1569 lines
124 KiB
Plaintext
1569 lines
124 KiB
Plaintext
|
The Embarrassing Second Amendment
|
||
|
by
|
||
|
Sanford Levinson
|
||
|
|
||
|
From The Yale Law Journal, Volume 99
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
- FORWARD -
|
||
|
|
||
|
I am a Charles Tilford McCormick Professor of Law at the
|
||
|
University of Texas Law School. This essay was initially prepared
|
||
|
for delivery at a symposium on Interpretation and the Bill of
|
||
|
Rights at Williams College on November 4, 1988. I am grateful for
|
||
|
the thought and effort put into that conference by its organizer,
|
||
|
Professor Mark Taylor. It was he who arranged for Wendy Brown,
|
||
|
then a member of the Williams Department of Political Science, to
|
||
|
deliver the excellent response that can be found following this
|
||
|
article. A timely letter from Linda Kerber contributed to the
|
||
|
reorganization of this article. Two long-distance friends and
|
||
|
colleagues, Akhil Reed Amar and Stephen Siegel, contributed
|
||
|
special and deeply appreciated insights and encouragement.
|
||
|
Finally, as always, I took full advantage of several of my
|
||
|
University of Texas Law School colleagues, including Jack Balkin,
|
||
|
Douglas Laycock, and Lucas Powe.
|
||
|
|
||
|
I should note that I wrote (and titled) this article before
|
||
|
reading Nelson Lund's The Second Amendment, Political Liberty,
|
||
|
and the Right to Self-Preservation, 39 Ala. L. REV. 103 (1987),
|
||
|
which begins, "The Second Amendment to the United States
|
||
|
Constitution has become the most embarrassing provision of the
|
||
|
Bill of Rights." I did hear Lund deliver a talk on the Second
|
||
|
Amendment at the University of Texas Law School during the winter
|
||
|
of 1987, which may have penetrated my consciousness more than I
|
||
|
realized while drafting the article.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Sanford Levinson
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
One of the best known pieces of American popular art in this
|
||
|
century is the New Yorker cover by Saul Steinberg presenting a
|
||
|
map of the United States as seen by a New Yorker. As most readers
|
||
|
can no doubt recall, Manhattan dominates the map; everything west
|
||
|
of the Hudson is more or less collapsed together and minimally
|
||
|
displayed to the viewer. Steinberg's great cover depends for its
|
||
|
force on the reality of what social psychologists call "cognitive
|
||
|
maps." If one asks inhabitants ostensibly of the same cities to
|
||
|
draw maps of that city, one will quickly discover that the images
|
||
|
carried around in people's minds will vary by race, social class,
|
||
|
and the like. What is true of maps of places--that they differ
|
||
|
according to the perspectives of the mapmakers--is certainly true
|
||
|
of all conceptual maps.
|
||
|
|
||
|
To continue the map analogy, consider in this context the
|
||
|
Bill of Rights: Is there an agreed upon "projection" of the
|
||
|
concept? Is there even a canonical text of the Bill of Rights?
|
||
|
Does it include the first eight, nine, or ten Amendments to the
|
||
|
Constitution?[1] Imagine two individuals who are asked to draw a
|
||
|
"map" of the Bill of Rights. One is a (stereo-) typical member of
|
||
|
the American Civil Liberties Union (of which I am a cardcarrying
|
||
|
member); the other is an equally (stereo-) typical member of the
|
||
|
"New Right." The first, I suggest, would feature the First
|
||
|
Amendment [2] as Main Street, dominating the map, though more,
|
||
|
one suspects, in its role as protector of speech and prohibitor
|
||
|
of established religion than as guardian of the rights of
|
||
|
religious believers. The other principal avenues would be the
|
||
|
criminal procedure aspects of the Constitution drawn from the
|
||
|
Fourth, [3] Fifth, [4] Sixth, [5] and Eighth [6] Amendments. Also
|
||
|
depicted prominently would be the Ninth Amendment, [7] although
|
||
|
perhaps as in the process of construction. I am confident that
|
||
|
the ACLU map would exclude any display of the just compensation
|
||
|
clause of the Fifth Amendment [8] or of the Tenth Amendment.[9]
|
||
|
|
||
|
The second map, drawn by the New Rightist, would highlight
|
||
|
the free exercise clause of the First Amendment, [10] the just
|
||
|
compensation clause of the Fifth Amendment, [11] and the Tenth
|
||
|
Amendment.[12] Perhaps the most notable difference between the
|
||
|
two maps, though, would be in regard to the Second Amendment: "A
|
||
|
well regulated Militia being necessary to the security of a free
|
||
|
State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms shall not be
|
||
|
infringed." What would be at most only a blind alley for the ACLU
|
||
|
mapmaker would, I am confident, be a major boulevard in the map
|
||
|
drawn by the New Right adherent. It is this last anomaly that I
|
||
|
want to explore in this essay.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
I. THE POLITICS OF INTERPRETING THE SECOND AMENDMENT
|
||
|
|
||
|
To put it mildly, the Second Amendment is not at the
|
||
|
forefront of constitutional discussion, at least as registered in
|
||
|
what the academy regards as the venues for such discussion--law
|
||
|
reviews, [13] casebooks, [14] and other scholarly legal
|
||
|
publications. As Professor LaRue has recently written, "the
|
||
|
second amendment is not taken seriously by most scholars."[15]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Both Laurence Tribe [16] and the Illinois team of Nowak,
|
||
|
Rotunda, and Young [17] at least acknowledge the existence of the
|
||
|
Second Amendment in their respective treatises on constitutional
|
||
|
law, perhaps because the treatise genre demands more encyclopedic
|
||
|
coverage than does the casebook. Neither, however, pays it the
|
||
|
compliment of extended analysis. Both marginalize the Amendment
|
||
|
by relegating it to footnotes; it becomes what a
|
||
|
deconstructionist might call a "supplement" to the ostensibly
|
||
|
"real" Constitution that is privileged by discussion in the
|
||
|
text.[18] Professor Tribe's footnote appears as part of a general
|
||
|
discussion of congressional power. He asserts that the history of
|
||
|
the Amendment "indicate[s] that the central concern of [its]
|
||
|
framers was to prevent such federal interferences with the state
|
||
|
militia as would permit the establishment of a standing national
|
||
|
army and the consequent destruction of local autonomy."[19] He
|
||
|
does note, however, that "the debates surrounding congressional
|
||
|
approval of the second amendment do contain references to
|
||
|
individual self-protection as well as to states' rights," but he
|
||
|
argues that the presence of the preamble to the Amendment, as
|
||
|
well as the qualifying phrase "'well regulated' makes any
|
||
|
invocation of the amendment as a restriction on state or local
|
||
|
gun control measures extremely problematic."[20] Nowak, Rotunda,
|
||
|
and Young mention the Amendment in the context of the
|
||
|
incorporation controversy, though they discuss its meaning at
|
||
|
slightly greater length.[21] They state that "[t]he Supreme Court
|
||
|
has not determined, at least not with any clarity, whether the
|
||
|
amendment protects only a right of state governments against
|
||
|
federal interference with state militia and police forces . . .
|
||
|
or a right of individuals against the federal and state
|
||
|
government[s]."[22]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Clearly the Second Amendment is not the only ignored patch
|
||
|
of text in our constitutional conversations. One will find
|
||
|
extraordinarily little discussion about another one of the
|
||
|
initial Bill of Rights, the Third Amendment: "No Soldier shall,
|
||
|
in time of peace be quartered in any house, without the consent
|
||
|
of the Owner, nor in time of war, but in a manner to be
|
||
|
prescribed by law." Nor does one hear much about letters of
|
||
|
marque and reprisal [23] or the granting of titles of
|
||
|
nobility.[24] There are, however, some differences that are worth
|
||
|
noting.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The Third Amendment, to take the easiest case, is ignored
|
||
|
because it is in fact of no current importance whatsoever
|
||
|
(although it did, for obvious reasons, have importance at the
|
||
|
time of the founding). It has never, for a single instant, been
|
||
|
viewed by any body of modern lawyers or groups of laity as highly
|
||
|
relevant to their legal or political concerns. For this reason,
|
||
|
there is almost no case law on the Amendment.[25] I suspect that
|
||
|
few among even the highly sophisticated readers of this Journal
|
||
|
can summon up the Amendment without the aid of the text.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The Second Amendment, though, is radically different from
|
||
|
these other pieces of constitutional text just mentioned, which
|
||
|
all share the attribute of being basically irrelevant to any
|
||
|
ongoing political struggles. To grasp the difference, one might
|
||
|
simply begin by noting that it is not at all unusual for the
|
||
|
Second Amendment to show up in letters to the editors of
|
||
|
newspapers and magazines.[26] That judges and academic lawyers,
|
||
|
including the ones who write casebooks, ignore it is most
|
||
|
certainly not evidence for the proposition that no one cares
|
||
|
about it. The National Rifle Association, to name the most
|
||
|
obvious example, cares deeply about the Amendment, and an
|
||
|
apparently serious Senator of the United States averred that the
|
||
|
right to keep and bear arms is the "right most valued by free
|
||
|
men."[27] Campaigns for Congress in both political parties, and
|
||
|
even presidential campaigns, may turn on the apparent commitment
|
||
|
of the candidates to a particular view of the Second Amendment.
|
||
|
This reality of the political process reflects the fact that
|
||
|
millions of Americans, even if (or perhaps especially if) they
|
||
|
are not academics, can quote the Amendment and would disdain any
|
||
|
presentation of the Bill of Rights that did not give it a place
|
||
|
of pride.
|
||
|
|
||
|
I cannot help but suspect that the best explanation for the
|
||
|
absence of the Second Amendment from the legal consciousness of
|
||
|
the elite bar, including that component found in the legal
|
||
|
academy, [28] is derived from a mixture of sheer opposition to
|
||
|
the idea of private ownership of guns and the perhaps
|
||
|
subconscious fear that altogether plausible, perhaps even
|
||
|
"winning," interpretations of the Second Amendment would present
|
||
|
real hurdles to those of us supporting prohibitory regulation.
|
||
|
Thus the title of this essay--The Embarrassing Second Amendment--
|
||
|
for I want to suggest that the Amendment may be profoundly
|
||
|
embarrassing to many who both support such regulation and view
|
||
|
themselves as committed to zealous adherence to the Bill of
|
||
|
Rights (such as most members of the ACLU). Indeed, one sometimes
|
||
|
discovers members of the NRA who are equally committed members of
|
||
|
the ACLU, differing with the latter only on the issue of the
|
||
|
Second Amendment but otherwise genuinely sharing the libertarian
|
||
|
viewpoint of the ACLU.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is not my style to offer "correct" or "incorrect"
|
||
|
interpretations of the Constitution.[29] My major interest is in
|
||
|
delineating the rhetorical structures of American constitutional
|
||
|
argument and elaborating what is sometimes called the "politics
|
||
|
of interpretation," that is, the factors that explain why one or
|
||
|
another approach will appeal to certain analysts at certain
|
||
|
times, while other analysts, or times, will favor quite different
|
||
|
approaches. Thus my general tendency to regard as wholly
|
||
|
untenable any approach to the Constitution that describes itself
|
||
|
as obviously correct and condemns its opposition as simply wrong
|
||
|
holds for the Second Amendment as well. In some contexts, this
|
||
|
would lead me to label as tendentious the certainty of NRA
|
||
|
advocates that the Amendment means precisely what they assert it
|
||
|
does. In this particular context--i.e., the pages of a journal
|
||
|
whose audience is much more likely to be drawn from an elite,
|
||
|
liberal portion of the public--I will instead be suggesting that
|
||
|
the skepticism should run in the other direction. That is, we
|
||
|
might consider the possibility that "our" views of the Amendment,
|
||
|
perhaps best reflected in Professor Tribe's offhand treatment of
|
||
|
it, might themselves be equally deserving of the "tendentious"
|
||
|
label.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
II. THE RHETORICAL STRUCTURES OF THE RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS
|
||
|
|
||
|
My colleague Philip Bobbitt has, in his book Constitutional
|
||
|
Fate, [30] spelled out six approaches--or "modalities," as he
|
||
|
terms them--of constitutional argument. These approaches, he
|
||
|
argues, comprise what might be termed our legal grammar. They are
|
||
|
the rhetorical structures within which "law-talk" as a
|
||
|
recognizable form of conversation is carried on. The six are as
|
||
|
follows:
|
||
|
|
||
|
1) textual argument--appeals to the unadorned
|
||
|
language of the text;[31]
|
||
|
|
||
|
2) historical argument--appeals to the historical
|
||
|
background of the provision being considered,
|
||
|
whether the history considered be general, such as
|
||
|
background but clearly crucial events (such as the
|
||
|
American Revolution), or specific appeals to the
|
||
|
so-called intentions of the framers;[32]
|
||
|
|
||
|
3) structural argument--analyses inferred from the
|
||
|
particular structures established by the
|
||
|
Constitution, including the tripartite division of
|
||
|
the national government; the separate existence of
|
||
|
both state and nation as political entities; and
|
||
|
the structured role of citizens within the
|
||
|
political order;[33]
|
||
|
|
||
|
4) doctrinal argument--emphasis on the implications
|
||
|
of prior cases decided by the Supreme Court;[34]
|
||
|
|
||
|
5) prudential argument--emphasis on the consequences
|
||
|
of adopting a proffered decision in any given
|
||
|
case;[35] and, finally,
|
||
|
|
||
|
6) ethical argument--reliance on the overall "ethos"
|
||
|
of limited government as centrally constituting
|
||
|
American political culture.[36]
|
||
|
|
||
|
I want to frame my consideration of the Second Amendment
|
||
|
within the first five of Bobbitt's categories; they are all
|
||
|
richly present in consideration of what the Amendment might mean.
|
||
|
The sixth, which emphasizes the ethos of limited government, does
|
||
|
not play a significant role in the debate of the Second
|
||
|
Amendment.[37]
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
A. TEXT
|
||
|
|
||
|
I begin with the appeal to text. Recall the Second
|
||
|
Amendment: "A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the
|
||
|
security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and
|
||
|
bear Arms, shall not be infringed." No one has ever described the
|
||
|
Constitution as a marvel of clarity, and the Second Amendment is
|
||
|
perhaps one of the worst drafted of all its provisions. What is
|
||
|
special about the Amendment is the inclusion of an opening
|
||
|
clause--a preamble, if you will--that seems to set out its
|
||
|
purpose. No similar clause is a part of any other Amendment,[38]
|
||
|
though that does not, of course, mean that we do not ascribe
|
||
|
purposes to them. It would be impossible to make sense of the
|
||
|
Constitution if we did not engage in the ascription of purpose.
|
||
|
Indeed, the major debates about the First Amendment arise
|
||
|
precisely when one tries to discern a purpose, given that
|
||
|
"literalism" is a hopelessly failing approach to interpreting it.
|
||
|
We usually do not even recognize punishment of fraud--a classic
|
||
|
speech act--as a free speech problem because we so sensibly
|
||
|
assume that the purpose of the First Amendment could not have
|
||
|
been, for example, to protect the circulation of patently
|
||
|
deceptive information to potential investors in commercial
|
||
|
enterprises. The sharp differences that distinguish those who
|
||
|
would limit the reach of the First Amendment to "political"
|
||
|
speech from those who would extend it much further, encompassing
|
||
|
non-deceptive commercial speech, are all derived from different
|
||
|
readings of the purpose that underlies the raw text.[39]
|
||
|
|
||
|
A standard move of those legal analysts who wish to limit
|
||
|
the Second Amendment's force is to focus on its "preamble" as
|
||
|
setting out a restrictive purpose. Recall Laurence Tribe's
|
||
|
assertion that that purpose was to allow the states to keep their
|
||
|
militias and to protect them against the possibility that the new
|
||
|
national government will use its power to establish a powerful
|
||
|
standing army and eliminate the state militias. This purposive
|
||
|
reading quickly disposes of any notion that there is an
|
||
|
"individual" right to keep and bear arms. The right, if such it
|
||
|
be, is only a state's right. The consequence of this reading is
|
||
|
obvious: the national government has the power to regulate--to
|
||
|
the point of prohibition--private ownership of guns, since that
|
||
|
has, by stipulation, nothing to do with preserving state
|
||
|
militias. This is, indeed, the position of the ACLU, which reads
|
||
|
the Amendment as protecting only the right of "maintaining an
|
||
|
effective state militia.... [T]he individual's right to bear arms
|
||
|
applies only to the preservation or efficiency of a well-
|
||
|
regulated [state] militia. Except for lawful police and military
|
||
|
purposes, the possession of weapons by individuals is not
|
||
|
constitutionally protected."[40]
|
||
|
|
||
|
This is not a wholly implausible reading, but one might ask
|
||
|
why the Framers did not simply say something like "Congress shall
|
||
|
have no power to prohibit state-organized and directed militias."
|
||
|
Perhaps they in fact meant to do something else. Moreover, we
|
||
|
might ask if ordinary readers of late 18th Century legal prose
|
||
|
would have interpreted it as meaning something else. The text at
|
||
|
best provides only a starting point for a conversation. In this
|
||
|
specific instance, it does not come close to resolving the
|
||
|
questions posed by federal regulation of arms. Even if we accept
|
||
|
the preamble as significant, we must still try to figure out what
|
||
|
might be suggested by guaranteeing to "the people the right to
|
||
|
keep and bear arms;" moreover, as we shall see presently, even
|
||
|
the preamble presents unexpected difficulties in interpretation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
B. HISTORY
|
||
|
|
||
|
One might argue (and some have) that the substantive right
|
||
|
is one pertaining to a collective body--"the people"--rather than
|
||
|
to individuals. Professor Cress, for example, argues that state
|
||
|
constitutions regularly used the words "man" or "person" in
|
||
|
regard to "individual rights such as freedom of conscience,"
|
||
|
whereas the use in those constitutions of the term "the people"
|
||
|
in regard to a right to bear arms is intended to refer to the
|
||
|
"sovereign citizenry" collectively organized.[41] Such an
|
||
|
argument founders, however, upon examination of the text of the
|
||
|
federal Bill of Rights itself and the usage there of the term
|
||
|
"the people" in the First, Fourth, Ninth, and Tenth Amendments.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Consider that the Fourth Amendment protects " [t]he right of
|
||
|
the people to be secure in their persons," or that the First
|
||
|
Amendment refers to the "right of the people peaceably to
|
||
|
assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of
|
||
|
grievances." It is difficult to know how one might plausibly read
|
||
|
the Fourth Amendment as other than a protection of individual
|
||
|
rights, and it would approach the frivolous to read the assembly
|
||
|
and petition clause as referring only to the right of state
|
||
|
legislatures to meet and pass a remonstrance directed to Congress
|
||
|
or the President against some governmental act. The Tenth
|
||
|
Amendment is trickier, though it does explicitly differentiate
|
||
|
between "states" and "the people" in terms of retained
|
||
|
rights.[42] Concededly, it would be possible to read the Tenth
|
||
|
Amendment as suggesting only an ultimate right of revolution by
|
||
|
the collective people should the "states" stray too far from
|
||
|
their designated role of protecting the rights of the people.
|
||
|
This reading follows directly from the social contract theory of
|
||
|
the state. (But, of course, many of these rights are held by
|
||
|
individuals.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Although the record is suitably complicated, it seems
|
||
|
tendentious to reject out of hand the argument that one purpose
|
||
|
of the Amendment was to recognize an individual's right to engage
|
||
|
in armed self-defense against criminal conduct.[43] Historian
|
||
|
Robert E. Shalhope supports this view, arguing in his article The
|
||
|
Ideological Origins of the Second Amendment [44] that the
|
||
|
Amendment guarantees individuals the right "to possess arms for
|
||
|
their own personal defense."[45] It would be especially
|
||
|
unsurprising if this were the case, given the fact that the
|
||
|
development of a professional police force (even within large
|
||
|
American cities) was still at least a half century away at the
|
||
|
end of the colonial period.[46] I shall return later in this
|
||
|
essay to this individualist notion of the Amendment, particularly
|
||
|
in regard to the argument that "changing circumstances,"
|
||
|
including the development of a professional police force, have
|
||
|
deprived it of any continuing plausibility. But I want now to
|
||
|
explore a second possible purpose of the Amendment, which as a
|
||
|
sometime political theorist I find considerably more interesting.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Assume, as Professor Cress has argued, that the Second
|
||
|
Amendment refers to a communitarian, rather than an individual,
|
||
|
right.[47] We are still left the task of defining the
|
||
|
relationship between the community and the state apparatus. It is
|
||
|
this fascinating problem to which I now turn.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Consider once more the preamble and its reference to the
|
||
|
importance of a well-regulated militia. Is the meaning of the
|
||
|
term obvious? Perhaps we should make some effort to find out what
|
||
|
the term "militia" meant to 18th century readers and writers,
|
||
|
rather than assume that it refers only to Dan Quayle's Indiana
|
||
|
National Guard and the like. By no means am I arguing that the
|
||
|
discovery of that meaning is dispositive as to the general
|
||
|
meaning of the Constitution for us today. But it seems foolhardy
|
||
|
to be entirely uninterested in the historical philology behind
|
||
|
the Second Amendment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
I, for one, have been persuaded that the term "militia" did
|
||
|
not have the limited reference that Professor Cress and many
|
||
|
modern legal analysts assign to it. There is strong evidence that
|
||
|
"militia" refers to all of the people, or at least all of those
|
||
|
treated as full citizens of the community. Consider, for example,
|
||
|
the question asked by George Mason, one of the Virginians who
|
||
|
refused to sign the Constitution because of its lack of a Bill of
|
||
|
Rights: "Who are the Militia? They consist now of the whole
|
||
|
people."[48] Similarly, the Federal Farmer, one of the most
|
||
|
important Anti-Federalist opponents of the Constitution, referred
|
||
|
to a "militia, when properly formed, [as] in fact the people
|
||
|
themselves."[49] We have, of course, moved now from text to
|
||
|
history. And this history is most interesting, especially when we
|
||
|
look at the development of notions of popular sovereignty. It has
|
||
|
become almost a cliche of contemporary American historiography to
|
||
|
link the development of American political thought, including its
|
||
|
constitutional aspects, to republican thought in England, the
|
||
|
"country" critique of the powerful "court" centered in London.
|
||
|
|
||
|
One of this school's important writers, of course, was James
|
||
|
Harrington, who not only was influential at the time but also has
|
||
|
recently been given a certain pride of place by one of the most
|
||
|
prominent of contemporary "neo-republicans," Professor Frank
|
||
|
Michelman.[50] One historian describes Harrington as having made
|
||
|
"the most significant contribution to English libertarian
|
||
|
attitudes toward arms, the individual, and society."[51] He was a
|
||
|
central figure in the development of the ideas of popular
|
||
|
sovereignty and republicanism.[52] For Harrington, preservation
|
||
|
of republican liberty requires independence, which rests
|
||
|
primarily on possession of adequate property to make men free
|
||
|
from coercion by employers or landlords. But widespread ownership
|
||
|
of land is not sufficient. These independent yeoman should also
|
||
|
bear arms. As Professor Morgan puts it, "[T]hese independent
|
||
|
yeomen, armed and embodied in a militia, are also a popular
|
||
|
government's best protection against its enemies, whether they be
|
||
|
aggressive foreign monarchs or scheming demagogues within the
|
||
|
nation itself."[53]
|
||
|
|
||
|
A central fear of Harrington and of all future republicans
|
||
|
was a standing army, composed of professional soldiers.
|
||
|
Harrington and his fellow republicans viewed a standing army as a
|
||
|
threat to freedom, to be avoided at almost all costs. Thus, says
|
||
|
Morgan, "A militia is the only safe form of military power that a
|
||
|
popular government can employ; and because it is composed of the
|
||
|
armed yeomanry, it will prevail over the mercenary professionals
|
||
|
who man the armies of neighboring monarchs."[54]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Scholars of the First Amendment have made us aware of the
|
||
|
importance of John Trenchard and Thomas Gordon, whose Cato's
|
||
|
Letter's were central to the formation of the American notion of
|
||
|
freedom of the press. That notion includes what Vincent Blasi
|
||
|
would come to call the "checking value" of a free press, which
|
||
|
stands as a sturdy exposer of governmental misdeeds.[55] Consider
|
||
|
the possibility, though, that the ultimate "checking value" in a
|
||
|
republican polity is the ability of an armed populace,
|
||
|
presumptively motivated by a shared commitment to the common
|
||
|
good, to resist governmental tyranny.[56] Indeed, one of Cato's
|
||
|
letters refers to "the Exercise of despotick Power [as] the
|
||
|
unrelenting War of an armed Tyrant upon his unarmed
|
||
|
Subjects...."[57]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Cress persuasively shows that no one defended universal
|
||
|
possession of arms. New Hampshire had no objection to disarming
|
||
|
those who "are or have been in actual rebellion," just as Samuel
|
||
|
Adams stressed that only "peaceable citizens" should be protected
|
||
|
in their right of "keeping their own arms."[58] All these points
|
||
|
can be conceded, however, without conceding as well that
|
||
|
Congress--or, for that matter, the States--had the power to
|
||
|
disarm these "peaceable citizens."
|
||
|
|
||
|
Surely one of the foundations of American political thought
|
||
|
of the period was the well-justified concern about political
|
||
|
corruption and consequent governmental tyranny. Even the
|
||
|
Federalists, fending off their opponents who accused them of
|
||
|
foisting an oppressive new scheme upon the American people, were
|
||
|
careful to acknowledge the risks of tyranny. James Madison, for
|
||
|
example, speaks in Federalist Number Forty-Six of "the advantage
|
||
|
of being armed, which the Americans possess over the people of
|
||
|
almost every other nation."[59] The advantage in question was not
|
||
|
merely the defense of American borders; a standing army might
|
||
|
well accomplish that. Rather, an armed public was advantageous in
|
||
|
protecting political liberty. It is therefore no surprise that
|
||
|
the Federal Farmer, the nom de plume of an anti-federalist critic
|
||
|
of the new Constitution and its absence of a Bill of Rights,
|
||
|
could write that "to preserve liberty, it is essential that the
|
||
|
whole body of the people always possess arms, and be taught
|
||
|
alike, especially when young, how to use them...."[60] On this
|
||
|
matter, at least, there was no cleavage between the pro-
|
||
|
ratification Madison and his opponent.
|
||
|
|
||
|
In his influential Commentaries on the Constitution, Joseph
|
||
|
Story, certainly no friend of Anti-Federalism, emphasized the
|
||
|
"importance" of the Second Amendment.[61] He went on to describe
|
||
|
the militia as "the natural defence of a free country" not only
|
||
|
"against sudden foreign invasions" and "domestic insurrections,"
|
||
|
with which one might well expect a Federalist to be concerned,
|
||
|
but also against "domestic usurpations of power by rulers."[62]
|
||
|
"The right of the citizens to keep and bear arms has justly been
|
||
|
considered," Story wrote, "as the palladium of the liberties of a
|
||
|
republic; since it offers a strong moral check against the
|
||
|
usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers; and will generally,
|
||
|
even if these are successful in the first instance, enable the
|
||
|
people to resist and triumph over them."[63]
|
||
|
|
||
|
We also see this blending of individualist and collective
|
||
|
accounts of the right to bear arms in remarks by Judge Thomas
|
||
|
Cooley, one of the most influential 19th century constitutional
|
||
|
commentators. Noting that the state might call into its official
|
||
|
militia only "a small number" of the eligible citizenry, Cooley
|
||
|
wrote that "if the right [to keep and bear arms] were limited to
|
||
|
those enrolled, the purpose of this guaranty might be defeated
|
||
|
altogether by the action or neglect to act of the government it
|
||
|
was meant to hold in check."[64] Finally, it is worth noting the
|
||
|
remarks of Theodore Schroeder, one of the most important
|
||
|
developers of the theory of freedom of speech early in this
|
||
|
century.[65] "[T]he obvious import [of the constitutional
|
||
|
guarantee to carry arms]," he argues, "is to promote a state of
|
||
|
preparedness for self-defense even against the invasions of
|
||
|
government, because only governments have ever disarmed any
|
||
|
considerable class of people as a means toward their
|
||
|
enslavement."[66]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Such analyses provide the basis for Edward Abbey's revision
|
||
|
of a common bumper sticker, "If guns are outlawed, only the
|
||
|
government will have guns."[67] One of the things this slogan has
|
||
|
helped me to understand is the political tilt contained within
|
||
|
the Weberian definition of the state--i.e., the repository of a
|
||
|
monopoly of the legitimate means of violence [68]--that is so
|
||
|
commonly used by political scientists. It is a profoundly statist
|
||
|
definition, the product of a specifically German tradition of the
|
||
|
(strong) state rather than of a strikingly different American
|
||
|
political tradition that is fundamentally mistrustful of state
|
||
|
power and vigilant about maintaining ultimate power, including
|
||
|
the power of arms, in the populace.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We thus see what I think is one of the most interesting
|
||
|
points in regard to the new historiography of the Second
|
||
|
Amendment--its linkage to conceptions of republican political
|
||
|
order. Contemporary admirers of republican theory use it as a
|
||
|
source both of critiques of more individualist liberal theory and
|
||
|
of positive insight into the way we today might reorder our
|
||
|
political lives.[69] One point of emphasis for neo-republicans is
|
||
|
the value of participation in government, as contrasted to mere
|
||
|
representation by a distant leadership, even if formally elected.
|
||
|
But the implications of republicanism might push us in
|
||
|
unexpected, even embarrassing, directions: just as ordinary
|
||
|
citizens should participate actively in governmental decision
|
||
|
making through offering their own deliberative insights, rather
|
||
|
than be confined to casting ballots once every two or four years
|
||
|
for those very few individuals who will actually make decisions,
|
||
|
so should ordinary citizens participate in the process of law
|
||
|
enforcement and defense of liberty rather than rely on
|
||
|
professionalized peacekeepers, whether we call them standing
|
||
|
armies or police.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
C. Structure
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have also passed imperceptibly into a form of structural
|
||
|
argument, for we see that one aspect of the structure of checks
|
||
|
and balances within the purview of 18th century thought was the
|
||
|
armed citizen. That is, those who would limit the meaning of the
|
||
|
Second Amendment to the constitutional protection of state-
|
||
|
controlled militias agree that such protection rests on the
|
||
|
perception that militarily competent states were viewed as a
|
||
|
potential protection against a tyrannical national government.
|
||
|
Indeed, in 1801 several governors threatened to call out state
|
||
|
militias if the Federalists in Congress refused to elect Thomas
|
||
|
Jefferson president.[70] But this argument assumes that there are
|
||
|
only two basic components in the vertical structure of the
|
||
|
American polity--the national government and the states. It
|
||
|
ignores the implication that might be drawn from the Second,
|
||
|
Ninth, and Tenth Amendments: the citizenry itself can be viewed
|
||
|
as an important third component of republican governance insofar
|
||
|
as it stands ready to defend republican liberty against the
|
||
|
depredations of the other two structures, however futile that
|
||
|
might appear as a practical matter.
|
||
|
|
||
|
One implication of this republican rationale for the Second
|
||
|
Amendment is that it calls into question the ability of a state
|
||
|
to disarm its citizenry. That is, the strongest version of the
|
||
|
republican argument would hold it to be a"privilege and immunity
|
||
|
of United States citizenship"--of membership in a liberty-
|
||
|
enhancing political order--to keep arms that could be taken up
|
||
|
against tyranny wherever found, including, obviously, state
|
||
|
government. Ironically, the principal citation supporting this
|
||
|
argument is to Chief Justice Taney's egregious opinion in Dred
|
||
|
Scott, [71] where he suggested that an uncontroversial attribute
|
||
|
of citizenship, in addition to the right to migrate from one
|
||
|
state to another, was the right to possess arms. The logic of
|
||
|
Taney's argument at this point seems to be that, because it was
|
||
|
inconceivable that the Framers could have genuinely imagined
|
||
|
blacks having the right to possess arms, it follows that they
|
||
|
could not have envisioned them as being citizens, since
|
||
|
citizenship entailed that right. Taney's seeming recognition of a
|
||
|
right to arms is much relied on by opponents of gun control.[72]
|
||
|
Indeed, recall Madison's critique, in Federalist Numbers Ten and
|
||
|
Fourteen, of republicanism's traditional emphasis on the
|
||
|
desirability of small states as preservers of republican liberty.
|
||
|
He transformed this debate by arguing that the states would be
|
||
|
less likely to preserve liberty because they could so easily fall
|
||
|
under the sway of a local dominant faction, whereas an extended
|
||
|
republic would guard against this danger. Anyone who accepts the
|
||
|
Madisonian argument could scarcely be happy enhancing the powers
|
||
|
of the states over their own citizens; indeed, this has been one
|
||
|
of the great themes of American constitutional history, as the
|
||
|
nationalization of the Bill of Rights has been deemed necessary
|
||
|
in order to protect popular liberty against state depredation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
D. Doctrine
|
||
|
|
||
|
Inevitably one must at least mention, even though there is
|
||
|
not space to discuss fully, the so-called incorporation
|
||
|
controversy regarding the application of the Bill of Rights to
|
||
|
the states through the Fourteenth Amendment. It should be no
|
||
|
surprise that the opponents of gun control appear to take a "full
|
||
|
incorporationist" view of that Amendment.[73] They view the
|
||
|
privileges and immunities clause, which was eviscerated in the
|
||
|
Slaughterhouse Cases,[74] as designed to require the states to
|
||
|
honor the rights that had been held, by Justice Marshall in
|
||
|
Barron v. Baltimore in 1833,[75] to restrict only the national
|
||
|
government. In 1875 the Court stated, in United States v.
|
||
|
Cruikshank,[76] that the Second Amendment, insofar as it grants
|
||
|
any right at all, "means no more than that it shall not be
|
||
|
infringed by Congress. This is one of the amendments that has no
|
||
|
other effect than to restrict the powers of the national
|
||
|
government. . ." Lest there be any remaining doubt on this point,
|
||
|
the Court specifically cited the Cruikshank language eleven years
|
||
|
later in Presser v. Illinois, [77] in rejecting the claim that
|
||
|
the Second Amendment served to invalidate an Illinois statute
|
||
|
that prohibited "any body of men whatever, other than the regular
|
||
|
organized volunteer militia of this State, and the troops of the
|
||
|
United States. . .to drill or parade with arms in any city, or
|
||
|
town, of this State, without the license of the Governor
|
||
|
thereof...."[78]
|
||
|
|
||
|
The first "incorporation decision," Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co.
|
||
|
v. Chicago, [79] was not delivered until eleven years after
|
||
|
Presser; one therefore cannot know if the judges in Cruikshank
|
||
|
and Presser were willing to concede that any of the amendments
|
||
|
comprising the Bill of Rights were anything more than limitations
|
||
|
on congressional or other national power. The obvious question,
|
||
|
given the modern legal reality of the incorporation of almost all
|
||
|
of the rights protected by the First, Fourth, Fifth, Sixth, and
|
||
|
Eighth Amendments, is what exactly justifies treating the Second
|
||
|
Amendment as the great exception. Why, that is, should Cruikshank
|
||
|
and Presser be regarded as binding precedent any more than any of
|
||
|
the other "pre-incorporation" decisions refusing to apply given
|
||
|
aspects of the Bill of Rights against the states?
|
||
|
|
||
|
If one agrees with Professor Tribe that the Amendment is
|
||
|
simply a federalist protection of state rights, then presumably
|
||
|
there is nothing to incorporate.[80] If, however, one accepts the
|
||
|
Amendment as a serious substantive limitation on the ability of
|
||
|
the national government to regulate the private possession of
|
||
|
arms based on either the "individualist" or "neo-republican"
|
||
|
theories sketched above, then why not follow the
|
||
|
"incorporationist" logic applied to other amendments and limit
|
||
|
the states as well in their powers to regulate (and especially to
|
||
|
prohibit) such possession? The Supreme Court has almost
|
||
|
shamelessly refused to discuss the issue, [81] but that need not
|
||
|
stop the rest of us.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Returning, though, to the question of Congress' power to
|
||
|
regulate the keeping and bearing of arms, one notes that there
|
||
|
is, basically, only one modern case that discusses the issue,
|
||
|
United States v. Miller, [82] decided in 1939. Jack Miller was
|
||
|
charged with moving a sawed-off shotgun in interstate commerce in
|
||
|
violation of the National Firearms Act of 1934. Among other
|
||
|
things, Miller and a compatriot had not registered the firearm,
|
||
|
as required by the Act. The court below had dismissed the charge,
|
||
|
accepting Miller's argument that the Act violated the Second
|
||
|
Amendment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The Supreme Court reversed unanimously, with the arch-
|
||
|
conservative Justice McReynolds writing the opinion. [83]
|
||
|
Interestingly enough, he emphasized that there was no evidence
|
||
|
showing that a sawed-off shotgun "at this time has some
|
||
|
reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a
|
||
|
well regulated militia."[84] And "[c]ertainly it is not within
|
||
|
judicial notice that this weapon is any part of the ordinary
|
||
|
military equipment or that its use could contribute to the common
|
||
|
defense."[85] Miller might have had a tenable argument had he
|
||
|
been able to show that he was keeping or bearing a weapon that
|
||
|
clearly had a potential military use.[86]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Justice McReynolds went on to describe the purpose of the
|
||
|
Second Amendment as "assur[ing] the continuation and render[ing]
|
||
|
possible the effectiveness of [the Militia]."[87] He contrasted
|
||
|
the Militia with troops of a standing army, which the
|
||
|
Constitution indeed forbade the states to keep without the
|
||
|
explicit consent of Congress. "The sentiment of the time strongly
|
||
|
disfavored standing armies; the common view was that adequate
|
||
|
defense of country and laws could be secured through the Militia-
|
||
|
-civilians primarily, soldiers on occasion."[88] McReynolds noted
|
||
|
further that "the debates in the Convention, the history and
|
||
|
legislation of Colonies and States, and the writings of approved
|
||
|
commentators [all] [s]how plainly enough that the Militia
|
||
|
comprised all males physically capable of acting in concert for
|
||
|
the common defense."[89]
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is difficult to read Miller as rendering the Second
|
||
|
Amendment meaningless as a control on Congress. Ironically,
|
||
|
Miller can be read to support some of the most extreme anti-gun
|
||
|
control arguments, e.g., that the individual citizen has a right
|
||
|
to keep and bear bazookas, rocket launchers, and other armaments
|
||
|
that are clearly relevant to modern warfare, including, of
|
||
|
course, assault weapons. Arguments about the constitutional
|
||
|
legitimacy of a prohibition by Congress of private ownership of
|
||
|
handguns or, what is much more likely, assault rifles, might turn
|
||
|
on the usefulness of such guns in military settings.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
E. Prudentialism
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have looked at four of Bobbitt's categories--text,
|
||
|
history, structure, and case law doctrine--and have seen, at the
|
||
|
very least, that the arguments on behalf of a "strong" Second
|
||
|
Amendment are stronger than many of us might wish were the case.
|
||
|
This, then, brings us to the fifth category, prudentialism, or an
|
||
|
attentiveness to practical consequences, which is clearly of
|
||
|
great importance in any debates about gun control. The standard
|
||
|
argument in favor of strict control and, ultimately, prohibition
|
||
|
of private ownership focuses on the extensive social costs of
|
||
|
widespread distribution of firearms. Consider, for example, a
|
||
|
recent speech given by former Justice Lewis Powell to the
|
||
|
American Bar Association. He noted that over 40,000 murders were
|
||
|
committed in the United States in 1986 and 1987, and that fully
|
||
|
sixty percent of them were committed with firearms. England and
|
||
|
Wales, however, saw only 662 homicides in 1986, less than eight
|
||
|
percent of which were committed with firearms.[90] Justice Powell
|
||
|
indicated that, "[w]ith respect to handguns," in contrast "to
|
||
|
sporting rifles and shotguns[,] it is not easy to understand why
|
||
|
the Second Amendment, or the notion of liberty, should be viewed
|
||
|
as creating a right to own and carry a weapon that contributes so
|
||
|
directly to the shocking number of murders in our society."[91]
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is hard to disagree with Justice Powell; it appears
|
||
|
almost crazy to protect as a constitutional right something that
|
||
|
so clearly results in extraordinary social costs with little, if
|
||
|
any, compensating social advantage. Indeed, since Justice
|
||
|
Powell's talk, the subject of assault rifles has become a staple
|
||
|
of national discussion, and the opponents of regulation of such
|
||
|
weapons have deservedly drawn the censure even of conservative
|
||
|
leaders like William Bennett. It is almost impossible to imagine
|
||
|
that the judiciary would strike down a determination by Congress
|
||
|
that the possession of assault weapons should be denied to
|
||
|
private citizens.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Even if one accepts the historical plausibility of the
|
||
|
arguments advanced above, the overriding temptation is to say
|
||
|
that times and circumstances have changed and that there is
|
||
|
simply no reason to continue enforcing an outmoded, and indeed
|
||
|
dangerous, understanding of private rights against public order.
|
||
|
This criticism is clearest in regard to the so-called
|
||
|
individualist argument, for one can argue that the rise of a
|
||
|
professional police force to enforce the law has made irrelevant,
|
||
|
and perhaps even counterproductive, the continuation of a strong
|
||
|
notion of self-help as the remedy for crime.[92]
|
||
|
|
||
|
I am not unsympathetic to such arguments. It is no purpose
|
||
|
of this essay to solicit membership for the National Rifle
|
||
|
Association or to express any sympathy for what even Don Kates, a
|
||
|
strong critic of the conventional dismissal of the Second
|
||
|
Amendment, describes as "the gun lobby's obnoxious habit of
|
||
|
assailing all forms of regulation on 2nd Amendment grounds."[93]
|
||
|
And yet ....
|
||
|
|
||
|
Circumstances may well have changed in regard to individual
|
||
|
defense, although we ignore at our political peril the good-faith
|
||
|
belief of many Americans that they cannot rely on the police for
|
||
|
protection against a variety of criminals. Still, let us assume
|
||
|
that the individualist reading of the Amendment has been vitiated
|
||
|
by changing circumstances. Are we quite so confident that
|
||
|
circumstances are equally different in regard to the republican
|
||
|
rationale outlined earlier?
|
||
|
|
||
|
One would, of course, like to believe that the state,
|
||
|
whether at the local or national level, presents no threat to
|
||
|
important political values, including liberty. But our propensity
|
||
|
to believe that this is the case may be little more than a sign
|
||
|
of how truly different we are from our radical forbearers. I do
|
||
|
not want to argue that the state is necessarily tyrannical; I am
|
||
|
not an anarchist. But it seems foolhardy to assume that the armed
|
||
|
state will necessarily be benevolent. The American political
|
||
|
tradition is, for good or ill, based in large measure on a
|
||
|
healthy mistrust of the state. The development of widespread
|
||
|
suffrage and greater majoritarianism in our polity is itself no
|
||
|
sure protection, at least within republican theory. The
|
||
|
republican theory is predicated on the stark contrast between
|
||
|
mere democracy, where people are motivated by selfish personal
|
||
|
interest, and a republic, where civic virtue, both in citizens
|
||
|
and leadership, tames selfishness on behalf of the common good.
|
||
|
In any event, it is hard for me to see how one can argue that
|
||
|
circumstances have so changed as to make mass disarmament
|
||
|
constitutionally unproblematic.[94]
|
||
|
|
||
|
Indeed, only in recent months have we seen the brutal
|
||
|
suppression of the Chinese student demonstrations in Tianamen
|
||
|
Square. It should not surprise us that some N.R.A. sympathizers
|
||
|
have presented that situation as an object lesson to those who
|
||
|
unthinkingly support the prohibition of private gun ownership.
|
||
|
"[I]f all Chinese citizens kept arms, their rulers would hardly
|
||
|
have dared to massacre the demonstrators .... The private keeping
|
||
|
of hand-held personal firearms is within the constitutional
|
||
|
design for a counter to government run amok .... As the Tianamen
|
||
|
Square tragedy showed so graphically, AK-47s fall into that
|
||
|
category of weapons, and that is why they are protected by the
|
||
|
Second Amendment."[95] It is simply silly to respond that small
|
||
|
arms are irrelevant against nuclear-armed states: Witness
|
||
|
contemporary Northern Ireland and the territories occupied by
|
||
|
Israel, where the sophisticated weaponry of Great Britain and
|
||
|
Israel have proved almost totally beside the point. The fact that
|
||
|
these may not be pleasant examples does not affect the principal
|
||
|
point, that a state facing a totally disarmed population is in a
|
||
|
far better position, for good or for ill, to suppress popular
|
||
|
demonstrations and uprisings than one that must calculate the
|
||
|
possibilities of its soldiers and officials being injured or
|
||
|
killed.'[96]
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
III. TAKING THE SECOND AMENDMENT SERIOUSLY
|
||
|
|
||
|
There is one further problem of no small import: If one does
|
||
|
accept the plausibility of any of the arguments on behalf of a
|
||
|
strong reading of the Second Amendment, but, nevertheless,
|
||
|
rejects them in the name of social prudence and the present-day
|
||
|
consequences produced by finicky adherence to earlier
|
||
|
understandings, why do we not apply such consequentialist
|
||
|
criteria to each and every part of the Bill of Rights?[97] As
|
||
|
Ronald Dworkin has argued, what it means to take rights seriously
|
||
|
is that one will honor them even when there is significant social
|
||
|
cost in doing so. If protecting freedom of speech, the rights of
|
||
|
criminal defendants, or any other part of the Bill of Rights were
|
||
|
always (or even most of the time) clearly cost less to the
|
||
|
society as a whole, it would truly be impossible to understand
|
||
|
why they would be as controversial as they are. The very fact
|
||
|
that there are often significant costs--criminals going free,
|
||
|
oppressed groups having to hear viciously racist speech and so
|
||
|
on--helps to account for the observed fact that those who view
|
||
|
themselves as defenders of the Bill of Rights are generally
|
||
|
antagonistic to prudential arguments. Most often, one finds them
|
||
|
embracing versions of textual, historical, or doctrinal argument
|
||
|
that dismiss as almost crass and vulgar any insistence that times
|
||
|
might have changed and made too "expensive" the continued
|
||
|
adherence to given view. "Cost-benefit" analysis, rightly or
|
||
|
wrongly, has come to be viewed as a "conservative" weapon to
|
||
|
attack liberal rights.[98] Yet one finds that the tables are
|
||
|
strikingly turned when the Second Amendment comes into play. ere
|
||
|
it is "conservatives" who argue in effect that social costs are
|
||
|
irrelevant and "liberals" who argue for a notion of the "living
|
||
|
Constitution" and "changed circumstances" that would have the
|
||
|
practical consequence of removing any real bite from the Second
|
||
|
Amendment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
As Fred Donaldson of Austin, Texas wrote, commenting on
|
||
|
those who defended the Supreme Court's decision upholding flag-
|
||
|
burning as compelled by a proper (and decidedly non-prudential)
|
||
|
understanding of the First Amendment, "[I]t seems inconsistent
|
||
|
for [defenders of the decision] to scream so loudly" at the
|
||
|
prospect of limiting the protection given expression "while you
|
||
|
smile complacently at the Second torn and bleeding. If the Second
|
||
|
Amendment is not worth the paper it is written on, what price the
|
||
|
First?"[99] The fact that Mr. Donaldson is an ordinary citizen
|
||
|
rather than an eminent law professor does not make his question
|
||
|
any less pointed or its answer less difficult.
|
||
|
|
||
|
For too long, most members of the legal academy have treated
|
||
|
the Second Amendment as the equivalent of an embarrassing
|
||
|
relative, whose mention brings a quick change of subject to
|
||
|
other, more respectable, family members. That will no longer do.
|
||
|
It is time for the Second Amendment to enter full scale into the
|
||
|
consciousness of the legal academy. Those of us who agree with
|
||
|
Martha Minow's emphasis on the desirability of encouraging
|
||
|
different "voices" in the legal conversation [100] should be
|
||
|
especially aware of the importance of recognizing the attempts of
|
||
|
Mr. Donaldson and his millions of colleagues to join the
|
||
|
conversation. To be sure, it is unlikely that Professor Minow had
|
||
|
those too often peremptorily dismissed as "gun nuts" in mind as
|
||
|
possible providers of "insight and growth," but surely the call
|
||
|
for sensitivity to different or excluded voices cannot extend
|
||
|
only to those groups "we" already, perhaps "complacent[ly],"
|
||
|
believe have a lot to tell "us."[101] I am not so naive as to
|
||
|
believe that conversation will overcome the chasm that now
|
||
|
separates the sensibility of, say, Senator Hatch and myself as to
|
||
|
what constitutes the "right[s] most valued by free men [and
|
||
|
women]."[102] It is important to remember that one will still
|
||
|
need to join up sides and engage in vigorous political struggle.
|
||
|
But it might at least help to make the political sides appear
|
||
|
more human to one another. Perhaps "we" might be led to stop
|
||
|
referring casually to "gun nuts" just as, maybe, members of the
|
||
|
NRA could be brought to understand the real fear that the
|
||
|
currently almost uncontrolled system of gun ownership sparks in
|
||
|
the minds of many whom they casually dismiss as "bleeding-heart
|
||
|
liberals." Is not, after all, the possibility of serious, engaged
|
||
|
discussion about political issues at the heart of what is most
|
||
|
attractive in both liberal and republican versions of politics?
|
||
|
|
||
|
-= APPENDIX =-
|
||
|
|
||
|
1. It is not irrelevant that the Bill of Rights submitted to
|
||
|
the states in 1789 included not only what are now the first
|
||
|
ten Amendments, but also two others. Indeed, what we call
|
||
|
the First Amendment was only the third one of the list
|
||
|
submitted to the states. The initial "first amendment" in
|
||
|
fact concerned the future size of the House of
|
||
|
Representatives, a topic of no small importance to the Anti-
|
||
|
Federalists, who were appalled by the smallness of the House
|
||
|
seemingly envisioned by the Philadelphia framers. The second
|
||
|
prohibited any pay raise voted by members of Congress to
|
||
|
themselves from taking effect until an election "shall have
|
||
|
intervened." See J. GOEBEL, 1 THE OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES
|
||
|
DEVISE HISTORY OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES:
|
||
|
ANTECEDENTS AND BEGINNINGS TO 1801, at 442 n.162 (1971). Had
|
||
|
all of the initial twelve proposals been ratified, we would,
|
||
|
it is possible, have a dramatically different cognitive map
|
||
|
of the Bill of Rights. At the very least, one would neither
|
||
|
hear defenses of the "preferred" status of freedom of speech
|
||
|
framed in terms of the "firstness" of (what we know as) the
|
||
|
First Amendment, nor the wholly invalid inference drawn from
|
||
|
that "firstness" of some special intention of the Framers to
|
||
|
safeguard the particular rights laid out there.
|
||
|
|
||
|
2. "Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of
|
||
|
religion . . . or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the
|
||
|
press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and
|
||
|
to petition the Government for a redress of grievances."
|
||
|
U.S. CONST. amend. 1.
|
||
|
|
||
|
3. "The right of the people to be secure in their persons,
|
||
|
houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches
|
||
|
and seizures, shall not be violated; and no Warrants shall
|
||
|
issue but upon probable cause, supported by Oath or
|
||
|
affirmation, and particularly describing the place to be
|
||
|
searched, and the persons or things to be seized." U.S.
|
||
|
CONST. amend. IV.
|
||
|
|
||
|
4. "No person shall be held to answer for a capital, or
|
||
|
otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentment or
|
||
|
indictment of a Grand Jury, except in cases arising in the
|
||
|
land or naval forces, or in the Militia, when in actual
|
||
|
service in time of War or public danger; nor shall any
|
||
|
person be subject for the same offense to be twice put in
|
||
|
jeopardy of life or limb; nor shall be compelled in any
|
||
|
criminal case to be a witness against himself, nor be
|
||
|
deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process
|
||
|
of law ...." U.S. CONST. amend. V.
|
||
|
|
||
|
5. "In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the
|
||
|
right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury of
|
||
|
the State and district wherein the crime shall have been
|
||
|
committed, which district shall have been previously
|
||
|
ascertained by law, and to be informed of the nature and
|
||
|
cause of the accusation; to be confronted with the witnesses
|
||
|
against him; to have compulsory process for obtaining
|
||
|
witnesses in his favor, and to have the Assistance of
|
||
|
Counsel for his defense." U.S. CONST. amend VI.
|
||
|
|
||
|
6. "Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive fines
|
||
|
imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted." U.S.
|
||
|
CONST. amend. VIII.
|
||
|
|
||
|
7. "The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights,
|
||
|
shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained
|
||
|
by the people." U.S. CONST. amend. IX.
|
||
|
|
||
|
8. "[N]or shall private property be taken for public use,
|
||
|
without just compensation." U.S. CONST. amend. IV.
|
||
|
|
||
|
9. "The powers not delegated to the United States by the
|
||
|
Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are
|
||
|
reserved to the States respectively, or to the people." U.S.
|
||
|
CONST. amend. X.
|
||
|
|
||
|
10. "Congress shall make no law ... prohibiting the free
|
||
|
exercise thereof [religion]...." U.S CONST. amend 1.
|
||
|
|
||
|
11. See supra note 8.
|
||
|
|
||
|
12. See supra note 9.
|
||
|
|
||
|
13. There are several law review articles discussing the
|
||
|
Amendment. See, e.g., Lund, supra note *, and the articles
|
||
|
cited in Dowlut & Knoop, State Constitutions and the Right
|
||
|
to Keep and Bear Arms, 7 OKLA. CITY U.L. REV. 177, 178 n.3
|
||
|
(1982). See also the valuable symposium on Gun Control,
|
||
|
edited by Don Kates, in 49 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 1-267
|
||
|
(1986), including articles by Shalhope, The Armed Citizen in
|
||
|
the Early Republic, at 125; Kates, The Second Amendment: A
|
||
|
Dialogue, at 143; Halbrook, What the Framers Intended: A
|
||
|
Linguistic Analysis of the Right to "Bear Arms," at 151. The
|
||
|
symposium also includes a valuable bibliography of published
|
||
|
materials on gun control, including Second Amendment
|
||
|
considerations, at 251-67. The most important single article
|
||
|
is almost undoubtedly Kates, Handgun Prohibition and the
|
||
|
Original Meaning of the Second Amendment, 82 MICH. L. REV.
|
||
|
204 (1983). Not the least significant aspect of Kates'
|
||
|
article is that it is basically the only one to have
|
||
|
appeared in an "elite" law review. However, like many of the
|
||
|
authors of other Second Amendment pieces, Kates is a
|
||
|
practicing lawyer rather than a legal academic. I think It
|
||
|
is accurate to say that no one recognized by the legal
|
||
|
academy as a "major" writer on constitutional law has
|
||
|
deigned to turn his or her talents to a full consideration
|
||
|
of the Amendment. But see LaRue, Constitutional Law and
|
||
|
Constitutional History, 36 BUFFALO L. REV. 373, 375-78
|
||
|
(1988) (briefly discussing Second Amendment). Akhil Reed
|
||
|
Amar's reconsideration of the foundations of the
|
||
|
Constitution also promises to delve more deeply into the
|
||
|
implications of the Amendment. See Amar, Of Sovereignty and
|
||
|
Federalism, 96 YALE L.J. 1425, 1495-1500 (1987). Finally,
|
||
|
there is one book that provides more in-depth treatment of
|
||
|
the Second Amendment: S. HALBROOK, THAT EVERY MAN BE ARMED,
|
||
|
THE EVOLUTION OF A CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT (1984).
|
||
|
|
||
|
George Fletcher, in his study of the Berhard Goetz case,
|
||
|
also suggests that Second Amendment analysis is not frivolous,
|
||
|
though he does not elaborate the point. G. FLETCHER, A CRIME OF
|
||
|
SELF-DEFENSE 156-58, 210-11 (1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
One might well find this overt reference to "elite" law
|
||
|
reviews and "major" writers objectionable, but it is foolish to
|
||
|
believe that these distinctions do not exist within the academy
|
||
|
or, more importantly, that we cannot learn about the sociology of
|
||
|
academic discourse through taking them into account. No one can
|
||
|
plausibly believe that the debates that define particular periods
|
||
|
of academic discourse are a simple reflection of "natural"
|
||
|
interest in the topic. Nothing helps an issue so much as its
|
||
|
being taken up as an obsession by a distinguished professor from,
|
||
|
say, Harvard or Yale.
|
||
|
|
||
|
14. One will search the "leading" casebooks in vain for any
|
||
|
mention of the Second Amendment. Other than its being
|
||
|
included in the text of the Constitution that all of the
|
||
|
casebooks reprint, a reader would have no reason to believe
|
||
|
that the Amendment exists or could possibly be of interest
|
||
|
to the constitutional analyst. I must include, alas, P.
|
||
|
BREST & S. LEVINSON, PROCESSES OF CONSTITUTIONAL DECISION
|
||
|
MAKING (2d ed. 1983), within this critique, though I have
|
||
|
every reason to believe that this will not be true of the
|
||
|
forthcoming third edition.
|
||
|
|
||
|
15. LaRue, supra note 13, at 375.
|
||
|
|
||
|
16. L. TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (2d ed. 1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
17. J. NOWAK, R. ROTUNDA & J. YOUNG, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (3d ed.
|
||
|
1986).
|
||
|
|
||
|
18. For a brilliant and playful meditation on the way the legal
|
||
|
world treats footnotes and other marginal phenomena, see
|
||
|
Balkin, The Footnote, 83 NW. U.L. REV. 275, 276-81 (1989).
|
||
|
|
||
|
19. TRIBE, supra note 16, at 299 n. 6.
|
||
|
|
||
|
20 Id.; see also J. ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 95 (1980)
|
||
|
("[T]he framers and ratifiers . . . opted against leaving to
|
||
|
the future the attribution Of [other] purposes, choosing
|
||
|
instead explicitly to legislate the goal in terms of which
|
||
|
the provision was to be interpreted."). As shall be seen
|
||
|
below, see infra text accompanying note 38, the preamble may
|
||
|
be less plain in its meaning than Tribe's (and Ely's)
|
||
|
confident argument suggests.
|
||
|
|
||
|
21. J. NOWAK, R. ROTUNDA & J. YOUNG, supra note 17, at 316 n.4.
|
||
|
They do go on to cite a spate of articles by scholars who
|
||
|
have debated the issue.
|
||
|
|
||
|
22. Id. at 316 n. 4.
|
||
|
|
||
|
23. U.S. CONST. art. I, 10.
|
||
|
|
||
|
24. U.S. CONST. art. I, 9, cl. 8.
|
||
|
|
||
|
25. See, e.g., LEGISLATIVE REFERENCE SERV., LIBRARY OF CONGRESS,
|
||
|
THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA: ANALYSIS
|
||
|
AND INTERPRETATION 923 (1964), which quotes the Amendment
|
||
|
and then a comment from MILLER, THE CONSTITUTION 646 (1893):
|
||
|
"This amendment seems to have been thought necessary. It
|
||
|
does not appear to have been the subject of judicial
|
||
|
exposition; and it is so thoroughly in accord with our
|
||
|
ideas, that further comment is unnecessary." Cf. Engblom v.
|
||
|
Carey, 724 F.2d 28 (2d Cir. 1983), aff'g 572 F. Supp. 44
|
||
|
(S.D.N.Y. 1983). Engblom grew out of a "statewide strike of
|
||
|
correction officers, when they were evicted from their
|
||
|
facility-residences . . . and members of the National Guard
|
||
|
were housed in their residences without their consent." The
|
||
|
district court had initially granted summary judgment for
|
||
|
the defendants in a suit brought by the officers claiming a
|
||
|
deprivation of their rights under the Third Amendment. The
|
||
|
Second Circuit, however, reversed on the ground that it
|
||
|
could not "say that as a matter of law appellants were not
|
||
|
entitled to the protection of the Third Amendment." Engblom
|
||
|
v. Carey, 677 F.2d 957, 964 (2d (Cir. 1982). The District
|
||
|
Court on remand held that, as the Third Amendment rights had
|
||
|
not been clearly established at the time of the strike, the
|
||
|
defendants were protected by a qualified immunity, and it is
|
||
|
this opinion that was upheld by the Second Circuit. I am
|
||
|
grateful to Mark Tushnet for bringing this case to my
|
||
|
attention.
|
||
|
|
||
|
26. See, e.g., The Firearms The Second Amendment Protects, N.Y.
|
||
|
Times, June 9, 1988, at A22, col. 2 (three letters); Second
|
||
|
Amendment and Gun Control, L.A. Times, March 11, 1989, Part
|
||
|
II, at 9 col. 1 (nine letters); What 'Right to Bear Arms'?,
|
||
|
N.Y. Times, July 20, 1989, at A23, col. 1 (national ed.)
|
||
|
(op. ed. essay by Daniel Abrams); see also We Rebelled To
|
||
|
Protect Our Gun Rights, Washington Times, July 20, 1989, at
|
||
|
F2, col. 4.
|
||
|
|
||
|
27. See SUBCOMMITTEE ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE COMM. ON THE
|
||
|
JUDICIARY, THE RIGHT TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS, 97th Cong., 2d
|
||
|
Sess. viii (1982) (preface by Senator Orrin Hatch)
|
||
|
[hereinafter THE RIGHT TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS].
|
||
|
|
||
|
28. See supra notes 13-14.
|
||
|
|
||
|
29. See Levinson, Constitutional Rhetoric and the Ninth
|
||
|
Amendment, 64 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 131 (1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
30. P. BOBBITT, CONSTITUTIONAL FATE (1982).
|
||
|
|
||
|
31. Id. at 25-38.
|
||
|
|
||
|
32. Id. at 9-24.
|
||
|
|
||
|
33. Id. at 74-92.
|
||
|
|
||
|
34. Id. at 39-58.
|
||
|
|
||
|
35. Id. at 59-73.
|
||
|
|
||
|
36. Id. at 93-119.
|
||
|
|
||
|
37. For the record, I should note that Bobbitt disagrees with
|
||
|
this statement, making an eloquent appeal (in conversation)
|
||
|
on behalf of the classic American value of self-reliance for
|
||
|
the defense of oneself and, perhaps more importantly, one's
|
||
|
family. I certainly do not doubt the possibility of
|
||
|
constructing an "ethical" rationale for limiting the state's
|
||
|
power to prohibit private gun ownership. Nonetheless, I
|
||
|
would claim that no one unpersuaded by any of the arguments
|
||
|
derived from the first five modes would suddenly change his
|
||
|
or her mind upon being presented with an "ethical" argument.
|
||
|
|
||
|
38. Cf., e.g., the patents and copyrights clause, which sets out
|
||
|
the power of Congress "[t]o promote the Progress of Science
|
||
|
and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors
|
||
|
and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective
|
||
|
Writings and Discoveries." U.S. CONST. art. I., 8.
|
||
|
|
||
|
39. For examples of this, see F. SCHAUER, FREEDOM OF SPEECH: A
|
||
|
PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIRY (1982); Levinson, First Amendment,
|
||
|
Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Expression: Does It Matter
|
||
|
What We Call It? 80 NW. U.L. REV. 767 (1985) (reviewing M.
|
||
|
REDISH, FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS (1984)).
|
||
|
|
||
|
40. ACLU Policy #47. I am grateful to Joan Mahoney, a member of
|
||
|
the national board of the ACLU, for providing me with a text
|
||
|
of the ACLU's current policy on gun control.
|
||
|
|
||
|
41. Cress, An Armed Community: The Origins and Meaning of the
|
||
|
Right to Bear Arms, 71 J. AM. HIST. 22, 31 (1984).
|
||
|
|
||
|
42. See U.S. CONST. amend. X.
|
||
|
|
||
|
43. For a full articulation of the the [sic] individualist view
|
||
|
of the Second Amendment, see Kates, Handgun Prohibition and
|
||
|
the Original Meaning of the Second Amendment, 82 MICH. L.
|
||
|
REV. 204 (1983). One can also find an efficient presentation
|
||
|
of this view in Lund, supra note *, at 117.
|
||
|
|
||
|
44. Shalhope, The Ideological Origins of the Second Amendment,
|
||
|
69 J. AM. HIST. 599 (1982).
|
||
|
|
||
|
45. Id. at 614.
|
||
|
|
||
|
46. See Daniel Boorstin's laconic comment that "the requirements
|
||
|
for self-defense and food gathering had put firearms in the
|
||
|
hands of nearly everyone" in colonial America. D. BOORSTIN,
|
||
|
THE AMERICANS--THE COLONIAL EXPERIENCE 353 (1958). The
|
||
|
beginnings of a professional police force in Boston are
|
||
|
traced in R. LANE, POLICING THE CITY: BOSTON 1822-1855
|
||
|
(1967). Lane argues that as of the earlier of his two dates,
|
||
|
"all the major eastern cities . . . had several kinds of
|
||
|
officials serving various police functions, all of them
|
||
|
haphazardly inherited from the British and colonial past.
|
||
|
These agents were gradually drawn into better defined and
|
||
|
more coherent organizations." Id. at 1. However, as Oscar
|
||
|
Handlin points out in his introduction to the book, "to
|
||
|
bring into being a professional police force was to create
|
||
|
precisely the kind of hireling body considered dangerous by
|
||
|
conventional political theory." Id. at vii.
|
||
|
|
||
|
47. See Cress, supra note 41.
|
||
|
|
||
|
48. 3 J. ELLIOT, DEBATES IN THE GENERAL STATE CONVENTIONS 425
|
||
|
(3d ed. 1937) (statement of George Mason, June 14, 1788),
|
||
|
reprinted in Kates, supra note 13, at 216 n.51.
|
||
|
|
||
|
49. LETTERS FROM THE FEDERAL FARMER TO THE REPUBLICAN 123 (W.
|
||
|
Bennett ed. 1978) (ascribed to Richard Henry Lee), reprinted
|
||
|
in Kates, supra note 13, at 216 n. 51.
|
||
|
|
||
|
50. Michelman, The Supreme Court 1985 Term--Foreword: Traces of
|
||
|
Self-Government, 100 HARV. L. REV. 4, 39 (1986) (Harrington
|
||
|
is "pivotal figure in the history of the 'Atlantic' branch
|
||
|
of republicanism that would find its way to America").
|
||
|
|
||
|
51. Shalhope, supra note 44, at 602.
|
||
|
|
||
|
52. Edmund Morgan discusses Harrington in his recent book,
|
||
|
INVENTING THE PEOPLE 85-87 (1988) (analyzing notion of
|
||
|
popular sovereignty in American thought).
|
||
|
|
||
|
53. Id. at 156.
|
||
|
|
||
|
54. Id. at 157. Morgan argues, incidentally, that the armed
|
||
|
yeomanry was neither effective as a fighting force nor
|
||
|
particularly protective of popular liberty, but that is
|
||
|
another matter. For our purposes, the ideological
|
||
|
perceptions are surely more important than the "reality"
|
||
|
accompanying them. Id. at 160-65.
|
||
|
|
||
|
55. Blasi, The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory, 1977
|
||
|
AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 521.
|
||
|
|
||
|
56. See Lund, supra note *, at 111-16.
|
||
|
|
||
|
57. Shalhope, supra note 44, at 603 (quoting 1755 edition of
|
||
|
Cato's Letters). Shalhope also quotes from James Burgh,
|
||
|
another English writer well known to American
|
||
|
revolutionaries: The possession of arms is the distinction
|
||
|
between a freeman and a slave. He, who has nothing, and who
|
||
|
himself belongs to another, must be defended by him, whose
|
||
|
property he is, and needs no arms. But he, who thinks he is
|
||
|
his own master, and has what he can call his own, ought to
|
||
|
have arms to defend himself, and what he possesses; else he
|
||
|
lives precariously, and at discretion.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Id. at 604. To be sure, Burgh also wrote that only men of
|
||
|
property should in fact comprise the militia: "A militia
|
||
|
consisting of any others than the men of *property* in a country,
|
||
|
is no militia; but a mungrel army." Cress, supra note 41, at 27
|
||
|
(emphasis in original) (quoting J. BURGH, 2 POLITICAL
|
||
|
DISQUISITIONS: OR, AN ENQUIRY INTO PUBLIC ERRORS, DEFECTS, AND
|
||
|
ABUSES (1774-75). Presumably, though, the widespread distribution
|
||
|
of property would bring with it equally widespread access to arms
|
||
|
and membership in the militia.
|
||
|
|
||
|
58. See Cress, supra note 41, at 34.
|
||
|
|
||
|
59. THE FEDERALIST NO. 46, at 299 (J. Madison) (C. Rossiter ed.
|
||
|
1961).
|
||
|
|
||
|
60. LETTERS FROM THE FEDERAL FARMER TO THE REPUBLICAN 124 (W.
|
||
|
Bennett ed. 1978).
|
||
|
|
||
|
61. 3 J. STORY, COMMENTARIES 1890 (1833), quoted in 5 THE
|
||
|
FOUNDERS' CONSTITUTION 214 (P. Kurland & R. Lerner eds.
|
||
|
1987).
|
||
|
|
||
|
62. Id.
|
||
|
|
||
|
63. Id. Lawrence Cress, despite his forceful critique of
|
||
|
Shalhope's individualist rendering of the Second Amendment,
|
||
|
nonetheless himself notes that "[t]he danger posed by
|
||
|
manipulating demagogues, *ambitious rulers*, and foreign
|
||
|
invaders to free institutions required the vigilance of
|
||
|
citizen-soldiers cognizant of the common good." Cress, supra
|
||
|
note 41, at 41 (emphasis added).
|
||
|
|
||
|
64. T. COOLEY, THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW IN
|
||
|
THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 298 (3d ed. 1898): The right of
|
||
|
the people to bear arms in their own defence, and to form
|
||
|
and drill military organizations in defence of the State,
|
||
|
may not be very important in this country, but it is
|
||
|
significant as having been reserved by the people as a
|
||
|
possible and necessary resort for the protection of self-
|
||
|
government against usurpation, and against any attempt on
|
||
|
the part of those who may for the time be in possession of
|
||
|
State authority or resources to set aside the constitution
|
||
|
and substitute their own rule for that of the people. Should
|
||
|
the contingency ever arise when it would be necessary for
|
||
|
the people to make use of the arms in their hands for the
|
||
|
protection of constitutional liberty, the proceeding, so far
|
||
|
from being revolutionary, would be in strict accord with
|
||
|
popular right and duty. Cooley advanced this same idea in
|
||
|
The Abnegation of Self-Government, 12 PRINCETON REV. 213-14
|
||
|
(1883).
|
||
|
|
||
|
65. See Rabban, The First Amendment in Its Forgotten Years, 90
|
||
|
YALE L.J. 514, 560 (1981) ("[P]rodigious theoretical
|
||
|
writings of Theodore Schroeder . . . were the most extensive
|
||
|
and libertarian treatments of freedom of speech in the
|
||
|
prewar period"); see also GRABER, TRANSFORMING FREE SPEECH
|
||
|
(forthcoming 1990) (manuscript at 4-12; on file with
|
||
|
author).
|
||
|
|
||
|
66. T. SCHROEDER, FREE SPEECH FOR RADICALS 104 (reprint ed.
|
||
|
1969).
|
||
|
|
||
|
67. Shalhope, supra note 44, at 45.
|
||
|
|
||
|
68. See M. WEBER, THE THEORY OF SOCIAL AND ECONOMIC ORGANIZATION
|
||
|
156 (T. Parsons ed. 1947), where he lists among "[t]he
|
||
|
primary formal characteristics of the modern state" the fact
|
||
|
that: to-day, the use of force is regarded as legitimate
|
||
|
only so far as it is either permitted by the state or
|
||
|
prescribed by it .... The claim of the modern state to
|
||
|
monopolize the use of force is as essential to it as its
|
||
|
character of compulsory jurisdiction and of continuous
|
||
|
organization.
|
||
|
|
||
|
69. See, e.g., Symposium: The Republican Civil Tradition, 97
|
||
|
YALE L.J. 1493-1723 (1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
70. See D. MALONE, 4 JEFFERSON AND HIS TIMES: JEFFERSON THE
|
||
|
PRESIDENT: FIRST TERM, 1801-1805, at 7-11 (1970) (republican
|
||
|
leaders ready to use state militias to resist should lame
|
||
|
duck Congress attempt to violate clear dictates of Article
|
||
|
II by designating someone other than Thomas Jefferson as
|
||
|
President in 1801).
|
||
|
|
||
|
71. Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393, 417 (1857).
|
||
|
|
||
|
72. See, e.g., Featherstone, Gardiner & Dowlut, The Second
|
||
|
Amendment to the United States Constitution Guarantees an
|
||
|
Individual Right to Keep and Bear Arms, in THE RIGHT TO KEEP
|
||
|
AND BEAR ARMS, supra note 27, at 100.
|
||
|
|
||
|
73. See, e.g., Halbrook, The Fourteenth Amendment and the Right
|
||
|
to Keep and Bear Arms: The Intent of the Framers, in THE
|
||
|
RIGHT TO KEEP AND BEAR ARMS, supra note 27, at 79. Not the
|
||
|
least of the ironies observed in the debate about the Second
|
||
|
Amendment is that N.R.A.-oriented conservatives like Senator
|
||
|
Hatch could scarcely have been happy with the wholesale
|
||
|
attack leveled by former Attorney General Meese on the
|
||
|
incorporation doctrine, for here is one area where some
|
||
|
"conservatives" may in fact be more zealous adherents of
|
||
|
that doctrine than are most liberals, who, at least where
|
||
|
the Second Amendment is concerned, have a considerably more
|
||
|
selective view of incorporation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
74. 83 U.S. 36 (1873).
|
||
|
|
||
|
75. 32 U.S. (7 Pet.) 243 (1833).
|
||
|
|
||
|
76. 92 U.S. 542, 553 (1875).
|
||
|
|
||
|
77. 116 U.S. 252, 267 (1886). For a fascinating discussion of
|
||
|
Presser, see Larue, supra note 13, at 386-90.
|
||
|
|
||
|
78. 116 U.S. at 253. There is good reason to believe this
|
||
|
statute, passed by the Illinois legislature in 1879, was
|
||
|
part of an effort to control (and, indeed, suppress)
|
||
|
widespread labor unrest linked to the economic troubles of
|
||
|
the time. For the background of the Illinois statute, see P.
|
||
|
AVRICH, THE HAYMARKET TRAGEDY 45 (1984):
|
||
|
|
||
|
79. 166 U.S. 226 (1897) (protecting rights of property owners by
|
||
|
requiring compensation for takings of property).
|
||
|
|
||
|
As early as 1875, a small group of Chicago socialists, most
|
||
|
of them German immigrants, had formed an armed club to protect
|
||
|
the workers against police and military assaults, as well as
|
||
|
against physical intimidation at the polls. In the eyes of its
|
||
|
supporters . . . the need for such a group was amply demonstrated
|
||
|
by the behavior of the police and [state-controlled] militia
|
||
|
during the Great Strike of 1877, a national protest by labor
|
||
|
triggered by a ten percent cut in wages by the Baltimore and Ohio
|
||
|
Railroad, which included the breaking up of workers' meetings,
|
||
|
the arrest of socialist leaders, [and] the use of club, pistol,
|
||
|
and bayonet against strikers and their supporters .... Workers
|
||
|
... were resolved never again to be shot and beaten without
|
||
|
resistance. Nor would they stand idly by while their meeting
|
||
|
places were invaded or their wives and children assaulted. They
|
||
|
were determined, as Albert Parsons [a leader of the anarchist
|
||
|
movement in Chicago] expressed it, to defend both "their persons
|
||
|
and their rights."
|
||
|
|
||
|
80. My colleague Douglas Laycock has reminded me that a similar
|
||
|
argument was made by some conservatives in regard to the
|
||
|
establishment clause of the First Amendment. Thus, Justice
|
||
|
Brennan noted that "[it] has been suggested, with some
|
||
|
support in history, that absorption of the First Amendment's
|
||
|
ban against congressional legislation 'respecting an
|
||
|
establishment of religion' is conceptually impossible
|
||
|
because the Framers meant the Establishment Clause also to
|
||
|
foreclose any attempt by Congress to *disestablish* the
|
||
|
existing official state churches." Abington School Dist. v.
|
||
|
Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 254 (1963) (Brennan, J., concurring)
|
||
|
(emphasis added). According to this reading, it would be
|
||
|
illogical to apply the establishment clause against the
|
||
|
states "because that clause is not one of the provisions of
|
||
|
the Bill of Rights which in terms protects a 'freedom' of
|
||
|
the individual," id. at 256, inasmuch as it is only a
|
||
|
federalist protection of states against a national
|
||
|
establishment (or disestablishment). "The fallacy in this
|
||
|
contention," responds Brennan, "is that it underestimates
|
||
|
the role of the Establishment Clause as a co-guarantor, with
|
||
|
the Free Exercise Clause, of religious liberty." Id.
|
||
|
Whatever the sometimes bitter debates about the precise
|
||
|
meaning of "establishment," it is surely the case that
|
||
|
Justice Brennan, even as he almost cheerfully concedes that
|
||
|
at one point in our history the "states-right" reading of
|
||
|
the establishment clause would have been thoroughly
|
||
|
plausible, expresses what has become the generally accepted
|
||
|
view as to the establishment clause being some kind of
|
||
|
limitation on the state as well as on the national
|
||
|
government. One may wonder whether the interpretive history
|
||
|
of the establishment clause might have any lessons for the
|
||
|
interpretation of the Second Amendment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
81. It refused, for example, to review the most important modern
|
||
|
gun control case, Quilici v. Village Of Morton Grove, 695
|
||
|
F.2d 261 (7th Cir. 1982), cert. denied, 464 U.S. 863 (1983),
|
||
|
where the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals upheld a local
|
||
|
ordinance in Morton Grove, Illinois, prohibiting the
|
||
|
possession of handguns within its borders.
|
||
|
|
||
|
82. 307 U.S. 174 (1939).
|
||
|
|
||
|
83. Justice Douglas, however, did not participate in the case.
|
||
|
|
||
|
84. Miller, 307 U.S. at 178.
|
||
|
|
||
|
85. Id. at 178 (citation omitted).
|
||
|
|
||
|
86. Lund notes that "commentators have since demonstrated that
|
||
|
sawed-off or short-barreled shotguns are commonly used as
|
||
|
military weapons." Lund, supra note *, at 109.
|
||
|
|
||
|
87. 307 U.S. at 178.
|
||
|
|
||
|
88. Id. at 179.
|
||
|
|
||
|
89. Id.
|
||
|
|
||
|
90. L. Powell, Capital Punishment, Remarks Delivered to the
|
||
|
Criminal Justice Section, ABA 10 (Aug. 7, 1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
91. Id . at 11.
|
||
|
|
||
|
92. This point is presumably demonstrated by the increasing
|
||
|
public opposition of police officials to private possession
|
||
|
of handguns (not to mention assault rifles).
|
||
|
|
||
|
93. D. Kates, Minimalist Interpretation of the Second Amendment
|
||
|
2 (draft Sept. 29, 1986) (unpublished manuscript available
|
||
|
from author).
|
||
|
|
||
|
94. See Lund, supra note *, at 116.
|
||
|
|
||
|
95. Wimmershoff-Caplan, The Founders and The AK-47, Washington
|
||
|
Post, July 6, 1989, at A18, col. 4, reprinted as Price of
|
||
|
Gun Deaths Small Compared to Price of Liberty, Austin
|
||
|
American-Statesman, July 11, 1989, at All. Ms. Wimmershoff-
|
||
|
Caplan is identified as a "lawyer in New York" who is "a
|
||
|
member of the National Board of the National Rifle
|
||
|
Association." Id. One of the first such arguments in regard
|
||
|
to the events at Tianamen Square was made by William A.
|
||
|
Black in a letter, Citizens Without Guns, N.Y. Times, June
|
||
|
18, 1989 at D26, col. 6. Though describing himself as
|
||
|
"find[ing] no glory in guns [and] a very profound anti-
|
||
|
hunter," he nonetheless "stand[s] with those who would
|
||
|
protect our right to keep and bear arms" and cited for
|
||
|
support the fact that "none [of the Chinese soldiers] feared
|
||
|
bullets: the citizens of China were long ago disarmed by the
|
||
|
Communists." "Who knows," he asks, "what the leaders and the
|
||
|
military and the police of our America will be up to at some
|
||
|
point in the future? We need an armed citizenry to protect
|
||
|
our liberty."
|
||
|
|
||
|
As one might expect, such arguments draw heated responses.
|
||
|
See Rudlin, The Founders and the AK-47 (Cont'd), Washington Post,
|
||
|
July 20, 1989, at A22, col. 3. Jonathan Rudlin accused Ms.
|
||
|
Wimmershoff-Caplan of engaging in Swiftian satire, as no one
|
||
|
could "take such brilliant burlesque seriously." Neal Knox,
|
||
|
however, endorsed her essay in full, adding the Holocaust to the
|
||
|
list of examples: "Could the Holocaust have occurred if Europe's
|
||
|
Jews had owned thousands of then-modern military Mauser bolt
|
||
|
action rifles?" See also Washington Post, July 12, 1989, at A22,
|
||
|
for other letters.
|
||
|
|
||
|
96. See Lund, supra note *, at 115: The decision to use military
|
||
|
force is not determined solely by whether the contemplated
|
||
|
benefits can be successfully obtained through the use of
|
||
|
available forces, but rather is determined by the ratio of
|
||
|
those benefits to the expected costs. It follows that any
|
||
|
factor increasing the anticipated cost of a military
|
||
|
operation makes the conduct of that operation incrementally
|
||
|
more unlikely. This explains why a relatively poorly armed
|
||
|
nation with a small population recently prevailed in a war
|
||
|
against the United States, and it explains why governments
|
||
|
bent on the oppression of their people almost always disarm
|
||
|
the civilian population before undertaking more drastically
|
||
|
oppressive measures.
|
||
|
|
||
|
97. See D. Kates, supra note 93, at 24-25 n.13, for a discussion
|
||
|
of this point.
|
||
|
|
||
|
98. See, e.g., Justice Marshall's dissent, joined by Justice
|
||
|
Brennan, in Skinner v. Railway Labor Executive Ass'n, 109 S.
|
||
|
Ct. 1402 (1989), upholding the government's right to require
|
||
|
drug tests of railroad employees following accidents. It
|
||
|
begins with his chastising the majority for "ignor[ing] the
|
||
|
text and doctrinal history of the Fourth Amendment, which
|
||
|
require that highly intrusive searches of this type be based
|
||
|
on probable cause, not on the evanescent cost-benefit
|
||
|
calculations of agencies or judges," id. at 1423, and
|
||
|
continues by arguing that "[t]he majority's concern with the
|
||
|
railroad safety problems caused by drug and alcohol abuse is
|
||
|
laudable; its cavalier disregard for the Constitution is
|
||
|
not. There is no drug exception to the Constitution, any
|
||
|
more than there is a communism exception or an exception for
|
||
|
other real or imagined sources of domestic unrest." Id. at
|
||
|
1426.
|
||
|
|
||
|
99. Donaldson, Letter to the Editor, Austin American-Statesman,
|
||
|
July 8, 1989, at A19, col. 4.
|
||
|
|
||
|
100. See Minow, The Supreme Court 1986 Term--Foreword: Justice
|
||
|
Engendered, 101 HARV. L. REV. 10, 74-90 (1987). "We need
|
||
|
settings in which to engage in the clash of realities that
|
||
|
breaks us out of settled and complacent meanings and creates
|
||
|
opportunities for insight and growth." Id. at 95; see also
|
||
|
Getman, Voices, 66 TEX. L. REV. 577 (1988).
|
||
|
|
||
|
101. And, perhaps more to the point, "you" who insufficiently
|
||
|
listen to "us" and to "our" favored groups.
|
||
|
|
||
|
102. See supra note 27 and accompanying text.
|
||
|
|
||
|
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
|
||
|
|
||
|
Note from the Combat Arms BBS SysOp:
|
||
|
|
||
|
This concludes the article. Each of the references in the
|
||
|
appendix is noted within the text by brackets (such as [23]).
|
||
|
Reading this article, along with many others on the Combat Arms
|
||
|
BBS, should help you to better understand the Second Amendment
|
||
|
and be better skilled in arguing its support. Other articles are
|
||
|
also available for downloading that you should carefully read as
|
||
|
well. Lastly, if you do not already have a copy of "That Every
|
||
|
Man Be Armed" by Stephen P. Holbrook, get a copy. The cost is
|
||
|
$14.95. This book will provide you with a lot of background on
|
||
|
the Second Amendment. You are also invited to download a copy
|
||
|
of my master's thesis. The file is entitled BASH.ZIP and contains
|
||
|
a lot of research on the Second Amendment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
Richard Bash
|
||
|
Combat Arms BBS SysOp
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
Bulletins updated: 13
|
||
|
Enter bulletin # [1..44], [R]elist menu, [N]ew, [ENTER] to quit? [ ]
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
X-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-X
|
||
|
Another file downloaded from: The NIRVANAnet(tm) Seven
|
||
|
|
||
|
& the Temple of the Screaming Electron Taipan Enigma 510/935-5845
|
||
|
Burn This Flag Zardoz 408/363-9766
|
||
|
realitycheck Poindexter Fortran 510/527-1662
|
||
|
Lies Unlimited Mick Freen 801/278-2699
|
||
|
The New Dork Sublime Biffnix 415/864-DORK
|
||
|
The Shrine Rif Raf 206/794-6674
|
||
|
Planet Mirth Simon Jester 510/786-6560
|
||
|
|
||
|
"Raw Data for Raw Nerves"
|
||
|
X-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-X
|