Action
|
|
17(3-4):31-62.
|
|
|
|
Ziman, John. 1968. Public Knowledge: An Essay concerning the Social
|
|
Dimensions of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
|
|
|
|
------------------------------
|
|
|
|
Date: Sun, 19 Apr 1995 22:51:01 CDT
|
|
From: CuD Moderators <cudigest@sun.soci.niu.edu>
|
|
Subject: File 2--Cu Digest Header Info (unchanged since 19 Apr, 1995)
|
|
|
|
Cu-Digest is a weekly electronic journal/newsletter. Subscriptions are
|
|
available at no cost electronically.
|
|
|
|
CuD is available as a Usenet newsgroup: comp.society.cu-digest
|
|
|
|
Or, to subscribe, send a one-line message: SUB CUDIGEST your name
|
|
Send it to LISTSERV@VMD.CSO.UIUC.EDU
|
|
The editors may be contacted by voice (815-753-0303), fax (815-753-6302)
|
|
or U.S. mail at: Jim Thomas, Department of Sociology, NIU, DeKalb, IL
|
|
60115, USA.
|
|
|
|
To UNSUB, send a one-line message: UNSUB CUDIGEST
|
|
Send it to LISTSERV@VMD.CSO.UIUC.EDU
|
|
(NOTE: The address you unsub must correspond to your From: line)
|
|
|
|
Issues of CuD can also be found in the Usenet comp.society.cu-digest
|
|
news group; on CompuServe in DL0 and DL4 of the IBMBBS SIG, DL1 of
|
|
LAWSIG, and DL1 of TELECOM; on GEnie in the PF*NPC RT
|
|
libraries and in the VIRUS/SECURITY library; from America Online in
|
|
the PC Telecom forum under "computing newsletters;"
|
|
On Delphi in the General Discussion database of the Internet SIG;
|
|
on RIPCO BBS (312) 528-5020 (and via Ripco on internet);
|
|
and on Rune Stone BBS (IIRGWHQ) (203) 832-8441.
|
|
CuD is also available via Fidonet File Request from
|
|
1:11/70; unlisted nodes and points welcome.
|
|
|
|
EUROPE: In BELGIUM: Virtual Access BBS: +32-69-844-019 (ringdown)
|
|
Brussels: STRATOMIC BBS +32-2-5383119 2:291/759@fidonet.org
|
|
In ITALY: Bits against the Empire BBS: +39-464-435189
|
|
In LUXEMBOURG: ComNet BBS: +352-466893
|
|
|
|
UNITED STATES: etext.archive.umich.edu (192.131.22.8) in /pub/CuD/
|
|
ftp.eff.org (192.88.144.4) in /pub/Publications/CuD/
|
|
aql.gatech.edu (128.61.10.53) in /pub/eff/cud/
|
|
world.std.com in /src/wuarchive/doc/EFF/Publications/CuD/
|
|
wuarchive.wustl.edu in /doc/EFF/Publications/CuD/
|
|
EUROPE: nic.funet.fi in pub/doc/cud/ (Finland)
|
|
ftp.warwick.ac.uk in pub/cud/ (United Kingdom)
|
|
|
|
JAPAN: ftp://www.rcac.tdi.co.jp/pub/mirror/CuD
|
|
|
|
The most recent issues of CuD can be obtained from the
|
|
Cu Digest WWW site at:
|
|
URL: http://www.soci.niu.edu:80/~cudigest/
|
|
|
|
COMPUTER UNDERGROUND DIGEST is an open forum dedicated to sharing
|
|
information among computerists and to the presentation and debate of
|
|
diverse views. CuD material may be reprinted for non-profit as long
|
|
as the source is cited. Authors hold a presumptive copyright, and
|
|
they should be contacted for reprint permission. It is assumed that
|
|
non-personal mail to the moderators may be reprinted unless otherwise
|
|
specified. Readers are encouraged to submit reasoned articles
|
|
relating to computer culture and communication. Articles are
|
|
preferred to short responses. Please avoid quoting previous posts
|
|
unless absolutely necessary.
|
|
|
|
DISCLAIMER: The views represented herein do not necessarily represent
|
|
the views of the moderators. Digest contributors assume all
|
|
responsibility for ensuring that articles submitted do not
|
|
violate copyright protections.
|
|
|
|
------------------------------
|
|
|
|
End of Computer Underground Digest #7.51
|
|
************************************
|
|
|