4064 lines
231 KiB
Plaintext
4064 lines
231 KiB
Plaintext
![]() |
350 BC
|
||
|
|
||
|
METEOROLOGY
|
||
|
|
||
|
by Aristotle
|
||
|
|
||
|
translated by E. W. Webster
|
||
|
|
||
|
Book I
|
||
|
|
||
|
1
|
||
|
|
||
|
WE have already discussed the first causes of nature, and all
|
||
|
natural motion, also the stars ordered in the motion of the heavens,
|
||
|
and the physical element-enumerating and specifying them and showing
|
||
|
how they change into one another-and becoming and perishing in
|
||
|
general. There remains for consideration a part of this inquiry
|
||
|
which all our predecessors called meteorology. It is concerned with
|
||
|
events that are natural, though their order is less perfect than
|
||
|
that of the first of the elements of bodies. They take place in the
|
||
|
region nearest to the motion of the stars. Such are the milky way, and
|
||
|
comets, and the movements of meteors. It studies also all the
|
||
|
affections we may call common to air and water, and the kinds and
|
||
|
parts of the earth and the affections of its parts. These throw
|
||
|
light on the causes of winds and earthquakes and all the
|
||
|
consequences the motions of these kinds and parts involve. Of these
|
||
|
things some puzzle us, while others admit of explanation in some
|
||
|
degree. Further, the inquiry is concerned with the falling of
|
||
|
thunderbolts and with whirlwinds and fire-winds, and further, the
|
||
|
recurrent affections produced in these same bodies by concretion. When
|
||
|
the inquiry into these matters is concluded let us consider what
|
||
|
account we can give, in accordance with the method we have followed,
|
||
|
of animals and plants, both generally and in detail. When that has
|
||
|
been done we may say that the whole of our original undertaking will
|
||
|
have been carried out.
|
||
|
|
||
|
After this introduction let us begin by discussing our immediate
|
||
|
subject.
|
||
|
|
||
|
2
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have already laid down that there is one physical element which
|
||
|
makes up the system of the bodies that move in a circle, and besides
|
||
|
this four bodies owing their existence to the four principles, the
|
||
|
motion of these latter bodies being of two kinds: either from the
|
||
|
centre or to the centre. These four bodies are fire, air, water,
|
||
|
earth. Fire occupies the highest place among them all, earth the
|
||
|
lowest, and two elements correspond to these in their relation to
|
||
|
one another, air being nearest to fire, water to earth. The whole
|
||
|
world surrounding the earth, then, the affections of which are our
|
||
|
subject, is made up of these bodies. This world necessarily has a
|
||
|
certain continuity with the upper motions: consequently all its
|
||
|
power and order is derived from them. (For the originating principle
|
||
|
of all motion is the first cause. Besides, that clement is eternal and
|
||
|
its motion has no limit in space, but is always complete; whereas
|
||
|
all these other bodies have separate regions which limit one another.)
|
||
|
So we must treat fire and earth and the elements like them as the
|
||
|
material causes of the events in this world (meaning by material
|
||
|
what is subject and is affected), but must assign causality in the
|
||
|
sense of the originating principle of motion to the influence of the
|
||
|
eternally moving bodies.
|
||
|
|
||
|
3
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us first recall our original principles and the distinctions
|
||
|
already drawn and then explain the 'milky way' and comets and the
|
||
|
other phenomena akin to these.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Fire, air, water, earth, we assert, originate from one another,
|
||
|
and each of them exists potentially in each, as all things do that can
|
||
|
be resolved into a common and ultimate substrate.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The first difficulty is raised by what is called the air. What are
|
||
|
we to take its nature to be in the world surrounding the earth? And
|
||
|
what is its position relatively to the other physical elements. (For
|
||
|
there is no question as to the relation of the bulk of the earth to
|
||
|
the size of the bodies which exist around it, since astronomical
|
||
|
demonstrations have by this time proved to us that it is actually
|
||
|
far smaller than some individual stars. As for the water, it is not
|
||
|
observed to exist collectively and separately, nor can it do so
|
||
|
apart from that volume of it which has its seat about the earth: the
|
||
|
sea, that is, and rivers, which we can see, and any subterranean water
|
||
|
that may be hidden from our observation.) The question is really about
|
||
|
that which lies between the earth and the nearest stars. Are we to
|
||
|
consider it to be one kind of body or more than one? And if more
|
||
|
than one, how many are there and what are the bounds of their regions?
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have already described and characterized the first element, and
|
||
|
explained that the whole world of the upper motions is full of that
|
||
|
body.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This is an opinion we are not alone in holding: it appears to be
|
||
|
an old assumption and one which men have held in the past, for the
|
||
|
word ether has long been used to denote that element. Anaxagoras, it
|
||
|
is true, seems to me to think that the word means the same as fire.
|
||
|
For he thought that the upper regions were full of fire, and that
|
||
|
men referred to those regions when they spoke of ether. In the
|
||
|
latter point he was right, for men seem to have assumed that a body
|
||
|
that was eternally in motion was also divine in nature; and, as such a
|
||
|
body was different from any of the terrestrial elements, they
|
||
|
determined to call it 'ether'.
|
||
|
|
||
|
For the um opinions appear in cycles among men not once nor twice,
|
||
|
but infinitely often.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now there are some who maintain that not only the bodies in motion
|
||
|
but that which contains them is pure fire, and the interval between
|
||
|
the earth and the stars air: but if they had considered what is now
|
||
|
satisfactorily established by mathematics, they might have given up
|
||
|
this puerile opinion. For it is altogether childish to suppose that
|
||
|
the moving bodies are all of them of a small size, because they so
|
||
|
to us, looking at them from the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This a matter which we have already discussed in our treatment of
|
||
|
the upper region, but we may return to the point now.
|
||
|
|
||
|
If the intervals were full of fire and the bodies consisted of
|
||
|
fire every one of the other elements would long ago have vanished.
|
||
|
|
||
|
However, they cannot simply be said to be full of air either; for
|
||
|
even if there were two elements to fill the space between the earth
|
||
|
and the heavens, the air would far exceed the quantitu required to
|
||
|
maintain its proper proportion to the other elements. For the bulk
|
||
|
of the earth (which includes the whole volume of water) is
|
||
|
infinitesimal in comparison with the whole world that surrounds it.
|
||
|
Now we find that the excess in volume is not proportionately great
|
||
|
where water dissolves into air or air into fire. Whereas the
|
||
|
proportion between any given small quantity of water and the air
|
||
|
that is generated from it ought to hold good between the total
|
||
|
amount of air and the total amount of water. Nor does it make any
|
||
|
difference if any one denies that the elements originate from one
|
||
|
another, but asserts that they are equal in power. For on this view it
|
||
|
is certain amounts of each that are equal in power, just as would be
|
||
|
the case if they actually originated from one another.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So it is clear that neither air nor fire alone fills the
|
||
|
intermediate space.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It remains to explain, after a preliminary discussion of
|
||
|
difficulties, the relation of the two elements air and fire to the
|
||
|
position of the first element, and the reason why the stars in the
|
||
|
upper region impart heat to the earth and its neighbourhood. Let us
|
||
|
first treat of the air, as we proposed, and then go on to these
|
||
|
questions.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since water is generated from air, and air from water, why are
|
||
|
clouds not formed in the upper air? They ought to form there the more,
|
||
|
the further from the earth and the colder that region is. For it is
|
||
|
neither appreciably near to the heat of the stars, nor to the rays
|
||
|
relected from the earth. It is these that dissolve any formation by
|
||
|
their heat and so prevent clouds from forming near the earth. For
|
||
|
clouds gather at the point where the reflected rays disperse in the
|
||
|
infinity of space and are lost. To explain this we must suppose either
|
||
|
that it is not all air which water is generated, or, if it is produced
|
||
|
from all air alike, that what immediately surrounds the earth is not
|
||
|
mere air, but a sort of vapour, and that its vaporous nature is the
|
||
|
reason why it condenses back to water again. But if the whole of
|
||
|
that vast region is vapour, the amount of air and of water will be
|
||
|
disproportionately great. For the spaces left by the heavenly bodies
|
||
|
must be filled by some element. This cannot be fire, for then all
|
||
|
the rest would have been dried up. Consequently, what fills it must be
|
||
|
air and the water that surrounds the whole earth-vapour being water
|
||
|
dissolved.
|
||
|
|
||
|
After this exposition of the difficulties involved, let us go on
|
||
|
to lay down the truth, with a view at once to what follows and to what
|
||
|
has already been said. The upper region as far as the moon we affirm
|
||
|
to consist of a body distinct both from fire and from air, but varying
|
||
|
degree of purity and in kind, especially towards its limit on the side
|
||
|
of the air, and of the world surrounding the earth. Now the circular
|
||
|
motion of the first element and of the bodies it contains dissolves,
|
||
|
and inflames by its motion, whatever part of the lower world is
|
||
|
nearest to it, and so generates heat. From another point of view we
|
||
|
may look at the motion as follows. The body that lies below the
|
||
|
circular motion of the heavens is, in a sort, matter, and is
|
||
|
potentially hot, cold, dry, moist, and possessed of whatever other
|
||
|
qualities are derived from these. But it actually acquires or
|
||
|
retains one of these in virtue of motion or rest, the cause and
|
||
|
principle of which has already been explained. So at the centre and
|
||
|
round it we get earth and water, the heaviest and coldest elements, by
|
||
|
themselves; round them and contiguous with them, air and what we
|
||
|
commonly call fire. It is not really fire, for fire is an excess of
|
||
|
heat and a sort of ebullition; but in reality, of what we call air,
|
||
|
the part surrounding the earth is moist and warm, because it
|
||
|
contains both vapour and a dry exhalation from the earth. But the next
|
||
|
part, above that, is warm and dry. For vapour is naturally moist and
|
||
|
cold, but the exhalation warm and dry; and vapour is potentially
|
||
|
like water, the exhalation potentially like fire. So we must take
|
||
|
the reason why clouds are not formed in the upper region to be this:
|
||
|
that it is filled not with mere air but rather with a sort of fire.
|
||
|
|
||
|
However, it may well be that the formation of clouds in that upper
|
||
|
region is also prevented by the circular motion. For the air round the
|
||
|
earth is necessarily all of it in motion, except that which is cut off
|
||
|
inside the circumference which makes the earth a complete sphere. In
|
||
|
the case of winds it is actually observable that they originate in
|
||
|
marshy districts of the earth; and they do not seem to blow above
|
||
|
the level of the highest mountains. It is the revolution of the heaven
|
||
|
which carries the air with it and causes its circular motion, fire
|
||
|
being continuous with the upper element and air with fire. Thus its
|
||
|
motion is a second reason why that air is not condensed into water.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But whenever a particle of air grows heavy, the warmth in it is
|
||
|
squeezed out into the upper region and it sinks, and other particles
|
||
|
in turn are carried up together with the fiery exhalation. Thus the
|
||
|
one region is always full of air and the other of fire, and each of
|
||
|
them is perpetually in a state of change.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much to explain why clouds are not formed and why the air is
|
||
|
not condensed into water, and what account must be given of the
|
||
|
space between the stars and the earth, and what is the body that fills
|
||
|
it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
As for the heat derived from the sun, the right place for a
|
||
|
special and scientific account of it is in the treatise about sense,
|
||
|
since heat is an affection of sense, but we may now explain how it can
|
||
|
be produced by the heavenly bodies which are not themselves hot.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We see that motion is able to dissolve and inflame the air;
|
||
|
indeed, moving bodies are often actually found to melt. Now the
|
||
|
sun's motion alone is sufficient to account for the origin of
|
||
|
terrestrial warmth and heat. For a motion that is to have this
|
||
|
effect must be rapid and near, and that of the stars is rapid but
|
||
|
distant, while that of the moon is near but slow, whereas the sun's
|
||
|
motion combines both conditions in a sufficient degree. That most heat
|
||
|
should be generated where the sun is present is easy to understand
|
||
|
if we consider the analogy of terrestrial phenomena, for here, too, it
|
||
|
is the air that is nearest to a thing in rapid motion which is
|
||
|
heated most. This is just what we should expect, as it is the
|
||
|
nearest air that is most dissolved by the motion of a solid body.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This then is one reason why heat reaches our world. Another is
|
||
|
that the fire surrounding the air is often scattered by the motion
|
||
|
of the heavens and driven downwards in spite of itself.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Shooting-stars further suffix to prove that the celestial sphere
|
||
|
is not hot or fiery: for they do not occur in that upper region but
|
||
|
below: yet the more and the faster a thing moves, the more apt it is
|
||
|
to take fire. Besides, the sun, which most of all the stars is
|
||
|
considered to be hot, is really white and not fiery in colour.
|
||
|
|
||
|
4
|
||
|
|
||
|
Having determined these principles let us explain the cause of the
|
||
|
appearance in the sky of burning flames and of shooting-stars, and
|
||
|
of 'torches', and 'goats', as some people call them. All these
|
||
|
phenomena are one and the same thing, and are due to the same cause,
|
||
|
the difference between them being one of degree.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The explanation of these and many other phenomena is this. When
|
||
|
the sun warms the earth the evaporation which takes place is
|
||
|
necessarily of two kinds, not of one only as some think. One kind is
|
||
|
rather of the nature of vapour, the other of the nature of a windy
|
||
|
exhalation. That which rises from the moisture contained in the
|
||
|
earth and on its surface is vapour, while that rising from the earth
|
||
|
itself, which is dry, is like smoke. Of these the windy exhalation,
|
||
|
being warm, rises above the moister vapour, which is heavy and sinks
|
||
|
below the other. Hence the world surrounding the earth is ordered as
|
||
|
follows. First below the circular motion comes the warm and dry
|
||
|
element, which we call fire, for there is no word fully adequate to
|
||
|
every state of the fumid evaporation: but we must use this terminology
|
||
|
since this element is the most inflammable of all bodies. Below this
|
||
|
comes air. We must think of what we just called fire as being spread
|
||
|
round the terrestrial sphere on the outside like a kind of fuel, so
|
||
|
that a little motion often makes it burst into flame just as smoke
|
||
|
does: for flame is the ebullition of a dry exhalation. So whenever the
|
||
|
circular motion stirs this stuff up in any way, it catches fire at the
|
||
|
point at which it is most inflammable. The result differs according to
|
||
|
the disposition and quantity of the combustible material. If this is
|
||
|
broad and long, we often see a flame burning as in a field of stubble:
|
||
|
if it burns lengthwise only, we see what are called 'torches' and
|
||
|
'goats' and shooting-stars. Now when the inflammable material is
|
||
|
longer than it is broad sometimes it seems to throw off sparks as it
|
||
|
burns. (This happens because matter catches fire at the sides in small
|
||
|
portions but continuously with the main body.) Then it is called a
|
||
|
'goat'. When this does not happen it is a 'torch'. But if the whole
|
||
|
length of the exhalation is scattered in small parts and in many
|
||
|
directions and in breadth and depth alike, we get what are called
|
||
|
shooting-stars.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The cause of these shooting-stars is sometimes the motion which
|
||
|
ignites the exhalation. At other times the air is condensed by cold
|
||
|
and squeezes out and ejects the hot element; making their motion
|
||
|
look more like that of a thing thrown than like a running fire. For
|
||
|
the question might be raised whether the 'shooting' of a 'star' is the
|
||
|
same thing as when you put an exhalation below a lamp and it lights
|
||
|
the lower lamp from the flame above. For here too the flame passes
|
||
|
wonderfully quickly and looks like a thing thrown, and not as if one
|
||
|
thing after another caught fire. Or is a 'star' when it 'shoots' a
|
||
|
single body that is thrown? Apparently both cases occur: sometimes
|
||
|
it is like the flame from the lamp and sometimes bodies are
|
||
|
projected by being squeezed out (like fruit stones from one's fingers)
|
||
|
and so are seen to fall into the sea and on the dry land, both by
|
||
|
night and by day when the sky is clear. They are thrown downwards
|
||
|
because the condensation which propels them inclines downwards.
|
||
|
Thunderbolts fall downwards for the same reason: their origin is never
|
||
|
combustion but ejection under pressure, since naturally all heat tends
|
||
|
upwards.
|
||
|
|
||
|
When the phenomenon is formed in the upper region it is due to the
|
||
|
combustion of the exhalation. When it takes place at a lower level
|
||
|
it is due to the ejection of the exhalation by the condensing and
|
||
|
cooling of the moister evaporation: for this latter as it condenses
|
||
|
and inclines downward contracts, and thrusts out the hot element and
|
||
|
causes it to be thrown downwards. The motion is upwards or downwards
|
||
|
or sideways according to the way in which the evaporation lies, and
|
||
|
its disposition in respect of breadth and depth. In most cases the
|
||
|
direction is sideways because two motions are involved, a compulsory
|
||
|
motion downwards and a natural motion upwards, and under these
|
||
|
circumstances an object always moves obliquely. Hence the motion of
|
||
|
'shooting-stars' is generally oblique.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So the material cause of all these phenomena is the exhalation,
|
||
|
the efficient cause sometimes the upper motion, sometimes the
|
||
|
contraction and condensation of the air. Further, all these things
|
||
|
happen below the moon. This is shown by their apparent speed, which is
|
||
|
equal to that of things thrown by us; for it is because they are close
|
||
|
to us, that these latter seem far to exceed in speed the stars, the
|
||
|
sun, and the moon.
|
||
|
|
||
|
5
|
||
|
|
||
|
Sometimes on a fine night we see a variety of appearances that
|
||
|
form in the sky: 'chasms' for instance and 'trenches' and blood-red
|
||
|
colours. These, too, have the same cause. For we have seen that the
|
||
|
upper air condenses into an inflammable condition and that the
|
||
|
combustion sometimes takes on the appearance of a burning flame,
|
||
|
sometimes that of moving torches and stars. So it is not surprising
|
||
|
that this same air when condensing should assume a variety of colours.
|
||
|
For a weak light shining through a dense air, and the air when it acts
|
||
|
as a mirror, will cause all kinds of colours to appear, but especially
|
||
|
crimson and purple. For these colours generally appear when
|
||
|
fire-colour and white are combined by superposition. Thus on a hot
|
||
|
day, or through a smoky, medium, the stars when they rise and set look
|
||
|
crimson. The light will also create colours by reflection when the
|
||
|
mirror is such as to reflect colour only and not shape.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These appearances do not persist long, because the condensation of
|
||
|
the air is transient.
|
||
|
|
||
|
'Chasms' get their appearance of depth from light breaking out of
|
||
|
a dark blue or black mass of air. When the process of condensation
|
||
|
goes further in such a case we often find 'torches' ejected. When
|
||
|
the 'chasm' contracts it presents the appearance of a 'trench'.
|
||
|
|
||
|
In general, white in contrast with black creates a variety of
|
||
|
colours; like flame, for instance, through a medium of smoke. But by
|
||
|
day the sun obscures them, and, with the exception of crimson, the
|
||
|
colours are not seen at night because they are dark.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These then must be taken to be the causes of 'shooting-stars' and
|
||
|
the phenomena of combustion and also of the other transient
|
||
|
appearances of this kind.
|
||
|
|
||
|
6
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us go on to explain the nature of comets and the 'milky way',
|
||
|
after a preliminary discussion of the views of others.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Anaxagoras and Democritus declare that comets are a conjunction of
|
||
|
the planets approaching one another and so appearing to touch one
|
||
|
another.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some of the Italians called Pythagoreans say that the comet is one
|
||
|
of the planets, but that it appears at great intervals of time and
|
||
|
only rises a little above the horizon. This is the case with Mercury
|
||
|
too; because it only rises a little above the horizon it often fails
|
||
|
to be seen and consequently appears at great intervals of time.
|
||
|
|
||
|
A view like theirs was also expressed by Hippocrates of Chios and
|
||
|
his pupil Aeschylus. Only they say that the tail does not belong to
|
||
|
the comet iself, but is occasionally assumed by it on its course in
|
||
|
certain situations, when our sight is reflected to the sun from the
|
||
|
moisture attracted by the comet. It appears at greater intervals
|
||
|
than the other stars because it is slowest to get clear of the sun and
|
||
|
has been left behind by the sun to the extent of the whole of its
|
||
|
circle before it reappears at the same point. It gets clear of the sun
|
||
|
both towards the north and towards the south. In the space between the
|
||
|
tropics it does not draw water to itself because that region is
|
||
|
dried up by the sun on its course. When it moves towards the south
|
||
|
it has no lack of the necessary moisture, but because the segment of
|
||
|
its circle which is above the horizon is small, and that below it many
|
||
|
times as large, it is impossible for the sun to be reflected to our
|
||
|
sight, either when it approaches the southern tropic, or at the summer
|
||
|
solstice. Hence in these regions it does not develop a tail at all.
|
||
|
But when it is visible in the north it assumes a tail because the
|
||
|
arc above the horizon is large and that below it small. For under
|
||
|
these circumstances there is nothing to prevent our vision from
|
||
|
being reflected to the sun.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These views involve impossibilities, some of which are common to all
|
||
|
of them, while others are peculiar to some only.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This is the case, first, with those who say that the comet is one of
|
||
|
the planets. For all the planets appear in the circle of the zodiac,
|
||
|
whereas many comets have been seen outside that circle. Again more
|
||
|
comets than one have often appeared simultaneously. Besides, if
|
||
|
their tail is due to reflection, as Aeschylus and Hippocrates say,
|
||
|
this planet ought sometimes to be visible without a tail since, as
|
||
|
they it does not possess a tail in every place in which it appears.
|
||
|
But, as a matter of fact, no planet has been observed besides the
|
||
|
five. And all of them are often visible above the horizon together
|
||
|
at the same time. Further, comets are often found to appear, as well
|
||
|
when all the planets are visible as when some are not, but are
|
||
|
obscured by the neighbourhood of the sun. Moreover the statement
|
||
|
that a comet only appears in the north, with the sun at the summer
|
||
|
solstice, is not true either. The great comet which appeared at the
|
||
|
time of the earthquake in Achaea and the tidal wave rose due west; and
|
||
|
many have been known to appear in the south. Again in the archonship
|
||
|
of Euclees, son of Molon, at Athens there appeared a comet in the
|
||
|
north in the month Gamelion, the sun being about the winter
|
||
|
solstice. Yet they themselves admit that reflection over so great a
|
||
|
space is an impossibility.
|
||
|
|
||
|
An objection that tells equally against those who hold this theory
|
||
|
and those who say that comets are a coalescence of the planets is,
|
||
|
first, the fact that some of the fixed stars too get a tail. For
|
||
|
this we must not only accept the authority of the Egyptians who assert
|
||
|
it, but we have ourselves observed the fact. For a star in the thigh
|
||
|
of the Dog had a tail, though a faint one. If you fixed your sight
|
||
|
on it its light was dim, but if you just glanced at it, it appeared
|
||
|
brighter. Besides, all the comets that have been seen in our day
|
||
|
have vanished without setting, gradually fading away above the
|
||
|
horizon; and they have not left behind them either one or more
|
||
|
stars. For instance the great comet we mentioned before appeared to
|
||
|
the west in winter in frosty weather when the sky was clear, in the
|
||
|
archonship of Asteius. On the first day it set before the sun and
|
||
|
was then not seen. On the next day it was seen, being ever so little
|
||
|
behind the sun and immediately setting. But its light extended over
|
||
|
a third part of the sky like a leap, so that people called it a
|
||
|
'path'. This comet receded as far as Orion's belt and there dissolved.
|
||
|
Democritus however, insists upon the truth of his view and affirms
|
||
|
that certain stars have been seen when comets dissolve. But on his
|
||
|
theory this ought not to occur occasionally but always. Besides, the
|
||
|
Egyptians affirm that conjunctions of the planets with one another,
|
||
|
and with the fixed stars, take place, and we have ourselves observed
|
||
|
Jupiter coinciding with one of the stars in the Twins and hiding it,
|
||
|
and yet no comet was formed. Further, we can also give a rational
|
||
|
proof of our point. It is true that some stars seem to be bigger
|
||
|
than others, yet each one by itself looks indivisible. Consequently,
|
||
|
just as, if they really had been indivisible, their conjunction
|
||
|
could not have created any greater magnitude, so now that they are not
|
||
|
in fact indivisible but look as if they were, their conjunction will
|
||
|
not make them look any bigger.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Enough has been said, without further argument, to show that the
|
||
|
causes brought forward to explain comets are false.
|
||
|
|
||
|
7
|
||
|
|
||
|
We consider a satisfactory explanation of phenomena inaccessible
|
||
|
to observation to have been given when our account of them is free
|
||
|
from impossibilities. The observations before us suggest the following
|
||
|
account of the phenomena we are now considering. We know that the
|
||
|
dry and warm exhalation is the outermost part of the terrestrial world
|
||
|
which falls below the circular motion. It, and a great part of the air
|
||
|
that is continuous with it below, is carried round the earth by the
|
||
|
motion of the circular revolution. In the course of this motion it
|
||
|
often ignites wherever it may happen to be of the right consistency,
|
||
|
and this we maintain to be the cause of the 'shooting' of scattered
|
||
|
'stars'. We may say, then, that a comet is formed when the upper
|
||
|
motion introduces into a gathering of this kind a fiery principle
|
||
|
not of such excessive strength as to burn up much of the material
|
||
|
quickly, nor so weak as soon to be extinguished, but stronger and
|
||
|
capable of burning up much material, and when exhalation of the
|
||
|
right consistency rises from below and meets it. The kind of comet
|
||
|
varies according to the shape which the exhalation happens to take. If
|
||
|
it is diffused equally on every side the star is said to be fringed,
|
||
|
if it stretches out in one direction it is called bearded. We have
|
||
|
seen that when a fiery principle of this kind moves we seem to have
|
||
|
a shooting-star: similarly when it stands still we seem to have a star
|
||
|
standing still. We may compare these phenomena to a heap or mass of
|
||
|
chaff into which a torch is thrust, or a spark thrown. That is what
|
||
|
a shooting-star is like. The fuel is so inflammable that the fire runs
|
||
|
through it quickly in a line. Now if this fire were to persist instead
|
||
|
of running through the fuel and perishing away, its course through the
|
||
|
fuel would stop at the point where the latter was densest, and then
|
||
|
the whole might begin to move. Such is a comet-like a shooting-star
|
||
|
that contains its beginning and end in itself.
|
||
|
|
||
|
When the matter begins to gather in the lower region independently
|
||
|
the comet appears by itself. But when the exhalation is constituted by
|
||
|
one of the fixed stars or the planets, owing to their motion, one of
|
||
|
them becomes a comet. The fringe is not close to the stars themselves.
|
||
|
Just as haloes appear to follow the sun and the moon as they move, and
|
||
|
encircle them, when the air is dense enough for them to form along
|
||
|
under the sun's course, so too the fringe. It stands in the relation
|
||
|
of a halo to the stars, except that the colour of the halo is due to
|
||
|
reflection, whereas in the case of comets the colour is something that
|
||
|
appears actually on them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now when this matter gathers in relation to a star the comet
|
||
|
necessarily appears to follow the same course as the star. But when
|
||
|
the comet is formed independently it falls behind the motion of the
|
||
|
universe, like the rest of the terrestrial world. It is this fact,
|
||
|
that a comet often forms independently, indeed oftener than round
|
||
|
one of the regular stars, that makes it impossible to maintain that
|
||
|
a comet is a sort of reflection, not indeed, as Hippocrates and his
|
||
|
school say, to the sun, but to the very star it is alleged to
|
||
|
accompany-in fact, a kind of halo in the pure fuel of fire.
|
||
|
|
||
|
As for the halo we shall explain its cause later.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The fact that comets when frequent foreshadow wind and drought
|
||
|
must be taken as an indication of their fiery constitution. For
|
||
|
their origin is plainly due to the plentiful supply of that secretion.
|
||
|
Hence the air is necessarily drier and the moist evaporation is so
|
||
|
dissolved and dissipated by the quantity of the hot exhalation as
|
||
|
not readily to condense into water.-But this phenomenon too shall be
|
||
|
explained more clearly later when the time comes to speak of the
|
||
|
winds.-So when there are many comets and they are dense, it is as we
|
||
|
say, and the years are clearly dry and windy. When they are fewer
|
||
|
and fainter this effect does not appear in the same degree, though
|
||
|
as a rule the is found to be excessive either in duration or strength.
|
||
|
For instance when the stone at Aegospotami fell out of the air-it
|
||
|
had been carried up by a wind and fell down in the daytime-then too
|
||
|
a comet happened to have appeared in the west. And at the time of
|
||
|
the great comet the winter was dry and north winds prevailed, and
|
||
|
the wave was due to an opposition of winds. For in the gulf a north
|
||
|
wind blew and outside it a violent south wind. Again in the archonship
|
||
|
of Nicomachus a comet appeared for a few days about the equinoctial
|
||
|
circle (this one had not risen in the west), and simultaneously with
|
||
|
it there happened the storm at Corinth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
That there are few comets and that they appear rarely and outside
|
||
|
the tropic circles more than within them is due to the motion of the
|
||
|
sun and the stars. For this motion does not only cause the hot
|
||
|
principle to be secreted but also dissolves it when it is gathering.
|
||
|
But the chief reason is that most of this stuff collects in the region
|
||
|
of the milky way.
|
||
|
|
||
|
8
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us now explain the origin, cause, and nature of the milky way.
|
||
|
And here too let us begin by discussing the statements of others on
|
||
|
the subject.
|
||
|
|
||
|
(1) Of the so-called Pythagoreans some say that this is the path
|
||
|
of one of the stars that fell from heaven at the time of Phaethon's
|
||
|
downfall. Others say that the sun used once to move in this circle and
|
||
|
that this region was scorched or met with some other affection of this
|
||
|
kind, because of the sun and its motion.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But it is absurd not to see that if this were the reason the
|
||
|
circle of the Zodiac ought to be affected in the same way, and
|
||
|
indeed more so than that of the milky way, since not the sun only
|
||
|
but all the planets move in it. We can see the whole of this circle
|
||
|
(half of it being visible at any time of the night), but it shows no
|
||
|
signs of any such affection except where a part of it touches the
|
||
|
circle of the milky way.
|
||
|
|
||
|
(2) Anaxagoras, Democritus, and their schools say that the milky way
|
||
|
is the light of certain stars. For, they say, when the sun passes
|
||
|
below the earth some of the stars are hidden from it. Now the light of
|
||
|
those on which the sun shines is invisible, being obscured by the of
|
||
|
the sun. But the milky way is the peculiar light of those stars
|
||
|
which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This, too, is obviously impossible. The milky way is always
|
||
|
unchanged and among the same constellations (for it is clearly a
|
||
|
greatest circle), whereas, since the sun does not remain in the same
|
||
|
place, what is hidden from it differs at different times. Consequently
|
||
|
with the change of the sun's position the milky way ought to change
|
||
|
its position too: but we find that this does not happen. Besides, if
|
||
|
astronomical demonstrations are correct and the size of the sun is
|
||
|
greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from
|
||
|
the earth many times greater than that of the sun (just as the sun
|
||
|
is further from the earth than the moon), then the cone made by the
|
||
|
rays of the sun would terminate at no great distance from the earth,
|
||
|
and the shadow of the earth (what we call night) would not reach the
|
||
|
stars. On the contrary, the sun shines on all the stars and the
|
||
|
earth screens none of them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
(3) There is a third theory about the milky way. Some say that it is
|
||
|
a reflection of our sight to the sun, just as they say that the
|
||
|
comet is.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But this too is impossible. For if the eye and the mirror and the
|
||
|
whole of the object were severally at rest, then the same part of
|
||
|
the image would appear at the same point in the mirror. But if the
|
||
|
mirror and the object move, keeping the same distance from the eye
|
||
|
which is at rest, but at different rates of speed and so not always at
|
||
|
the same interval from one another, then it is impossible for the same
|
||
|
image always to appear in the same part of the mirror. Now the
|
||
|
constellations included in the circle of the milky way move; and so
|
||
|
does the sun, the object to which our sight is reflected; but we stand
|
||
|
still. And the distance of those two from us is constant and
|
||
|
uniform, but their distance from one another varies. For the Dolphin
|
||
|
sometimes rises at midnight, sometimes in the morning. But in each
|
||
|
case the same parts of the milky way are found near it. But if it were
|
||
|
a reflection and not a genuine affection of these this ought not to be
|
||
|
the case.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, we can see the milky way reflected at night in water and
|
||
|
similar mirrors. But under these circumstances it is impossible for
|
||
|
our sight to be reflected to the sun.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These considerations show that the milky way is not the path of
|
||
|
one of the planets, nor the light of imperceptible stars, nor a
|
||
|
reflection. And those are the chief theories handed down by others
|
||
|
hitherto.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us recall our fundamental principle and then explain our
|
||
|
views. We have already laid down that the outermost part of what is
|
||
|
called the air is potentially fire and that therefore when the air
|
||
|
is dissolved by motion, there is separated off a kind of matter-and of
|
||
|
this matter we assert that comets consist. We must suppose that what
|
||
|
happens is the same as in the case of the comets when the matter
|
||
|
does not form independently but is formed by one of the fixed stars or
|
||
|
the planets. Then these stars appear to be fringed, because matter
|
||
|
of this kind follows their course. In the same way, a certain kind
|
||
|
of matter follows the sun, and we explain the halo as a reflection
|
||
|
from it when the air is of the right constitution. Now we must
|
||
|
assume that what happens in the case of the stars severally happens in
|
||
|
the case of the whole of the heavens and all the upper motion. For
|
||
|
it is natural to suppose that, if the motion of a single star
|
||
|
excites a flame, that of all the stars should have a similar result,
|
||
|
and especially in that region in which the stars are biggest and
|
||
|
most numerous and nearest to one another. Now the circle of the zodiac
|
||
|
dissolves this kind of matter because of the motion of the sun and the
|
||
|
planets, and for this reason most comets are found outside the
|
||
|
tropic circles. Again, no fringe appears round the sun or moon: for
|
||
|
they dissolve such matter too quickly to admit of its formation. But
|
||
|
this circle in which the milky way appears to our sight is the
|
||
|
greatest circle, and its position is such that it extends far
|
||
|
outside the tropic circles. Besides the region is full of the
|
||
|
biggest and brightest constellations and also of what called
|
||
|
'scattered' stars (you have only to look to see this clearly). So
|
||
|
for these reasons all this matter is continually and ceaselessly
|
||
|
collecting there. A proof of the theory is this: In the circle
|
||
|
itself the light is stronger in that half where the milky way is
|
||
|
divided, and in it the constellations are more numerous and closer
|
||
|
to one another than in the other half; which shows that the cause of
|
||
|
the light is the motion of the constellations and nothing else. For if
|
||
|
it is found in the circle in which there are most constellations and
|
||
|
at that point in the circle at which they are densest and contain
|
||
|
the biggest and the most stars, it is natural to suppose that they are
|
||
|
the true cause of the affection in question. The circle and the
|
||
|
constellations in it may be seen in the diagram. The so-called
|
||
|
'scattered' stars it is not possible to set down in the same way on
|
||
|
the sphere because none of them have an evident permanent position;
|
||
|
but if you look up to the sky the point is clear. For in this circle
|
||
|
alone are the intervals full of these stars: in the other circles
|
||
|
there are obvious gaps. Hence if we accept the cause assigned for
|
||
|
the appearance of comets as plausible we must assume that the same
|
||
|
kind of thing holds good of the milky way. For the fringe which in the
|
||
|
former case is an affection of a single star here forms in the same
|
||
|
way in relation to a whole circle. So if we are to define the milky
|
||
|
way we may call it 'a fringe attaching to the greatest circle, and due
|
||
|
to the matter secreted'. This, as we said before, explains why there
|
||
|
are few comets and why they appear rarely; it is because at each
|
||
|
revolution of the heavens this matter has always been and is always
|
||
|
being separated off and gathered into this region.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now explained the phenomena that occur in that part of the
|
||
|
terrestrial world which is continuous with the motions of the heavens,
|
||
|
namely, shooting-stars and the burning flame, comets and the milky
|
||
|
way, these being the chief affections that appear in that region.
|
||
|
|
||
|
9
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us go on to treat of the region which follows next in order
|
||
|
after this and which immediately surrounds the earth. It is the region
|
||
|
common to water and air, and the processes attending the formation
|
||
|
of water above take place in it. We must consider the principles and
|
||
|
causes of all these phenomena too as before. The efficient and chief
|
||
|
and first cause is the circle in which the sun moves. For the sun as
|
||
|
it approaches or recedes, obviously causes dissipation and
|
||
|
condensation and so gives rise to generation and destruction. Now
|
||
|
the earth remains but the moisture surrounding it is made to evaporate
|
||
|
by the sun's rays and the other heat from above, and rises. But when
|
||
|
the heat which was raising it leaves it, in part dispersing to the
|
||
|
higher region, in part quenched through rising so far into the upper
|
||
|
air, then the vapour cools because its heat is gone and because the
|
||
|
place is cold, and condenses again and turns from air into water.
|
||
|
And after the water has formed it falls down again to the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The exhalation of water is vapour: air condensing into water is
|
||
|
cloud. Mist is what is left over when a cloud condenses into water,
|
||
|
and is therefore rather a sign of fine weather than of rain; for
|
||
|
mist might be called a barren cloud. So we get a circular process that
|
||
|
follows the course of the sun. For according as the sun moves to
|
||
|
this side or that, the moisture in this process rises or falls. We
|
||
|
must think of it as a river flowing up and down in a circle and made
|
||
|
up partly of air, partly of water. When the sun is near, the stream of
|
||
|
vapour flows upwards; when it recedes, the stream of water flows down:
|
||
|
and the order of sequence, at all events, in this process always
|
||
|
remains the same. So if 'Oceanus' had some secret meaning in early
|
||
|
writers, perhaps they may have meant this river that flows in a circle
|
||
|
about the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So the moisture is always raised by the heat and descends to the
|
||
|
earth again when it gets cold. These processes and, in some cases,
|
||
|
their varieties are distinguished by special names. When the water
|
||
|
falls in small drops it is called a drizzle; when the drops are larger
|
||
|
it is rain.
|
||
|
|
||
|
10
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some of the vapour that is formed by day does not rise high
|
||
|
because the ratio of the fire that is raising it to the water that
|
||
|
is being raised is small. When this cools and descends at night it
|
||
|
is called dew and hoar-frost. When the vapour is frozen before it
|
||
|
has condensed to water again it is hoar-frost; and this appears in
|
||
|
winter and is commoner in cold places. It is dew when the vapour has
|
||
|
condensed into water and the heat is not so great as to dry up the
|
||
|
moisture that has been raised nor the cold sufficient (owing to the
|
||
|
warmth of the climate or season) for the vapour itself to freeze.
|
||
|
For dew is more commonly found when the season or the place is warm,
|
||
|
whereas the opposite, as has been said, is the case with hoar-frost.
|
||
|
For obviously vapour is warmer than water, having still the fire
|
||
|
that raised it: consequently more cold is needed to freeze it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Both dew and hoar-frost are found when the sky is clear and there is
|
||
|
no wind. For the vapour could not be raised unless the sky were clear,
|
||
|
and if a wind were blowing it could not condense.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The fact that hoar-frost is not found on mountains contributes to
|
||
|
prove that these phenomena occur because the vapour does not rise
|
||
|
high. One reason for this is that it rises from hollow and watery
|
||
|
places, so that the heat that is raising it, bearing as it were too
|
||
|
heavy a burden cannot lift it to a great height but soon lets it
|
||
|
fall again. A second reason is that the motion of the air is more
|
||
|
pronounced at a height, and this dissolves a gathering of this kind.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Everywhere, except in Pontus, dew is found with south winds and
|
||
|
not with north winds. There the opposite is the case and it is found
|
||
|
with north winds and not with south. The reason is the same as that
|
||
|
which explains why dew is found in warm weather and not in cold. For
|
||
|
the south wind brings warm, and the north, wintry weather. For the
|
||
|
north wind is cold and so quenches the heat of the evaporation. But in
|
||
|
Pontus the south wind does not bring warmth enough to cause
|
||
|
evaporation, whereas the coldness of the north wind concentrates the
|
||
|
heat by a sort of recoil, so that there is more evaporation and not
|
||
|
less. This is a thing which we can often observe in other places
|
||
|
too. Wells, for instance, give off more vapour in a north than in a
|
||
|
south wind. Only the north winds quench the heat before any
|
||
|
considerable quantity of vapour has gathered, while in a south wind
|
||
|
the evaporation is allowed to accumulate.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Water, once formed, does not freeze on the surface of the earth,
|
||
|
in the way that it does in the region of the clouds.
|
||
|
|
||
|
11
|
||
|
|
||
|
From the latter there fall three bodies condensed by cold, namely
|
||
|
rain, snow, hail. Two of these correspond to the phenomena on the
|
||
|
lower level and are due to the same causes, differing from them only
|
||
|
in degree and quantity.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Snow and hoar-frost are one and the same thing, and so are rain
|
||
|
and dew: only there is a great deal of the former and little of the
|
||
|
latter. For rain is due to the cooling of a great amount of vapour,
|
||
|
for the region from which and the time during which the vapour is
|
||
|
collected are considerable. But of dew there is little: for the vapour
|
||
|
collects for it in a single day and from a small area, as its quick
|
||
|
formation and scanty quantity show.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The relation of hoar-frost and snow is the same: when cloud
|
||
|
freezes there is snow, when vapour freezes there is hoar-frost.
|
||
|
Hence snow is a sign of a cold season or country. For a great deal
|
||
|
of heat is still present and unless the cold were overpowering it
|
||
|
the cloud would not freeze. For there still survives in it a great
|
||
|
deal of the heat which caused the moisture to rise as vapour from
|
||
|
the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hail on the other hand is found in the upper region, but the
|
||
|
corresponding phenomenon in the vaporous region near the earth is
|
||
|
lacking. For, as we said, to snow in the upper region corresponds
|
||
|
hoar-frost in the lower, and to rain in the upper region, dew in the
|
||
|
lower. But there is nothing here to correspond to hail in the upper
|
||
|
region. Why this is so will be clear when we have explained the nature
|
||
|
of hail.
|
||
|
|
||
|
12
|
||
|
|
||
|
But we must go on to collect the facts bearing on the origin of
|
||
|
it, both those which raise no difficulties and those which seem
|
||
|
paradoxical.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hail is ice, and water freezes in winter; yet hailstorms occur
|
||
|
chiefly in spring and autumn and less often in the late summer, but
|
||
|
rarely in winter and then only when the cold is less intense. And in
|
||
|
general hailstorms occur in warmer, and snow in colder places.
|
||
|
Again, there is a difficulty about water freezing in the upper region.
|
||
|
It cannot have frozen before becoming water: and water cannot remain
|
||
|
suspended in the air for any space of time. Nor can we say that the
|
||
|
case is like that of particles of moisture which are carried up
|
||
|
owing to their small size and rest on the iar (the water swimming on
|
||
|
the air just as small particles of earth and gold often swim on
|
||
|
water). In that case large drops are formed by the union of many
|
||
|
small, and so fall down. This cannot take place in the case of hail,
|
||
|
since solid bodies cannot coalesce like liquid ones. Clearly then
|
||
|
drops of that size were suspended in the air or else they could not
|
||
|
have been so large when frozen.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some think that the cause and origin of hail is this. The cloud is
|
||
|
thrust up into the upper atmosphere, which is colder because the
|
||
|
reflection of the sun's rays from the earth ceases there, and upon its
|
||
|
arrival there the water freezes. They think that this explains why
|
||
|
hailstorms are commoner in summer and in warm countries; the heat is
|
||
|
greater and it thrusts the clouds further up from the earth. But the
|
||
|
fact is that hail does not occur at all at a great height: yet it
|
||
|
ought to do so, on their theory, just as we see that snow falls most
|
||
|
on high mountains. Again clouds have often been observed moving with a
|
||
|
great noise close to the earth, terrifying those who heard and saw
|
||
|
them as portents of some catastrophe. Sometimes, too, when such clouds
|
||
|
have been seen, without any noise, there follows a violent
|
||
|
hailstorm, and the stones are of incredible size, and angular in
|
||
|
shape. This shows that they have not been falling for long and that
|
||
|
they were frozen near to the earth, and not as that theory would
|
||
|
have it. Moreover, where the hailstones are large, the cause of
|
||
|
their freezing must be present in the highest degree: for hail is
|
||
|
ice as every one can see. Now those hailstones are large which are
|
||
|
angular in shape. And this shows that they froze close to the earth,
|
||
|
for those that fall far are worn away by the length of their fall
|
||
|
and become round and smaller in size.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It clearly follows that the congelation does not take place
|
||
|
because the cloud is thrust up into the cold upper region.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now we see that warm and cold react upon one another by recoil.
|
||
|
Hence in warm weather the lower parts of the earth are cold and in a
|
||
|
frost they are warm. The same thing, we must suppose, happens in the
|
||
|
air, so that in the warmer seasons the cold is concentrated by the
|
||
|
surrounding heat and causes the cloud to go over into water
|
||
|
suddenly. (For this reason rain-drops are much larger on warm days
|
||
|
than in winter, and showers more violent. A shower is said to be
|
||
|
more violent in proportion as the water comes down in a body, and this
|
||
|
happens when the condensation takes place quickly,-though this is just
|
||
|
the opposite of what Anaxagoras says. He says that this happens when
|
||
|
the cloud has risen into the cold air; whereas we say that it
|
||
|
happens when the cloud has descended into the warm air, and that the
|
||
|
more the further the cloud has descended). But when the cold has
|
||
|
been concentrated within still more by the outer heat, it freezes
|
||
|
the water it has formed and there is hail. We get hail when the
|
||
|
process of freezing is quicker than the descent of the water. For if
|
||
|
the water falls in a certain time and the cold is sufficient to freeze
|
||
|
it in less, there is no difficulty about its having frozen in the air,
|
||
|
provided that the freezing takes place in a shorter time than its
|
||
|
fall. The nearer to the earth, and the more suddenly, this process
|
||
|
takes place, the more violent is the rain that results and the
|
||
|
larger the raindrops and the hailstones because of the shortness of
|
||
|
their fall. For the same reason large raindrops do not fall thickly.
|
||
|
Hail is rarer in summer than in spring and autumn, though commoner
|
||
|
than in winter, because the air is drier in summer, whereas in
|
||
|
spring it is still moist, and in autumn it is beginning to grow moist.
|
||
|
It is for the same reason that hailstorms sometimes occur in the
|
||
|
late summer as we have said.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The fact that the water has previously been warmed contributes to
|
||
|
its freezing quickly: for so it cools sooner. Hence many people,
|
||
|
when they want to cool hot water quickly, begin by putting it in the
|
||
|
sun. So the inhabitants of Pontus when they encamp on the ice to
|
||
|
fish (they cut a hole in the ice and then fish) pour warm water
|
||
|
round their reeds that it may freeze the quicker, for they use the ice
|
||
|
like lead to fix the reeds. Now it is in hot countries and seasons
|
||
|
that the water which forms soon grows warm.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is for the same reason that rain falls in summer and not in
|
||
|
winter in Arabia and Ethiopia too, and that in torrents and repeatedly
|
||
|
on the same day. For the concentration or recoil due to the extreme
|
||
|
heat of the country cools the clouds quickly.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for an account of the nature and causes of rain, dew,
|
||
|
snow, hoar-frost, and hail.
|
||
|
|
||
|
13
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us explain the nature of winds, and all windy vapours, also of
|
||
|
rivers and of the sea. But here, too, we must first discuss the
|
||
|
difficulties involved: for, as in other matters, so in this no
|
||
|
theory has been handed down to us that the most ordinary man could not
|
||
|
have thought of.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some say that what is called air, when it is in motion and flows, is
|
||
|
wind, and that this same air when it condenses again becomes cloud and
|
||
|
water, implying that the nature of wind and water is the same. So they
|
||
|
define wind as a motion of the air. Hence some, wishing to say a
|
||
|
clever thing, assert that all the winds are one wind, because the
|
||
|
air that moves is in fact all of it one and the same; they maintain
|
||
|
that the winds appear to differ owing to the region from which the air
|
||
|
may happen to flow on each occasion, but really do not differ at
|
||
|
all. This is just like thinking that all rivers are one and the same
|
||
|
river, and the ordinary unscientific view is better than a
|
||
|
scientific theory like this. If all rivers flow from one source, and
|
||
|
the same is true in the case of the winds, there might be some truth
|
||
|
in this theory; but if it is no more true in the one case than in
|
||
|
the other, this ingenious idea is plainly false. What requires
|
||
|
investigation is this: the nature of wind and how it originates, its
|
||
|
efficient cause and whence they derive their source; whether one ought
|
||
|
to think of the wind as issuing from a sort of vessel and flowing
|
||
|
until the vessel is empty, as if let out of a wineskin, or, as
|
||
|
painters represent the winds, as drawing their source from themselves.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We find analogous views about the origin of rivers. It is thought
|
||
|
that the water is raised by the sun and descends in rain and gathers
|
||
|
below the earth and so flows from a great reservoir, all the rivers
|
||
|
from one, or each from a different one. No water at all is
|
||
|
generated, but the volume of the rivers consists of the water that
|
||
|
is gathered into such reservoirs in winter. Hence rivers are always
|
||
|
fuller in winter than in summer, and some are perennial, others not.
|
||
|
Rivers are perennial where the reservoir is large and so enough
|
||
|
water has collected in it to last out and not be used up before the
|
||
|
winter rain returns. Where the reservoirs are smaller there is less
|
||
|
water in the rivers, and they are dried up and their vessel empty
|
||
|
before the fresh rain comes on.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But if any one will picture to himself a reservoir adequate to the
|
||
|
water that is continuously flowing day by day, and consider the amount
|
||
|
of the water, it is obvious that a receptacle that is to contain all
|
||
|
the water that flows in the year would be larger than the earth, or,
|
||
|
at any rate, not much smaller.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Though it is evident that many reservoirs of this kind do exist in
|
||
|
many parts of the earth, yet it is unreasonable for any one to
|
||
|
refuse to admit that air becomes water in the earth for the same
|
||
|
reason as it does above it. If the cold causes the vaporous air to
|
||
|
condense into water above the earth we must suppose the cold in the
|
||
|
earth to produce this same effect, and recognize that there not only
|
||
|
exists in it and flows out of it actually formed water, but that water
|
||
|
is continually forming in it too.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, even in the case of the water that is not being formed from
|
||
|
day to day but exists as such, we must not suppose as some do that
|
||
|
rivers have their source in definite subterranean lakes. On the
|
||
|
contrary, just as above the earth small drops form and these join
|
||
|
others, till finally the water descends in a body as rain, so too we
|
||
|
must suppose that in the earth the water at first trickles together
|
||
|
little by little, and that the sources of the rivers drip, as it were,
|
||
|
out of the earth and then unite. This is proved by facts. When men
|
||
|
construct an aqueduct they collect the water in pipes and trenches, as
|
||
|
if the earth in the higher ground were sweating the water out.
|
||
|
Hence, too, the head-waters of rivers are found to flow from
|
||
|
mountains, and from the greatest mountains there flow the most
|
||
|
numerous and greatest rivers. Again, most springs are in the
|
||
|
neighbourhood of mountains and of high ground, whereas if we except
|
||
|
rivers, water rarely appears in the plains. For mountains and high
|
||
|
ground, suspended over the country like a saturated sponge, make the
|
||
|
water ooze out and trickle together in minute quantities but in many
|
||
|
places. They receive a great deal of water falling as rain (for it
|
||
|
makes no difference whether a spongy receptacle is concave and
|
||
|
turned up or convex and turned down: in either case it will contain
|
||
|
the same volume of matter) and, they also cool the vapour that rises
|
||
|
and condense it back into water.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hence, as we said, we find that the greatest rivers flow from the
|
||
|
greatest mountains. This can be seen by looking at itineraries: what
|
||
|
is recorded in them consists either of things which the writer has
|
||
|
seen himself or of such as he has compiled after inquiry from those
|
||
|
who have seen them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
In Asia we find that the most numerous and greatest rivers flow from
|
||
|
the mountain called Parnassus, admittedly the greatest of all
|
||
|
mountains towards the south-east. When you have crossed it you see the
|
||
|
outer ocean, the further limit of which is unknown to the dwellers
|
||
|
in our world. Besides other rivers there flow from it the Bactrus, the
|
||
|
Choaspes, the Araxes: from the last a branch separates off and flows
|
||
|
into lake Maeotis as the Tanais. From it, too, flows the Indus, the
|
||
|
volume of whose stream is greatest of all rivers. From the Caucasus
|
||
|
flows the Phasis, and very many other great rivers besides. Now the
|
||
|
Caucasus is the greatest of the mountains that lie to the northeast,
|
||
|
both as regards its extent and its height. A proof of its height is
|
||
|
the fact that it can be seen from the so-called 'deeps' and from the
|
||
|
entrance to the lake. Again, the sun shines on its peaks for a third
|
||
|
part of the night before sunrise and again after sunset. Its extent is
|
||
|
proved by the fact that thought contains many inhabitable regions
|
||
|
which are occupied by many nations and in which there are said to be
|
||
|
great lakes, yet they say that all these regions are visible up to the
|
||
|
last peak. From Pyrene (this is a mountain towards the west in
|
||
|
Celtice) there flow the Istrus and the Tartessus. The latter flows
|
||
|
outside the pillars, while the Istrus flows through all Europe into
|
||
|
the Euxine. Most of the remaining rivers flow northwards from the
|
||
|
Hercynian mountains, which are the greatest in height and extent about
|
||
|
that region. In the extreme north, beyond furthest Scythia, are the
|
||
|
mountains called Rhipae. The stories about their size are altogether
|
||
|
too fabulous: however, they say that the most and (after the Istrus)
|
||
|
the greatest rivers flow from them. So, too, in Libya there flow
|
||
|
from the Aethiopian mountains the Aegon and the Nyses; and from the
|
||
|
so-called Silver Mountain the two greatest of named rivers, the
|
||
|
river called Chremetes that flows into the outer ocean, and the main
|
||
|
source of the Nile. Of the rivers in the Greek world, the Achelous
|
||
|
flows from Pindus, the Inachus from the same mountain; the Strymon,
|
||
|
the Nestus, and the Hebrus all three from Scombrus; many rivers,
|
||
|
too, flow from Rhodope.
|
||
|
|
||
|
All other rivers would be found to flow in the same way, but we have
|
||
|
mentioned these as examples. Even where rivers flow from marshes,
|
||
|
the marshes in almost every case are found to lie below mountains or
|
||
|
gradually rising ground.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is clear then that we must not suppose rivers to originate from
|
||
|
definite reservoirs: for the whole earth, we might almost say, would
|
||
|
not be sufficient (any more than the region of the clouds would be) if
|
||
|
we were to suppose that they were fed by actually existing water
|
||
|
only and it were not the case that as some water passed out of
|
||
|
existence some more came into existence, but rivers always drew
|
||
|
their stream from an existing store. Secondly, the fact that rivers
|
||
|
rise at the foot of mountains proves that a place transmits the
|
||
|
water it contains by gradual percolation of many drops, little by
|
||
|
little, and that this is how the sources of rivers originate. However,
|
||
|
there is nothing impossible about the existence of such places
|
||
|
containing a quantity of water like lakes: only they cannot be big
|
||
|
enough to produce the supposed effect. To think that they are is
|
||
|
just as absurd as if one were to suppose that rivers drew all their
|
||
|
water from the sources we see (for most rivers do flow from
|
||
|
springs). So it is no more reasonable to suppose those lakes to
|
||
|
contain the whole volume of water than these springs.
|
||
|
|
||
|
That there exist such chasms and cavities in the earth we are taught
|
||
|
by the rivers that are swallowed up. They are found in many parts of
|
||
|
the earth: in the Peloponnesus, for instance, there are many such
|
||
|
rivers in Arcadia. The reason is that Arcadia is mountainous and there
|
||
|
are no channels from its valleys to the sea. So these places get
|
||
|
full of water, and this, having no outlet, under the pressure of the
|
||
|
water that is added above, finds a way out for itself underground.
|
||
|
In Greece this kind of thing happens on quite a small scale, but the
|
||
|
lake at the foot of the Caucasus, which the inhabitants of these parts
|
||
|
call a sea, is considerable. Many great rivers fall into it and it has
|
||
|
no visible outlet but issues below the earth off the land of the
|
||
|
Coraxi about the so-called 'deeps of Pontus'. This is a place of
|
||
|
unfathomable depth in the sea: at any rate no one has yet been able to
|
||
|
find bottom there by sounding. At this spot, about three hundred
|
||
|
stadia from land, there comes up sweet water over a large area, not
|
||
|
all of it together but in three places. And in Liguria a river equal
|
||
|
in size to the Rhodanus is swallowed up and appears again elsewhere:
|
||
|
the Rhodanus being a navigable river.
|
||
|
|
||
|
14
|
||
|
|
||
|
The same parts of the earth are not always moist or dry, but they
|
||
|
change according as rivers come into existence and dry up. And so
|
||
|
the relation of land to sea changes too and a place does not always
|
||
|
remain land or sea throughout all time, but where there was dry land
|
||
|
there comes to be sea, and where there is now sea, there one day comes
|
||
|
to be dry land. But we must suppose these changes to follow some order
|
||
|
and cycle. The principle and cause of these changes is that the
|
||
|
interior of the earth grows and decays, like the bodies of plants
|
||
|
and animals. Only in the case of these latter the process does not
|
||
|
go on by parts, but each of them necessarily grows or decays as a
|
||
|
whole, whereas it does go on by parts in the case of the earth. Here
|
||
|
the causes are cold and heat, which increase and diminish on account
|
||
|
of the sun and its course. It is owing to them that the parts of the
|
||
|
earth come to have a different character, that some parts remain moist
|
||
|
for a certain time, and then dry up and grow old, while other parts in
|
||
|
their turn are filled with life and moisture. Now when places become
|
||
|
drier the springs necessarily give out, and when this happens the
|
||
|
rivers first decrease in size and then finally become dry; and when
|
||
|
rivers change and disappear in one part and come into existence
|
||
|
correspondingly in another, the sea must needs be affected.
|
||
|
|
||
|
If the sea was once pushed out by rivers and encroached upon the
|
||
|
land anywhere, it necessarily leaves that place dry when it recedes;
|
||
|
again, if the dry land has encroached on the sea at all by a process
|
||
|
of silting set up by the rivers when at their full, the time must come
|
||
|
when this place will be flooded again.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But the whole vital process of the earth takes place so gradually
|
||
|
and in periods of time which are so immense compared with the length
|
||
|
of our life, that these changes are not observed, and before their
|
||
|
course can be recorded from beginning to end whole nations perish
|
||
|
and are destroyed. Of such destructions the most utter and sudden
|
||
|
are due to wars; but pestilence or famine cause them too. Famines,
|
||
|
again, are either sudden and severe or else gradual. In the latter
|
||
|
case the disappearance of a nation is not noticed because some leave
|
||
|
the country while others remain; and this goes on until the land is
|
||
|
unable to maintain any inhabitants at all. So a long period of time is
|
||
|
likely to elapse from the first departure to the last, and no one
|
||
|
remembers and the lapse of time destroys all record even before the
|
||
|
last inhabitants have disappeared. In the same way a nation must be
|
||
|
supposed to lose account of the time when it first settled in a land
|
||
|
that was changing from a marshy and watery state and becoming dry.
|
||
|
Here, too, the change is gradual and lasts a long time and men do
|
||
|
not remember who came first, or when, or what the land was like when
|
||
|
they came. This has been the case with Egypt. Here it is obvious
|
||
|
that the land is continually getting drier and that the whole
|
||
|
country is a deposit of the river Nile. But because the neighbouring
|
||
|
peoples settled in the land gradually as the marshes dried, the
|
||
|
lapse of time has hidden the beginning of the process. However, all
|
||
|
the mouths of the Nile, with the single exception of that at
|
||
|
Canopus, are obviously artificial and not natural. And Egypt was
|
||
|
nothing more than what is called Thebes, as Homer, too, shows,
|
||
|
modern though he is in relation to such changes. For Thebes is the
|
||
|
place that he mentions; which implies that Memphis did not yet
|
||
|
exist, or at any rate was not as important as it is now. That this
|
||
|
should be so is natural, since the lower land came to be inhabited
|
||
|
later than that which lay higher. For the parts that lie nearer to the
|
||
|
place where the river is depositing the silt are necessarily marshy
|
||
|
for a longer time since the water always lies most in the newly formed
|
||
|
land. But in time this land changes its character, and in its turn
|
||
|
enjoys a period of prosperity. For these places dry up and come to
|
||
|
be in good condition while the places that were formerly well-tempered
|
||
|
some day grow excessively dry and deteriorate. This happened to the
|
||
|
land of Argos and Mycenae in Greece. In the time of the Trojan wars
|
||
|
the Argive land was marshy and could only support a small
|
||
|
population, whereas the land of Mycenae was in good condition (and for
|
||
|
this reason Mycenae was the superior). But now the opposite is the
|
||
|
case, for the reason we have mentioned: the land of Mycenae has become
|
||
|
completely dry and barren, while the Argive land that was formerly
|
||
|
barren owing to the water has now become fruitful. Now the same
|
||
|
process that has taken place in this small district must be supposed
|
||
|
to be going on over whole countries and on a large scale.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Men whose outlook is narrow suppose the cause of such events to be
|
||
|
change in the universe, in the sense of a coming to be of the world as
|
||
|
a whole. Hence they say that the sea being dried up and is growing
|
||
|
less, because this is observed to have happened in more places now
|
||
|
than formerly. But this is only partially true. It is true that many
|
||
|
places are now dry, that formerly were covered with water. But the
|
||
|
opposite is true too: for if they look they will find that there are
|
||
|
many places where the sea has invaded the land. But we must not
|
||
|
suppose that the cause of this is that the world is in process of
|
||
|
becoming. For it is absurd to make the universe to be in process
|
||
|
because of small and trifling changes, when the bulk and size of the
|
||
|
earth are surely as nothing in comparison with the whole world. Rather
|
||
|
we must take the cause of all these changes to be that, just as winter
|
||
|
occurs in the seasons of the year, so in determined periods there
|
||
|
comes a great winter of a great year and with it excess of rain. But
|
||
|
this excess does not always occur in the same place. The deluge in the
|
||
|
time of Deucalion, for instance, took place chiefly in the Greek world
|
||
|
and in it especially about ancient Hellas, the country about Dodona
|
||
|
and the Achelous, a river which has often changed its course. Here the
|
||
|
Selli dwelt and those who were formerly called Graeci and now
|
||
|
Hellenes. When, therefore, such an excess of rain occurs we must
|
||
|
suppose that it suffices for a long time. We have seen that some say
|
||
|
that the size of the subterranean cavities is what makes some rivers
|
||
|
perennial and others not, whereas we maintain that the size of the
|
||
|
mountains is the cause, and their density and coldness; for great,
|
||
|
dense, and cold mountains catch and keep and create most water:
|
||
|
whereas if the mountains that overhang the sources of rivers are small
|
||
|
or porous and stony and clayey, these rivers run dry earlier. We
|
||
|
must recognize the same kind of thing in this case too. Where such
|
||
|
abundance of rain falls in the great winter it tends to make the
|
||
|
moisture of those places almost everlasting. But as time goes on
|
||
|
places of the latter type dry up more, while those of the former,
|
||
|
moist type, do so less: until at last the beginning of the same
|
||
|
cycle returns.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since there is necessarily some change in the whole world, but not
|
||
|
in the way of coming into existence or perishing (for the universe
|
||
|
is permanent), it must be, as we say, that the same places are not for
|
||
|
ever moist through the presence of sea and rivers, nor for ever dry.
|
||
|
And the facts prove this. The whole land of the Egyptians, whom we
|
||
|
take to be the most ancient of men, has evidently gradually come
|
||
|
into existence and been produced by the river. This is clear from an
|
||
|
observation of the country, and the facts about the Red Sea suffice to
|
||
|
prove it too. One of their kings tried to make a canal to it (for it
|
||
|
would have been of no little advantage to them for the whole region to
|
||
|
have become navigable; Sesostris is said to have been the first of the
|
||
|
ancient kings to try), but he found that the sea was higher than the
|
||
|
land. So he first, and Darius afterwards, stopped making the canal,
|
||
|
lest the sea should mix with the river water and spoil it. So it is
|
||
|
clear that all this part was once unbroken sea. For the same reason
|
||
|
Libya-the country of Ammon-is, strangely enough, lower and hollower
|
||
|
than the land to the seaward of it. For it is clear that a barrier
|
||
|
of silt was formed and after it lakes and dry land, but in course of
|
||
|
time the water that was left behind in the lakes dried up and is now
|
||
|
all gone. Again the silting up of the lake Maeotis by the rivers has
|
||
|
advanced so much that the limit to the size of the ships which can now
|
||
|
sail into it to trade is much lower than it was sixty years ago. Hence
|
||
|
it is easy to infer that it, too, like most lakes, was originally
|
||
|
produced by the rivers and that it must end by drying up entirely.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, this process of silting up causes a continuous current
|
||
|
through the Bosporus; and in this case we can directly observe the
|
||
|
nature of the process. Whenever the current from the Asiatic shore
|
||
|
threw up a sandbank, there first formed a small lake behind it.
|
||
|
Later it dried up and a second sandbank formed in front of the first
|
||
|
and a second lake. This process went on uniformly and without
|
||
|
interruption. Now when this has been repeated often enough, in the
|
||
|
course of time the strait must become like a river, and in the end the
|
||
|
river itself must dry up.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So it is clear, since there will be no end to time and the world
|
||
|
is eternal, that neither the Tanais nor the Nile has always been
|
||
|
flowing, but that the region whence they flow was once dry: for
|
||
|
their effect may be fulfilled, but time cannot. And this will be
|
||
|
equally true of all other rivers. But if rivers come into existence
|
||
|
and perish and the same parts of the earth were not always moist,
|
||
|
the sea must needs change correspondingly. And if the sea is always
|
||
|
advancing in one place and receding in another it is clear that the
|
||
|
same parts of the whole earth are not always either sea or land, but
|
||
|
that all this changes in course of time.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So we have explained that the same parts of the earth are not always
|
||
|
land or sea and why that is so: and also why some rivers are perennial
|
||
|
and others not.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Book II
|
||
|
|
||
|
1
|
||
|
|
||
|
LET us explain the nature of the sea and the reason why such a large
|
||
|
mass of water is salt and the way in which it originally came to be.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The old writers who invented theogonies say that the sea has
|
||
|
springs, for they want earth and sea to have foundations and roots
|
||
|
of their own. Presumably they thought that this view was grander and
|
||
|
more impressive as implying that our earth was an important part of
|
||
|
the universe. For they believed that the whole world had been built up
|
||
|
round our earth and for its sake, and that the earth was the most
|
||
|
important and primary part of it. Others, wiser in human knowledge,
|
||
|
give an account of its origin. At first, they say, the earth was
|
||
|
surrounded by moisture. Then the sun began to dry it up, part of it
|
||
|
evaporated and is the cause of winds and the turnings back of the
|
||
|
sun and the moon, while the remainder forms the sea. So the sea is
|
||
|
being dried up and is growing less, and will end by being some day
|
||
|
entirely dried up. Others say that the sea is a kind of sweat exuded
|
||
|
by the earth when the sun heats it, and that this explains its
|
||
|
saltness: for all sweat is salt. Others say that the saltness is due
|
||
|
to the earth. Just as water strained through ashes becomes salt, so
|
||
|
the sea owes its saltness to the admixture of earth with similar
|
||
|
properties.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must now consider the facts which prove that the sea cannot
|
||
|
possibly have springs. The waters we find on the earth either flow
|
||
|
or are stationary. All flowing water has springs. (By a spring, as
|
||
|
we have explained above, we must not understand a source from which
|
||
|
waters are ladled as it were from a vessel, but a first point at which
|
||
|
the water which is continually forming and percolating gathers.)
|
||
|
Stationary water is either that which has collected and has been
|
||
|
left standing, marshy pools, for instance, and lakes, which differ
|
||
|
merely in size, or else it comes from springs. In this case it is
|
||
|
always artificial, I mean as in the case of wells, otherwise the
|
||
|
spring would have to be above the outlet. Hence the water from
|
||
|
fountains and rivers flows of itself, whereas wells need to be
|
||
|
worked artificially. All the waters that exist belong to one or
|
||
|
other of these classes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
On the basis of this division we can sec that the sea cannot have
|
||
|
springs. For it falls under neither of the two classes; it does not
|
||
|
flow and it is not artificial; whereas all water from springs must
|
||
|
belong to one or other of them. Natural standing water from springs is
|
||
|
never found on such a large scale.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, there are several seas that have no communication with one
|
||
|
another at all. The Red Sea, for instance, communicates but slightly
|
||
|
with the ocean outside the straits, and the Hyrcanian and Caspian seas
|
||
|
are distinct from this ocean and people dwell all round them. Hence,
|
||
|
if these seas had had any springs anywhere they must have been
|
||
|
discovered.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is true that in straits, where the land on either side
|
||
|
contracts an open sea into a small space, the sea appears to flow. But
|
||
|
this is because it is swinging to and fro. In the open sea this motion
|
||
|
is not observed, but where the land narrows and contracts the sea
|
||
|
the motion that was imperceptible in the open necessarily strikes
|
||
|
the attention.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The whole of the Mediterranean does actually flow. The direction
|
||
|
of this flow is determined by the depth of the basins and by the
|
||
|
number of rivers. Maeotis flows into Pontus and Pontus into the
|
||
|
Aegean. After that the flow of the remaining seas is not so easy to
|
||
|
observe. The current of Maeotis and Pontus is due to the number of
|
||
|
rivers (more rivers flow into the Euxine and Maeotis than into the
|
||
|
whole Mediterranean with its much larger basin), and to their own
|
||
|
shallowness. For we find the sea getting deeper and deeper. Pontus
|
||
|
is deeper than Maeotis, the Aegean than Pontus, the Sicilian sea
|
||
|
than the Aegean; the Sardinian and Tyrrhenic being the deepest of all.
|
||
|
(Outside the pillars of Heracles the sea is shallow owing to the
|
||
|
mud, but calm, for it lies in a hollow.) We see, then, that just as
|
||
|
single rivers flow from mountains, so it is with the earth as a whole:
|
||
|
the greatest volume of water flows from the higher regions in the
|
||
|
north. Their alluvium makes the northern seas shallow, while the outer
|
||
|
seas are deeper. Some further evidence of the height of the northern
|
||
|
regions of the earth is afforded by the view of many of the ancient
|
||
|
meteorologists. They believed that the sun did not pass below the
|
||
|
earth, but round its northern part, and that it was the height of this
|
||
|
which obscured the sun and caused night.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much to prove that there cannot be sources of the sea and to
|
||
|
explain its observed flow.
|
||
|
|
||
|
2
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must now discuss the origin of the sea, if it has an origin,
|
||
|
and the cause of its salt and bitter taste.
|
||
|
|
||
|
What made earlier writers consider the sea to be the original and
|
||
|
main body of water is this. It seems reasonable to suppose that to
|
||
|
be the case on the analogy of the other elements. Each of them has a
|
||
|
main bulk which by reason of its mass is the origin of that element,
|
||
|
and any parts which change and mix with the other elements come from
|
||
|
it. Thus the main body of fire is in the upper region; that of air
|
||
|
occupies the place next inside the region of fire; while the mass of
|
||
|
the earth is that round which the rest of the elements are seen to
|
||
|
lie. So we must clearly look for something analogous in the case of
|
||
|
water. But here we can find no such single mass, as in the case of the
|
||
|
other elements, except the sea. River water is not a unity, nor is
|
||
|
it stable, but is seen to be in a continuous process of becoming
|
||
|
from day to day. It was this difficulty which made people regard the
|
||
|
sea as the origin and source of moisture and of all water. And so we
|
||
|
find it maintained that rivers not only flow into the sea but
|
||
|
originate from it, the salt water becoming sweet by filtration.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But this view involves another difficulty. If this body of water
|
||
|
is the origin and source of all water, why is it salt and not sweet?
|
||
|
The reason for this, besides answering this question, will ensure
|
||
|
our having a right first conception of the nature of the sea.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The earth is surrounded by water, just as that is by the sphere of
|
||
|
air, and that again by the sphere called that of fire (which is the
|
||
|
outermost both on the common view and on ours). Now the sun, moving as
|
||
|
it does, sets up processes of change and becoming and decay, and by
|
||
|
its agency the finest and sweetest water is every day carried up and
|
||
|
is dissolved into vapour and rises to the upper region, where it is
|
||
|
condensed again by the cold and so returns to the earth. This, as we
|
||
|
have said before, is the regular course of nature.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hence all my predecessors who supposed that the sun was nourished by
|
||
|
moisture are absurdly mistaken. Some go on to say that the solstices
|
||
|
are due to this, the reason being that the same places cannot always
|
||
|
supply the sun with nourishment and that without it he must perish.
|
||
|
For the fire we are familiar with lives as long as it is fed, and
|
||
|
the only food for fire is moisture. As if the moisture that is
|
||
|
raised could reach the sun! or this ascent were really like that
|
||
|
performed by flame as it comes into being, and to which they
|
||
|
supposed the case of the sun to be analogous! Really there is no
|
||
|
similarity. A flame is a process of becoming, involving a constant
|
||
|
interchange of moist and dry. It cannot be said to be nourished
|
||
|
since it scarcely persists as one and the same for a moment. This
|
||
|
cannot be true of the sun; for if it were nourished like that, as they
|
||
|
say it is, we should obviously not only have a new sun every day, as
|
||
|
Heraclitus says, but a new sun every moment. Again, when the sun
|
||
|
causes the moisture to rise, this is like fire heating water. So, as
|
||
|
the fire is not fed by the water above it, it is absurd to suppose
|
||
|
that the sun feeds on that moisture, even if its heat made all the
|
||
|
water in the world evaporate. Again, it is absurd, considering the
|
||
|
number and size of the stars, that these thinkers should consider
|
||
|
the sun only and overlook the question how the rest of the heavenly
|
||
|
bodies subsist. Again, they are met by the same difficulty as those
|
||
|
who say that at first the earth itself was moist and the world round
|
||
|
the earth was warmed by the sun, and so air was generated and the
|
||
|
whole firmament grew, and the air caused winds and solstices. The
|
||
|
objection is that we always plainly see the water that has been
|
||
|
carried up coming down again. Even if the same amount does not come
|
||
|
back in a year or in a given country, yet in a certain period all that
|
||
|
has been carried up is returned. This implies that the celestial
|
||
|
bodies do not feed on it, and that we cannot distinguish between
|
||
|
some air which preserves its character once it is generated and some
|
||
|
other which is generated but becomes water again and so perishes; on
|
||
|
the contrary, all the moisture alike is dissolved and all of it
|
||
|
condensed back into water.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The drinkable, sweet water, then, is light and is all of it drawn
|
||
|
up: the salt water is heavy and remains behind, but not in its natural
|
||
|
place. For this is a question which has been sufficiently discussed (I
|
||
|
mean about the natural place that water, like the other elements, must
|
||
|
in reason have), and the answer is this. The place which we see the
|
||
|
sea filling is not its natural place but that of water. It seems to
|
||
|
belong to the sea because the weight of the salt water makes it remain
|
||
|
there, while the sweet, drinkable water which is light is carried
|
||
|
up. The same thing happens in animal bodies. Here, too, the food
|
||
|
when it enters the body is sweet, yet the residuum and dregs of liquid
|
||
|
food are found to be bitter and salt. This is because the sweet and
|
||
|
drinkable part of it has been drawn away by the natural animal heat
|
||
|
and has passed into the flesh and the other parts of the body
|
||
|
according to their several natures. Now just as here it would be wrong
|
||
|
for any one to refuse to call the belly the place of liquid food
|
||
|
because that disappears from it soon, and to call it the place of
|
||
|
the residuum because this is seen to remain, so in the case of our
|
||
|
present subject. This place, we say, is the place of water. Hence
|
||
|
all rivers and all the water that is generated flow into it: for water
|
||
|
flows into the deepest place, and the deepest part of the earth is
|
||
|
filled by the sea. Only all the light and sweet part of it is
|
||
|
quickly carried off by the sun, while herest remains for the reason we
|
||
|
have explained. It is quite natural that some people should have
|
||
|
been puzzled by the old question why such a mass of water leaves no
|
||
|
trace anywhere (for the sea does not increase though innumerable and
|
||
|
vast rivers are flowing into it every day.) But if one considers the
|
||
|
matter the solution is easy. The same amount of water does not take as
|
||
|
long to dry up when it is spread out as when it is gathered in a body,
|
||
|
and indeed the difference is so great that in the one case it might
|
||
|
persist the whole day long while in the other it might all disappear
|
||
|
in a moment-as for instance if one were to spread out a cup of water
|
||
|
over a large table. This is the case with the rivers: all the time
|
||
|
they are flowing their water forms a compact mass, but when it arrives
|
||
|
at a vast wide place it quickly and imperceptibly evaporates.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But the theory of the Phaedo about rivers and the sea is impossible.
|
||
|
There it is said that the earth is pierced by intercommunicating
|
||
|
channels and that the original head and source of all waters is what
|
||
|
is called Tartarus-a mass of water about the centre, from which all
|
||
|
waters, flowing and standing, are derived. This primary and original
|
||
|
water is always surging to and fro, and so it causes the rivers to
|
||
|
flow on this side of the earth's centre and on that; for it has no
|
||
|
fixed seat but is always oscillating about the centre. Its motion up
|
||
|
and down is what fills rivers. Many of these form lakes in various
|
||
|
places (our sea is an instance of one of these), but all of them
|
||
|
come round again in a circle to the original source of their flow,
|
||
|
many at the same point, but some at a point opposite to that from
|
||
|
which they issued; for instance, if they started from the other side
|
||
|
of the earth's centre, they might return from this side of it. They
|
||
|
descend only as far as the centre, for after that all motion is
|
||
|
upwards. Water gets its tastes and colours from the kind of earth
|
||
|
the rivers happened to flow through.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But on this theory rivers do not always flow in the same sense.
|
||
|
For since they flow to the centre from which they issue forth they
|
||
|
will not be flowing down any more than up, but in whatever direction
|
||
|
the surging of Tartarus inclines to. But at this rate we shall get the
|
||
|
proverbial rivers flowing upwards, which is impossible. Again, where
|
||
|
is the water that is generated and what goes up again as vapour to
|
||
|
come from? For this must all of it simply be ignored, since the
|
||
|
quantity of water is always the same and all the water that flows
|
||
|
out from the original source flows back to it again. This itself is
|
||
|
not true, since all rivers are seen to end in the sea except where one
|
||
|
flows into another. Not one of them ends in the earth, but even when
|
||
|
one is swallowed up it comes to the surface again. And those rivers
|
||
|
are large which flow for a long distance through a lowying country,
|
||
|
for by their situation and length they cut off the course of many
|
||
|
others and swallow them up. This is why the Istrus and the Nile are
|
||
|
the greatest of the rivers which flow into our sea. Indeed, so many
|
||
|
rivers fall into them that there is disagreement as to the sources
|
||
|
of them both. All of which is plainly impossible on the theory, and
|
||
|
the more so as it derives the sea from Tartarus.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Enough has been said to prove that this is the natural place of
|
||
|
water and not of the sea, and to explain why sweet water is only found
|
||
|
in rivers, while salt water is stationary, and to show that the sea is
|
||
|
the end rather than the source of water, analogous to the residual
|
||
|
matter of all food, and especially liquid food, in animal bodies.
|
||
|
|
||
|
3
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must now explain why the sea is salt, and ask whether it
|
||
|
eternally exists as identically the same body, or whether it did not
|
||
|
exist at all once and some day will exist no longer, but will dry up
|
||
|
as some people think.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Every one admits this, that if the whole world originated the sea
|
||
|
did too; for they make them come into being at the same time. It
|
||
|
follows that if the universe is eternal the same must be true of the
|
||
|
sea. Any one who thinks like Democritus that the sea is diminishing
|
||
|
and will disappear in the end reminds us of Aesop's tales. His story
|
||
|
was that Charybdis had twice sucked in the sea: the first time she
|
||
|
made the mountains visible; the second time the islands; and when
|
||
|
she sucks it in for the last time she will dry it up entirely. Such
|
||
|
a tale is appropriate enough to Aesop in a rage with the ferryman, but
|
||
|
not to serious inquirers. Whatever made the sea remain at first,
|
||
|
whether it was its weight, as some even of those who hold these
|
||
|
views say (for it is easy to see the cause here), or some other
|
||
|
reason-clearly the same thing must make it persist for ever. They must
|
||
|
either deny that the water raised by the sun will return at all, or,
|
||
|
if it does, they must admit that the sea persists for ever or as
|
||
|
long as this process goes on, and again, that for the same period of
|
||
|
time that sweet water must have been carried up beforehand. So the sea
|
||
|
will never dry up: for before that can happen the water that has
|
||
|
gone up beforehand will return to it: for if you say that this happens
|
||
|
once you must admit its recurrence. If you stop the sun's course there
|
||
|
is no drying agency. If you let it go on it will draw up the sweet
|
||
|
water as we have said whenever it approaches, and let it descend again
|
||
|
when it recedes. This notion about the sea is derived from the fact
|
||
|
that many places are found to be drier now than they once were. Why
|
||
|
this is so we have explained. The phenomenon is due to temporary
|
||
|
excess of rain and not to any process of becoming in which the
|
||
|
universe or its parts are involved. Some day the opposite will take
|
||
|
place and after that the earth will grow dry once again. We must
|
||
|
recognize that this process always goes on thus in a cycle, for that
|
||
|
is more satisfactory than to suppose a change in the whole world in
|
||
|
order to explain these facts. But we have dwelt longer on this point
|
||
|
than it deserves.
|
||
|
|
||
|
To return to the saltness of the sea: those who create the sea
|
||
|
once for all, or indeed generate it at all, cannot account for its
|
||
|
saltness. It makes no difference whether the sea is the residue of all
|
||
|
the moisture that is about the earth and has been drawn up by the sun,
|
||
|
or whether all the flavour existing in the whole mass of sweet water
|
||
|
is due to the admixture of a certain kind of earth. Since the total
|
||
|
volume of the sea is the same once the water that evaporated has
|
||
|
returned, it follows that it must either have been salt at first
|
||
|
too, or, if not at first, then not now either. If it was salt from the
|
||
|
very beginning, then we want to know why that was so; and why, if salt
|
||
|
water was drawn up then, that is not the case now.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, if it is maintained that an admixture of earth makes the
|
||
|
sea salt (for they say that earth has many flavours and is washed down
|
||
|
by the rivers and so makes the sea salt by its admixture), it is
|
||
|
strange that rivers should not be salt too. How can the admixture of
|
||
|
this earth have such a striking effect in a great quantity of water
|
||
|
and not in each river singly? For the sea, differing in nothing from
|
||
|
rivers but in being salt, is evidently simply the totality of river
|
||
|
water, and the rivers are the vehicle in which that earth is carried
|
||
|
to their common destination.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is equally absurd to suppose that anything has been explained
|
||
|
by calling the sea 'the sweat of the earth', like Empedicles.
|
||
|
Metaphors are poetical and so that expression of his may satisfy the
|
||
|
requirements of a poem, but as a scientific theory it is
|
||
|
unsatisfactory. Even in the case of the body it is a question how
|
||
|
the sweet liquid drunk becomes salt sweat whether it is merely by
|
||
|
the departure of some element in it which is sweetest, or by the
|
||
|
admixture of something, as when water is strained through ashes.
|
||
|
Actually the saltness seems to be due to the same cause as in the case
|
||
|
of the residual liquid that gathers in the bladder. That, too, becomes
|
||
|
bitter and salt though the liquid we drink and that contained in our
|
||
|
food is sweet. If then the bitterness is due in these cases (as with
|
||
|
the water strained through lye) to the presence of a certain sort of
|
||
|
stuff that is carried along by the urine (as indeed we actually find a
|
||
|
salt deposit settling in chamber-pots) and is secreted from the
|
||
|
flesh in sweat (as if the departing moisture were washing the stuff
|
||
|
out of the body), then no doubt the admixture of something earthy with
|
||
|
the water is what makes the sea salt.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now in the body stuff of this kind, viz. the sediment of food, is
|
||
|
due to failure to digest: but how there came to be any such thing in
|
||
|
the earth requires explanation. Besides, how can the drying and
|
||
|
warming of the earth cause the secretion such a great quantity of
|
||
|
water; especially as that must be a mere fragment of what is left in
|
||
|
the earth? Again, waiving the question of quantity, why does not the
|
||
|
earth sweat now when it happens to be in process of drying? If it
|
||
|
did so then, it ought to do so now. But it does not: on the
|
||
|
contrary, when it is dry it graws moist, but when it is moist it
|
||
|
does not secrete anything at all. How then was it possible for the
|
||
|
earth at the beginning when it was moist to sweat as it grew dry?
|
||
|
Indeed, the theory that maintains that most of the moisture departed
|
||
|
and was drawn up by the sun and that what was left over is the sea
|
||
|
is more reasonable; but for the earth to sweat when it is moist is
|
||
|
impossible.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since all the attempts to account for the saltness of the sea seem
|
||
|
unsuccessful let us explain it by the help of the principle we have
|
||
|
used already.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since we recognize two kinds of evaporation, one moist, the other
|
||
|
dry, it is clear that the latter must be recognized as the source of
|
||
|
phenomena like those we are concerned with.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But there is a question which we must discuss first. Does the sea
|
||
|
always remain numerically one and consisting of the same parts, or
|
||
|
is it, too, one in form and volume while its parts are in continual
|
||
|
change, like air and sweet water and fire? All of these are in a
|
||
|
constant state of change, but the form and the quantity of each of
|
||
|
them are fixed, just as they are in the case of a flowing river or a
|
||
|
burning flame. The answer is clear, and there is no doubt that the
|
||
|
same account holds good of all these things alike. They differ in that
|
||
|
some of them change more rapidly or more slowly than others; and
|
||
|
they all are involved in a process of perishing and becoming which yet
|
||
|
affects them all in a regular course.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This being so we must go on to try to explain why the sea is salt.
|
||
|
There are many facts which make it clear that this taste is due to the
|
||
|
admixture of something. First, in animal bodies what is least
|
||
|
digested, the residue of liquid food, is salt and bitter, as we said
|
||
|
before. All animal excreta are undigested, but especially that which
|
||
|
gathers in the bladder (its extreme lightness proves this; for
|
||
|
everything that is digested is condensed), and also sweat; in these
|
||
|
then is excreted (along with other matter) an identical substance to
|
||
|
which this flavour is due. The case of things burnt is analogous. What
|
||
|
heat fails to assimilate becomes the excrementary residue in animal
|
||
|
bodies, and, in things burnt, ashes. That is why some people say
|
||
|
that it was burnt earth that made the sea salt. To say that it was
|
||
|
burnt earth is absurd; but to say that it was something like burnt
|
||
|
earth is true. We must suppose that just as in the cases we have
|
||
|
described, so in the world as a whole, everything that grows and is
|
||
|
naturally generated always leaves an undigested residue, like that
|
||
|
of things burnt, consisting of this sort of earth. All the earthy
|
||
|
stuff in the dry exhalation is of this nature, and it is the dry
|
||
|
exhalation which accounts for its great quantity. Now since, as we
|
||
|
have said, the moist and the dry evaporations are mixed, some quantity
|
||
|
of this stuff must always be included in the clouds and the water that
|
||
|
are formed by condensation, and must redescend to the earth in rain.
|
||
|
This process must always go on with such regularity as the sublunary
|
||
|
world admits of. and it is the answer to the question how the sea
|
||
|
comes to be salt.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It also explains why rain that comes from the south, and the first
|
||
|
rains of autumn, are brackish. The south is the warmest of winds and
|
||
|
it blows from dry and hot regions. Hence it carries little moist
|
||
|
vapour and that is why it is hot. (It makes no difference even if this
|
||
|
is not its true character and it is originally a cold wind, for it
|
||
|
becomes warm on its way by incorporating with itself a great
|
||
|
quantity of dry evaporation from the places it passes over.) The north
|
||
|
wind, on the other hand, comb ing from moist regions, is full of
|
||
|
vapour and therefore cold. It is dry in our part of the world
|
||
|
because it drives the clouds away before it, but in the south it is
|
||
|
rainy; just as the south is a dry wind in Libya. So the south wind
|
||
|
charges the rain that falls with a great quantity of this stuff.
|
||
|
Autumn rain is brackish because the heaviest water must fall first; so
|
||
|
that that which contains the greatest quantity of this kind of earth
|
||
|
descends quickest.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This, too, is why the sea is warm. Everything that has been
|
||
|
exposed to fire contains heat potentially, as we see in the case of
|
||
|
lye and ashes and the dry and liquid excreta of animals. Indeed
|
||
|
those animals which are hottest in the belly have the hottest excreta.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The action of this cause is continually making the sea more salt,
|
||
|
but some part of its saltness is always being drawn up with the
|
||
|
sweet water. This is less than the sweet water in the same ratio in
|
||
|
which the salt and brackish element in rain is less than the sweet,
|
||
|
and so the saltness of the sea remains constant on the whole. Salt
|
||
|
water when it turns into vapour becomes sweet, and the vapour does not
|
||
|
form salt water when it condenses again. This I know by experiment.
|
||
|
The same thing is true in every case of the kind: wine and all
|
||
|
fluids that evaporate and condense back into a liquid state become
|
||
|
water. They all are water modified by a certain admixture, the
|
||
|
nature of which determines their flavour. But this subject must be
|
||
|
considered on another more suitable occasion.
|
||
|
|
||
|
For the present let us say this. The sea is there and some of it
|
||
|
is continually being drawn up and becoming sweet; this returns from
|
||
|
above with the rain. But it is now different from what it was when
|
||
|
it was drawn up, and its weight makes it sink below the sweet water.
|
||
|
This process prevents the sea, as it does rivers, from drying up
|
||
|
except from local causes (this must happen to sea and rivers alike).
|
||
|
On the other hand the parts neither of the earth nor of the sea remain
|
||
|
constant but only their whole bulk. For the same thing is true of
|
||
|
the earth as of the sea: some of it is carried up and some comes
|
||
|
down with the rain, and both that which remains on the surface and
|
||
|
that which comes down again change their situations.
|
||
|
|
||
|
There is more evidence to prove that saltness is due to the
|
||
|
admixture of some substance, besides that which we have adduced.
|
||
|
Make a vessel of wax and put it in the sea, fastening its mouth in
|
||
|
such a way as to prevent any water getting in. Then the water that
|
||
|
percolates through the wax sides of the vessel is sweet, the earthy
|
||
|
stuff, the admixture of which makes the water salt, being separated
|
||
|
off as it were by a filter. It is this stuff which make salt water
|
||
|
heavy (it weighs more than fresh water) and thick. The difference in
|
||
|
consistency is such that ships with the same cargo very nearly sink in
|
||
|
a river when they are quite fit to navigate in the sea. This
|
||
|
circumstance has before now caused loss to shippers freighting their
|
||
|
ships in a river. That the thicker consistency is due to an
|
||
|
admixture of something is proved by the fact that if you make strong
|
||
|
brine by the admixture of salt, eggs, even when they are full, float
|
||
|
in it. It almost becomes like mud; such a quantity of earthy matter is
|
||
|
there in the sea. The same thing is done in salting fish.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again if, as is fabled, there is a lake in Palestine, such that if
|
||
|
you bind a man or beast and throw it in it floats and does not sink,
|
||
|
this would bear out what we have said. They say that this lake is so
|
||
|
bitter and salt that no fish live in it and that if you soak clothes
|
||
|
in it and shake them it cleans them. The following facts all of them
|
||
|
support our theory that it is some earthy stuff in the water which
|
||
|
makes it salt. In Chaonia there is a spring of brackish water that
|
||
|
flows into a neighbouring river which is sweet but contains no fish.
|
||
|
The local story is that when Heracles came from Erytheia driving the
|
||
|
oxen and gave the inhabitants the choice, they chose salt in
|
||
|
preference to fish. They get the salt from the spring. They boil off
|
||
|
some of the water and let the rest stand; when it has cooled and the
|
||
|
heat and moisture have evaporated together it gives them salt, not
|
||
|
in lumps but loose and light like snow. It is weaker than ordinary
|
||
|
salt and added freely gives a sweet taste, and it is not as white as
|
||
|
salt generally is. Another instance of this is found in Umbria.
|
||
|
There is a place there where reeds and rushes grow. They burn some
|
||
|
of these, put the ashes into water and boil it off. When a little
|
||
|
water is left and has cooled it gives a quantity of salt.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Most salt rivers and springs must once have been hot. Then the
|
||
|
original fire in them was extinguished but the earth through which
|
||
|
they percolate preserves the character of lye or ashes. Springs and
|
||
|
rivers with all kinds of flavours are found in many places. These
|
||
|
flavours must in every case be due to the fire that is or was in them,
|
||
|
for if you expose earth to different degrees of heat it assumes
|
||
|
various kinds and shades of flavour. It becomes full of alum and lye
|
||
|
and other things of the kind, and the fresh water percolates through
|
||
|
these and changes its character. Sometimes it becomes acid as in
|
||
|
Sicania, a part of Sicily. There they get a salt and acid water
|
||
|
which they use as vinegar to season some of their dishes. In the
|
||
|
neighbourhood of Lyncus, too, there is a spring of acid water, and
|
||
|
in Scythia a bitter spring. The water from this makes the whole of the
|
||
|
river into which it flows bitter. These differences are explained by a
|
||
|
knowledge of the particular mixtures that determine different savours.
|
||
|
But these have been explained in another treatise.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now given an account of waters and the sea, why they
|
||
|
persist, how they change, what their nature is, and have explained
|
||
|
most of their natural operations and affections.
|
||
|
|
||
|
4
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us proceed to the theory of winds. Its basis is a distinction we
|
||
|
have already made. We recognize two kinds of evaporation, one moist,
|
||
|
the other dry. The former is called vapour: for the other there is
|
||
|
no general name but we must call it a sort of smoke, applying to the
|
||
|
whole of it a word that is proper to one of its forms. The moist
|
||
|
cannot exist without the dry nor the dry without the moist: whenever
|
||
|
we speak of either we mean that it predominates. Now when the sun in
|
||
|
its circular course approaches, it draws up by its heat the moist
|
||
|
evaporation: when it recedes the cold makes the vapour that had been
|
||
|
raised condense back into water which falls and is distributed through
|
||
|
the earth. (This explains why there is more rain in winter and more by
|
||
|
night than by day: though the fact is not recognized because rain by
|
||
|
night is more apt to escape observation than by day.) But there is a
|
||
|
great quantity of fire and heat in the earth, and the sun not only
|
||
|
draws up the moisture that lies on the surface of it, but warms and
|
||
|
dries the earth itself. Consequently, since there are two kinds of
|
||
|
evaporation, as we have said, one like vapour, the other like smoke,
|
||
|
both of them are necessarily generated. That in which moisture
|
||
|
predominates is the source of rain, as we explained before, while
|
||
|
the dry evaporation is the source and substance of all winds. That
|
||
|
things must necessarily take this course is clear from the resulting
|
||
|
phenomena themselves, for the evaporation that is to produce them must
|
||
|
necessarily differ; and the sun and the warmth in the earth not only
|
||
|
can but must produce these evaporations.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since the two evaporations are specifically distinct, wind and
|
||
|
rain obviously differ and their substance is not the same, as those
|
||
|
say who maintain that one and the same air when in motion is wind, but
|
||
|
when it condenses again is water. Air, as we have explained in an
|
||
|
earlier book, is made up of these as constituents. Vapour is moist
|
||
|
and cold (for its fluidity is due to its moistness, and because it
|
||
|
derives from water it is naturally cold, like water that has not
|
||
|
been warmed): whereas the smoky evaporation is hot and dry. Hence each
|
||
|
contributes a part, and air is moist and hot. It is absurd that this
|
||
|
air that surrounds us should become wind when in motion, whatever be
|
||
|
the source of its motion on the contrary the case of winds is like
|
||
|
that of rivers. We do not call water that flows anyhow a river, even
|
||
|
if there is a great quantity of it, but only if the flow comes from
|
||
|
a spring. So too with the winds; a great quantity of air might be
|
||
|
moved by the fall of some large object without flowing from any source
|
||
|
or spring.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The facts bear out our theory. It is because the evaporation takes
|
||
|
place uninterruptedly but differs in degree and quantity that clouds
|
||
|
and winds appear in their natural proportion according to the
|
||
|
season; and it is because there is now a great excess of the vaporous,
|
||
|
now of the dry and smoky exhalation, that some years are rainy and
|
||
|
wet, others windy and dry. Sometimes there is much drought or rain,
|
||
|
and it prevails over a great and continuous stretch of country. At
|
||
|
other times it is local; the surrounding country often getting
|
||
|
seasonable or even excessive rains while there is drought in a certain
|
||
|
part; or, contrariwise, all the surrounding country gets little or
|
||
|
even no rain while a certain part gets rain in abundance. The reason
|
||
|
for all this is that while the same affection is generally apt to
|
||
|
prevail over a considerable district because adjacent places (unless
|
||
|
there is something special to differentiate them) stand in the same
|
||
|
relation to the sun, yet on occasion the dry evaporation will
|
||
|
prevail in one part and the moist in another, or conversely. Again the
|
||
|
reason for this latter is that each evaporation goes over to that of
|
||
|
the neighbouring district: for instance, the dry evaporation
|
||
|
circulates in its own place while the moist migrates to the next
|
||
|
district or is even driven by winds to some distant place: or else the
|
||
|
moist evaporation remains and the dry moves away. Just as in the
|
||
|
case of the body when the stomach is dry the lower belly is often in
|
||
|
the contrary state, and when it is dry the stomach is moist and
|
||
|
cold, so it often happens that the evaporations reciprocally take
|
||
|
one another's place and interchange.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Further, after rain wind generally rises in those places where the
|
||
|
rain fell, and when rain has come on the wind ceases. These are
|
||
|
necessary effects of the principles we have explained. After rain
|
||
|
the earth is being dried by its own heat and that from above and gives
|
||
|
off the evaporation which we saw to be the material cause of. wind.
|
||
|
Again, suppose this secretion is present and wind prevails; the heat
|
||
|
is continually being thrown off, rising to the upper region, and so
|
||
|
the wind ceases; then the fall in temperature makes vapour form and
|
||
|
condense into water. Water also forms and cools the dry evaporation
|
||
|
when the clouds are driven together and the cold concentrated in them.
|
||
|
These are the causes that make wind cease on the advent of rain, and
|
||
|
rain fall on the cessation of wind.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The cause of the predominance of winds from the north and from the
|
||
|
south is the same. (Most winds, as a matter of fact, are north winds
|
||
|
or south winds.) These are the only regions which the sun does not
|
||
|
visit: it approaches them and recedes from them, but its course is
|
||
|
always over the-west and the east. Hence clouds collect on either
|
||
|
side, and when the sun approaches it provokes the moist evaporation,
|
||
|
and when it recedes to the opposite side there are storms and rain. So
|
||
|
summer and winter are due to the sun's motion to and from the
|
||
|
solstices, and water ascends and falls again for the same reason.
|
||
|
Now since most rain falls in those regions towards which and from
|
||
|
which the sun turns and these are the north and the south, and since
|
||
|
most evaporation must take place where there is the greatest rainfall,
|
||
|
just as green wood gives most smoke, and since this evaporation is
|
||
|
wind, it is natural that the most and most important winds should come
|
||
|
from these quarters. (The winds from the north are called Boreae,
|
||
|
those from the south Noti.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
The course of winds is oblique: for though the evaporation rises
|
||
|
straight up from the earth, they blow round it because all the
|
||
|
surrounding air follows the motion of the heavens. Hence the
|
||
|
question might be asked whether winds originate from above or from
|
||
|
below. The motion comes from above: before we feel the wind blowing
|
||
|
the air betrays its presence if there are clouds or a mist, for
|
||
|
their motion shows that the wind has begun to blow before it has
|
||
|
actually reached us; and this implies that the source of winds is
|
||
|
above. But since wind is defined as 'a quantity of dry evaporation
|
||
|
from the earth moving round the earth', it is clear that while the
|
||
|
origin of the motion is from above, the matter and the generation of
|
||
|
wind come from below. The oblique movement of the rising evaporation
|
||
|
is caused from above: for the motion of the heavens determines the
|
||
|
processes that are at a distance from the earth, and the motion from
|
||
|
below is vertical and every cause is more active where it is nearest
|
||
|
to the effect; but in its generation and origin wind plainly derives
|
||
|
from the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The facts bear out the view that winds are formed by the gradual
|
||
|
union of many evaporations just as rivers derive their sources from
|
||
|
the water that oozes from the earth. Every wind is weakest in the spot
|
||
|
from which it blows; as they proceed and leave their source at a
|
||
|
distance they gather strength. Thus the winter in the north is
|
||
|
windless and calm: that is, in the north itself; but, the breeze
|
||
|
that blows from there so gently as to escape observation becomes a
|
||
|
great wind as it passes on.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have explained the nature and origin of wind, the occurrence of
|
||
|
drought and rains, the reason why rain stops wind and wind rises after
|
||
|
rain, the prevalence of north and south winds and also why wind
|
||
|
moves in the way it does.
|
||
|
|
||
|
5
|
||
|
|
||
|
The sun both checks the formation of winds and stimulates it. When
|
||
|
the evaporation is small in amount and faint the sun wastes it and
|
||
|
dissipates by its greater heat the lesser heat contained in the
|
||
|
evaporation. It also dries up the earth, the source of the
|
||
|
evaporation, before the latter has appeared in bulk: just as, when you
|
||
|
throw a little fuel into a great fire, it is often burnt up before
|
||
|
giving off any smoke. In these ways the sun checks winds and
|
||
|
prevents them from rising at all: it checks them by wasting the
|
||
|
evaporation, and prevents their rising by drying up the earth quickly.
|
||
|
Hence calm is very apt to prevail about the rising of Orion and
|
||
|
lasts until the coming of the Etesiae and their 'forerunners'.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Calm is due to two causes. Either cold quenches the evaporation, for
|
||
|
instance a sharp frost: or excessive heat wastes it. In the
|
||
|
intermediate periods, too, the causes are generally either that the
|
||
|
evaporation has not had time to develop or that it has passed away and
|
||
|
there is none as yet to replace it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Both the setting and the rising of Orion are considered to be
|
||
|
treacherous and stormy, because they place at a change of season
|
||
|
(namely of summer or winter; and because the size of the constellation
|
||
|
makes its rise last over many days) and a state of change is always
|
||
|
indefinite and therefore liable to disturbance.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The Etesiae blow after the summer solstice and the rising of the
|
||
|
dog-star: not at the time when the sun is closest nor when it is
|
||
|
distant; and they blow by day and cease at night. The reason is that
|
||
|
when the sun is near it dries up the earth before evaporation has
|
||
|
taken place, but when it has receded a little its heat and the
|
||
|
evaporation are present in the right proportion; so the ice melts
|
||
|
and the earth, dried by its own heat and that of the sun, smokes and
|
||
|
vapours. They abate at night because the cold pf the nights checks the
|
||
|
melting of the ice. What is frozen gives off no evaporation, nor
|
||
|
does that which contains no dryness at all: it is only where something
|
||
|
dry contains moisture that it gives off evaporation under the
|
||
|
influence of heat.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The question is sometimes asked: why do the north winds which we
|
||
|
call the Etesiae blow continuously after the summer solstice, when
|
||
|
there are no corresponding south winds after the winter solstice?
|
||
|
The facts are reasonable enough: for the so-called 'white south winds'
|
||
|
do blow at the corresponding season, though they are not equally
|
||
|
continuous and so escape observation and give rise to this inquiry.
|
||
|
The reason for this is that the north wind I from the arctic regions
|
||
|
which are full of water and snow. The sun thaws them and so the
|
||
|
Etesiae blow: after rather than at the summer solstice. (For the
|
||
|
greatest heat is developed not when the sun is nearest to the north,
|
||
|
but when its heat has been felt for a considerable period and it has
|
||
|
not yet receded far. The 'bird winds' blow in the same way after the
|
||
|
winter solstice. They, too, are weak Etesiae, but they blow less and
|
||
|
later than the Etesiae. They begin to blow only on the seventieth
|
||
|
day because the sun is distant and therefore weaker. They do not
|
||
|
blow so continuously because only things on the surface of the earth
|
||
|
and offering little resistance evaporate then, the thoroughly frozen
|
||
|
parts requiring greater heat to melt them. So they blow intermittently
|
||
|
till the true Etesiae come on again at the summer solstice: for from
|
||
|
that time onwards the wind tends to blow continuously.) But the
|
||
|
south wind blows from the tropic of Cancer and not from the
|
||
|
antarctic region.
|
||
|
|
||
|
There are two inhabitable sections of the earth: one near our upper,
|
||
|
or nothern pole, the other near the other or southern pole; and
|
||
|
their shape is like that of a tambourine. If you draw lines from the
|
||
|
centre of the earth they cut out a drum-shaped figure. The lines
|
||
|
form two cones; the base of the one is the tropic, of the other the
|
||
|
ever visible circle, their vertex is at the centre of the earth. Two
|
||
|
other cones towards the south pole give corresponding segments of
|
||
|
the earth. These sections alone are habitable. Beyond the tropics no
|
||
|
one can live: for there the shade would not fall to the north, whereas
|
||
|
the earth is known to be uninhabitable before the sun is in the zenith
|
||
|
or the shade is thrown to the south: and the regions below the Bear
|
||
|
are uninhabitable because of the cold.
|
||
|
|
||
|
(The Crown, too, moves over this region: for it is in the zenith
|
||
|
when it is on our meridian.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
So we see that the way in which they now describe the geography of
|
||
|
the earth is ridiculous. They depict the inhabited earth as round, but
|
||
|
both ascertained facts and general considerations show this to be
|
||
|
impossible. If we reflect we see that the inhabited region is
|
||
|
limited in breadth, while the climate admits of its extending all
|
||
|
round the earth. For we meet with no excessive heat or cold in the
|
||
|
direction of its length but only in that of its breadth; so that there
|
||
|
is nothing to prevent our travelling round the earth unless the extent
|
||
|
of the sea presents an obstacle anywhere. The records of journeys by
|
||
|
sea and land bear this out. They make the length far greater than
|
||
|
the breadth. If we compute these voyages and journeys the distance
|
||
|
from the Pillars of Heracles to India exceeds that from Aethiopia to
|
||
|
Maeotis and the northernmost Scythians by a ratio of more than 5 to 3,
|
||
|
as far as such matters admit of accurate statement. Yet we know the
|
||
|
whole breadth of the region we dwell in up to the uninhabited parts:
|
||
|
in one direction no one lives because of the cold, in the other
|
||
|
because of the heat.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But it is the sea which divides as it seems the parts beyond India
|
||
|
from those beyond the Pillars of Heracles and prevents the earth
|
||
|
from being inhabited all round.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now since there must be a region bearing the same relation to the
|
||
|
southern pole as the place we live in bears to our pole, it will
|
||
|
clearly correspond in the ordering of its winds as well as in other
|
||
|
things. So just as we have a north wind here, they must have a
|
||
|
corresponding wind from the antarctic. This wind cannot reach us since
|
||
|
our own north wind is like a land breeze and does not even reach the
|
||
|
limits of the region we live in. The prevalence of north winds here is
|
||
|
due to our lying near the north. Yet even here they give out and
|
||
|
fail to penetrate far: in the southern sea beyond Libya east and
|
||
|
west winds are always blowing alternately, like north and south
|
||
|
winds with us. So it is clear that the south wind is not the wind that
|
||
|
blows from the south pole. It is neither that nor the wind from the
|
||
|
winter tropic. For symmetry would require another wind blowing from
|
||
|
the summer tropic, which there is not, since we know that only one
|
||
|
wind blows from that quarter. So the south wind clearly blows from the
|
||
|
torrid region. Now the sun is so near to that region that it has no
|
||
|
water, or snow which might melt and cause Etesiae. But because that
|
||
|
place is far more extensive and open the south wind is greater and
|
||
|
stronger and warmer than the north and penetrates farther to the north
|
||
|
than the north wind does to the south.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The origin of these winds and their relation to one another has
|
||
|
now been explained.
|
||
|
|
||
|
6
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us now explain the position of the winds, their oppositions,
|
||
|
which can blow simultaneously with which, and which cannot, their
|
||
|
names and number, and any other of their affections that have not been
|
||
|
treated in the 'particular questions'. What we say about their
|
||
|
position must be followed with the help of the figure. For
|
||
|
clearness' sake we have drawn the circle of the horizon, which is
|
||
|
round, but it represents the zone in which we live; for that can be
|
||
|
divided in the same way. Let us also begin by laying down that those
|
||
|
things are locally contrary which are locally most distant from one
|
||
|
another, just as things specifically most remote from one another
|
||
|
are specific contraries. Now things that face one another from
|
||
|
opposite ends of a diameter are locally most distant from one another.
|
||
|
(See diagram.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let A be the point where the sun sets at the equinox and B, the
|
||
|
point opposite, the place where it rises at the equinox. Let there
|
||
|
be another diameter cutting this at right angles, and let the point
|
||
|
H on it be the north and its diametrical opposite O the south. Let Z
|
||
|
be the rising of the sun at the summer solstice and E its setting at
|
||
|
the summer solstice; D its rising at the winter solstice, and G its
|
||
|
setting at the winter solstice. Draw a diameter from Z to G from D
|
||
|
to E. Then since those things are locally contrary which are most
|
||
|
distant from one another in space, and points diametrically opposite
|
||
|
are most distant from one another, those winds must necessarily be
|
||
|
contrary to one another that blow from opposite ends of a diameter.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The names of the winds according to their position are these.
|
||
|
Zephyrus is the wind that blows from A, this being the point where the
|
||
|
sun sets at the equinox. Its contrary is Apeliotes blowing from B
|
||
|
the point where the sun rises at the equinox. The wind blowing from H,
|
||
|
the north, is the true north wind, called Aparctias: while Notus
|
||
|
blowing from O is its contrary; for this point is the south and O is
|
||
|
contrary to H, being diametrically opposite to it. Caecias blows
|
||
|
from Z, where the sun rises at the summer solstice. Its contrary is
|
||
|
not the wind blowing from E but Lips blowing from G. For Lips blows
|
||
|
from the point where the sun sets at the winter solstice and is
|
||
|
diametrically opposite to Caecias: so it is its contrary. Eurus
|
||
|
blows from D, coming from the point where the sun rises at the
|
||
|
winter solstice. It borders on Notus, and so we often find that people
|
||
|
speak of 'Euro-Noti'. Its contrary is not Lips blowing from G but
|
||
|
the wind that blows from E which some call Argestes, some Olympias,
|
||
|
and some Sciron. This blows from the point where the sun sets at the
|
||
|
summer solstice, and is the only wind that is diametrically opposite
|
||
|
to Eurus. These are the winds that are diametrically opposite to one
|
||
|
another and their contraries.
|
||
|
|
||
|
There are other winds which have no contraries. The wind they call
|
||
|
Thrascias, which lies between Argestes and Aparctias, blows from I;
|
||
|
and the wind called Meses, which lies between Caecias and Aparctias,
|
||
|
from K. (The line IK nearly coincides with the ever visible circle,
|
||
|
but not quite.) These winds have no contraries. Meses has not, or else
|
||
|
there would be a wind blowing from the point M which is
|
||
|
diametrically opposite. Thrascias corresponding to the point I has
|
||
|
not, for then there would be a wind blowing from N, the point which is
|
||
|
diametrically opposite. (But perhaps a local wind which the
|
||
|
inhabitants of those parts call Phoenicias blows from that point.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
These are the most important and definite winds and these their
|
||
|
places.
|
||
|
|
||
|
There are more winds from the north than from the south. The
|
||
|
reason for this is that the region in which we live lies nearer to the
|
||
|
north. Also, much more water and snow is pushed aside into this
|
||
|
quarter because the other lies under the sun and its course. When this
|
||
|
thaws and soaks into the earth and is exposed to the heat of the sun
|
||
|
and the earth it necessarily causes evaporation to rise in greater
|
||
|
quantities and over a greater space.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of the winds we have described Aparctias is the north wind in the
|
||
|
strict sense. Thrascias and Meses are north winds too. (Caecias is
|
||
|
half north and half east.) South are that which blows from due south
|
||
|
and Lips. East, the wind from the rising of the sun at the equinox and
|
||
|
Eurus. Phoenicias is half south and half east. West, the wind from the
|
||
|
true west and that called Argestes. More generally these winds are
|
||
|
classified as northerly or southerly. The west winds are counted as
|
||
|
northerly, for they blow from the place of sunset and are therefore
|
||
|
colder; the east winds as southerly, for they are warmer because
|
||
|
they blow from the place of sunrise. So the distinction of cold and
|
||
|
hot or warm is the basis for the division of the winds into
|
||
|
northerly and southerly. East winds are warmer than west winds because
|
||
|
the sun shines on the east longer, whereas it leaves the west sooner
|
||
|
and reaches it later.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since this is the distribution of the winds it is clear that
|
||
|
contrary winds cannot blow simultaneously. They are diametrically
|
||
|
opposite to one another and one of the two must be overpowered and
|
||
|
cease. Winds that are not diametrically opposite to one another may
|
||
|
blow simultaneously: for instance the winds from Z and from D. Hence
|
||
|
it sometimes happens that both of them, though different winds and
|
||
|
blowing from different quarters, are favourable to sailors making
|
||
|
for the same point.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Contrary winds commonly blow at opposite seasons. Thus Caecias and
|
||
|
in general the winds north of the summer solstice blow about the
|
||
|
time of the spring equinox, but about the autumn equinox Lips; and
|
||
|
Zephyrus about the summer solstice, but about the winter solstice
|
||
|
Eurus.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Aparctias, Thrascias, and Argestes are the winds that fall on others
|
||
|
most and stop them. Their source is so close to us that they are
|
||
|
greater and stronger than other winds. They bring fair weather most of
|
||
|
all winds for the same reason, for, blowing as they do, from close
|
||
|
at hand, they overpower the other winds and stop them; they also
|
||
|
blow away the clouds that are forming and leave a clear sky-unless
|
||
|
they happen to be very cold. Then they do not bring fair weather,
|
||
|
but being colder than they are strong they condense the clouds
|
||
|
before driving them away.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Caecias does not bring fair weather because it returns upon
|
||
|
itself. Hence the saying: 'Bringing it on himself as Caecias does
|
||
|
clouds.'
|
||
|
|
||
|
When they cease, winds are succeeded by their neighbours in the
|
||
|
direction of the movement of the sun. For an effect is most apt to
|
||
|
be produced in the neighbourhood of its cause, and the cause of
|
||
|
winds moves with the sun.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Contrary winds have either the same or contrary effects. Thus Lips
|
||
|
and Caecias, sometimes called Hellespontias, are both rainy gestes and
|
||
|
Eurus are dry: the latter being dry at first and rainy afterwards.
|
||
|
Meses and Aparctias are coldest and bring most snow. Aparctias,
|
||
|
Thrascias, and Argestes bring hail. Notus, Zephyrus, and Eurus are
|
||
|
hot. Caecias covers the sky with heavy clouds, Lips with lighter ones.
|
||
|
Caecias does this because it returns upon itself and combines the
|
||
|
qualities of Boreas and Eurus. By being cold it condenses and
|
||
|
gathers the vaporous air, and because it is easterly it carries with
|
||
|
it and drives before it a great quantity of such matter. Aparctias,
|
||
|
Thrascias, and Argestes bring fair weather for the reason we have
|
||
|
explained before. These winds and Meses are most commonly
|
||
|
accompanied by lightning. They are cold because they blow from the
|
||
|
north, and lightning is due to cold, being ejected when the clouds
|
||
|
contract. Some of these same bring hail with them for the same reason;
|
||
|
namely, that they cause a sudden condensation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hurricanes are commonest in autumn, and next in spring: Aparctias,
|
||
|
Thrascias, and Argestes give rise to them most. This is because
|
||
|
hurricanes are generally formed when some winds are blowing and others
|
||
|
fall on them; and these are the winds which are most apt to fall on
|
||
|
others that are blowing; the reason for which, too, we have
|
||
|
explained before.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The Etesiae veer round: they begin from the north, and become for
|
||
|
dwellers in the west Thrasciae, Argestae, and Zephyrus (for Zephyrus
|
||
|
belongs to the north). For dwellers in the east they veer round as far
|
||
|
as Apeliotes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for the winds, their origin and nature and the properties
|
||
|
common to them all or peculiar to each.
|
||
|
|
||
|
7
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must go on to discuss earthquakes next, for their cause is akin
|
||
|
to our last subject.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The theories that have been put forward up to the present date are
|
||
|
three, and their authors three men, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, and
|
||
|
before him Anaximenes of Miletus, and later Democritus of Abdera.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Anaxagoras says that the ether, which naturally moves upwards, is
|
||
|
caught in hollows below the earth and so shakes it, for though the
|
||
|
earth is really all of it equally porous, its surface is clogged up by
|
||
|
rain. This implies that part of the whole sphere is 'above' and part
|
||
|
'below': 'above' being the part on which we live, 'below' the other.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This theory is perhaps too primitive to require refutation. It is
|
||
|
absurd to think of up and down otherwise than as meaning that heavy
|
||
|
bodies move to the earth from every quarter, and light ones, such as
|
||
|
fire, away from it; especially as we see that, as far as our knowledge
|
||
|
of the earth goes, the horizon always changes with a change in our
|
||
|
position, which proves that the earth is convex and spherical. It is
|
||
|
absurd, too, to maintain that the earth rests on the air because of
|
||
|
its size, and then to say that impact upwards from below shakes it
|
||
|
right through. Besides he gives no account of the circumstances
|
||
|
attendant on earthquakes: for not every country or every season is
|
||
|
subject to them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Democritus says that the earth is full of water and that when a
|
||
|
quantity of rain-water is added to this an earthquake is the result.
|
||
|
The hollows in the earth being unable to admit the excess of water
|
||
|
it forces its way in and so causes an earthquake. Or again, the
|
||
|
earth as it dries draws the water from the fuller to the emptier
|
||
|
parts, and the inrush of the water as it changes its place causes
|
||
|
the earthquake.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Anaximenes says that the earth breaks up when it grows wet or dry,
|
||
|
and earthquakes are due to the fall of these masses as they break
|
||
|
away. Hence earthquakes take place in times of drought and again of
|
||
|
heavy rain, since, as we have explained, the earth grows dry in time
|
||
|
of drought and breaks up, whereas the rain makes it sodden and
|
||
|
destroys its cohesion.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But if this were the case the earth ought to be found to be
|
||
|
sinking in many places. Again, why do earthquakes frequently occur
|
||
|
in places which are not excessively subject to drought or rain, as
|
||
|
they ought to be on the theory? Besides, on this view, earthquakes
|
||
|
ought always to be getting fewer, and should come to an end entirely
|
||
|
some day: the notion of contraction by packing together implies
|
||
|
this. So this is impossible the theory must be impossible too.
|
||
|
|
||
|
8
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have already shown that wet and dry must both give rise to an
|
||
|
evaporation: earthquakes are a necessary consequence of this fact. The
|
||
|
earth is essentially dry, but rain fills it with moisture. Then the
|
||
|
sun and its own fire warm it and give rise to a quantity of wind
|
||
|
both outside and inside it. This wind sometimes flows outwards in a
|
||
|
single body, sometimes inwards, and sometimes it is divided. All these
|
||
|
are necessary laws. Next we must find out what body has the greatest
|
||
|
motive force. This will certainly be the body that naturally moves
|
||
|
farthest and is most violent. Now that which has the most rapid motion
|
||
|
is necessarily the most violent; for its swiftness gives its impact
|
||
|
the greatest force. Again, the rarest body, that which can most
|
||
|
readily pass through every other body, is that which naturally moves
|
||
|
farthest. Wind satisfies these conditions in the highest degree
|
||
|
(fire only becomes flame and moves rapidly when wind accompanies
|
||
|
it): so that not water nor earth is the cause of earthquakes but
|
||
|
wind-that is, the inrush of the external evaporation into the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hence, since the evaporation generally follows in a continuous
|
||
|
body in the direction in which it first started, and either all of
|
||
|
it flows inwards or all outwards, most earthquakes and the greatest
|
||
|
are accompanied by calm. It is true that some take place when a wind
|
||
|
is blowing, but this presents no difficulty. We sometimes find several
|
||
|
winds blowing simultaneously. If one of these enters the earth we
|
||
|
get an earthquake attended by wind. Only these earthquakes are less
|
||
|
severe because their source and cause is divided.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, most earthquakes and the severest occur at night or, if by
|
||
|
day, about noon, that being generally the calmest part of the day. For
|
||
|
when the sun exerts its full power (as it does about noon) it shuts
|
||
|
the evaporation into the earth. Night, too, is calmer than day. The
|
||
|
absence of the sun makes the evaporation return into the earth like
|
||
|
a sort of ebb tide, corresponding to the outward flow; especially
|
||
|
towards dawn, for the winds, as a rule, begin to blow then, and if
|
||
|
their source changes about like the Euripus and flows inwards the
|
||
|
quantity of wind in the earth is greater and a more violent earthquake
|
||
|
results.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The severest earthquakes take place where the sea is full of
|
||
|
currents or the earth spongy and cavernous: so they occur near the
|
||
|
Hellespont and in Achaea and Sicily, and those parts of Euboea which
|
||
|
correspond to our description-where the sea is supposed to flow in
|
||
|
channels below the earth. The hot springs, too, near Aedepsus are
|
||
|
due to a cause of this kind. It is the confined character of these
|
||
|
places that makes them so liable to earthquakes. A great and therefore
|
||
|
violent wind is developed, which would naturally blow away from the
|
||
|
earth: but the onrush of the sea in a great mass thrusts it back
|
||
|
into the earth. The countries that are spongy below the surface are
|
||
|
exposed to earthquakes because they have room for so much wind.
|
||
|
|
||
|
For the same reason earthquakes usually take place in spring and
|
||
|
autumn and in times of wet and of drought-because these are the
|
||
|
windiest seasons. Summer with its heat and winter with its frost cause
|
||
|
calm: winter is too cold, summer too dry for winds to form. In time of
|
||
|
drought the air is full of wind; drought is just the predominance of
|
||
|
the dry over the moist evaporation. Again, excessive rain causes
|
||
|
more of the evaporation to form in the earth. Then this secretion is
|
||
|
shut up in a narrow compass and forced into a smaller space by the
|
||
|
water that fills the cavities. Thus a great wind is compressed into
|
||
|
a smaller space and so gets the upper hand, and then breaks out and
|
||
|
beats against the earth and shakes it violently.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must suppose the action of the wind in the earth to be
|
||
|
analogous to the tremors and throbbings caused in us by the force of
|
||
|
the wind contained in our bodies. Thus some earthquakes are a sort
|
||
|
of tremor, others a sort of throbbing. Again, we must think of an
|
||
|
earthquake as something like the tremor that often runs through the
|
||
|
body after passing water as the wind returns inwards from without in
|
||
|
one volume.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The force wind can have may be gathered not only from what happens
|
||
|
in the air (where one might suppose that it owed its power to
|
||
|
produce such effects to its volume), but also from what is observed in
|
||
|
animal bodies. Tetanus and spasms are motions of wind, and their force
|
||
|
is such that the united efforts of many men do not succeed in
|
||
|
overcoming the movements of the patients. We must suppose, then (to
|
||
|
compare great things with small), that what happens in the earth is
|
||
|
just like that. Our theory has been verified by actual observation
|
||
|
in many places. It has been known to happen that an earthquake has
|
||
|
continued until the wind that caused it burst through the earth into
|
||
|
the air and appeared visibly like a hurricane. This happened lately
|
||
|
near Heracleia in Pontus and some time past at the island Hiera, one
|
||
|
of the group called the Aeolian islands. Here a portion of the earth
|
||
|
swelled up and a lump like a mound rose with a noise: finally it
|
||
|
burst, and a great wind came out of it and threw up live cinders and
|
||
|
ashes which buried the neighbouring town of Lipara and reached some of
|
||
|
the towns in Italy. The spot where this eruption occurred is still
|
||
|
to be seen.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Indeed, this must be recognized as the cause of the fire that is
|
||
|
generated in the earth: the air is first broken up in small
|
||
|
particles and then the wind is beaten about and so catches fire.
|
||
|
|
||
|
A phenomenon in these islands affords further evidence of the fact
|
||
|
that winds move below the surface of the earth. When a south wind is
|
||
|
going to blow there is a premonitory indication: a sound is heard in
|
||
|
the places from which the eruptions issue. This is because the sea
|
||
|
is being pushed on from a distance and its advance thrusts back into
|
||
|
the earth the wind that was issuing from it. The reason why there is a
|
||
|
noise and no earthquake is that the underground spaces are so
|
||
|
extensive in proportion to the quantity of the air that is being
|
||
|
driven on that the wind slips away into the void beyond.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Again, our theory is supported by the facts that the sun appears
|
||
|
hazy and is darkened in the absence of clouds, and that there is
|
||
|
sometimes calm and sharp frost before earthquakes at sunrise. The
|
||
|
sun is necessarily obscured and darkened when the evaporation which
|
||
|
dissolves and rarefies the air begins to withdraw into the earth.
|
||
|
The calm, too, and the cold towards sunrise and dawn follow from the
|
||
|
theory. The calm we have already explained. There must as a rule be
|
||
|
calm because the wind flows back into the earth: again, it must be
|
||
|
most marked before the more violent earthquakes, for when the wind
|
||
|
is not part outside earth, part inside, but moves in a single body,
|
||
|
its strength must be greater. The cold comes because the evaporation
|
||
|
which is naturally and essentially hot enters the earth. (Wind is
|
||
|
not recognized to be hot, because it sets the air in motion, and
|
||
|
that is full of a quantity of cold vapour. It is the same with the
|
||
|
breath we blow from our mouth: close by it is warm, as it is when we
|
||
|
breathe out through the mouth, but there is so little of it that it is
|
||
|
scarcely noticed, whereas at a distance it is cold for the same reason
|
||
|
as wind.) Well, when this evaporation disappears into the earth the
|
||
|
vaporous exhalation concentrates and causes cold in any place in which
|
||
|
this disappearance occurs.
|
||
|
|
||
|
A sign which sometimes precedes earthquakes can be explained in
|
||
|
the same way. Either by day or a little after sunset, in fine weather,
|
||
|
a little, light, long-drawn cloud is seen, like a long very straight
|
||
|
line. This is because the wind is leaving the air and dying down.
|
||
|
Something analogous to this happens on the sea-shore. When the sea
|
||
|
breaks in great waves the marks left on the sand are very thick and
|
||
|
crooked, but when the sea is calm they are slight and straight
|
||
|
(because the secretion is small). As the sea is to the shore so the
|
||
|
wind is to the cloudy air; so, when the wind drops, this very straight
|
||
|
and thin cloud is left, a sort of wave-mark in the air.
|
||
|
|
||
|
An earthquake sometimes coincides with an eclipse of the moon for
|
||
|
the same reason. When the earth is on the point of being interposed,
|
||
|
but the light and heat of the sun has not quite vanished from the
|
||
|
air but is dying away, the wind which causes the earthquake before the
|
||
|
eclipse, turns off into the earth, and calm ensues. For there often
|
||
|
are winds before eclipses: at nightfall if the eclipse is at midnight,
|
||
|
and at midnight if the eclipse is at dawn. They are caused by the
|
||
|
lessening of the warmth from the moon when its sphere approaches the
|
||
|
point at which the eclipse is going to take place. So the influence
|
||
|
which restrained and quieted the air weakens and the air moves again
|
||
|
and a wind rises, and does so later, the later the eclipse.
|
||
|
|
||
|
A severe earthquake does not stop at once or after a single shock,
|
||
|
but first the shocks go on, often for about forty days; after that,
|
||
|
for one or even two years it gives premonitory indications in the same
|
||
|
place. The severity of the earthquake is determined by the quantity of
|
||
|
wind and the shape of the passages through which it flows. Where it is
|
||
|
beaten back and cannot easily find its way out the shocks are most
|
||
|
violent, and there it must remain in a cramped space like water that
|
||
|
cannot escape. Any throbbing in the body does not cease suddenly or
|
||
|
quickly, but by degrees according as the affection passes off. So here
|
||
|
the agency which created the evaporation and gave it an impulse to
|
||
|
motion clearly does not at once exhaust the whole of the material from
|
||
|
which it forms the wind which we call an earthquake. So until the rest
|
||
|
of this is exhausted the shocks must continue, though more gently, and
|
||
|
they must go on until there is too little of the evaporation left to
|
||
|
have any perceptible effect on the earth at all.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Subterranean noises, too, are due to the wind; sometimes they
|
||
|
portend earthquakes but sometimes they have been heard without any
|
||
|
earthquake following. Just as the air gives off various sounds when it
|
||
|
is struck, so it does when it strikes other things; for striking
|
||
|
involves being struck and so the two cases are the same. The sound
|
||
|
precedes the shock because sound is thinner and passes through
|
||
|
things more readily than wind. But when the wind is too weak by reason
|
||
|
of thinness to cause an earthquake the absence of a shock is due to
|
||
|
its filtering through readily, though by striking hard and hollow
|
||
|
masses of different shapes it makes various noises, so that the
|
||
|
earth sometimes seems to 'bellow' as the portentmongers say.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Water has been known to burst out during an earthquake. But that
|
||
|
does not make water the cause of the earthquake. The wind is the
|
||
|
efficient cause whether it drives the water along the surface or up
|
||
|
from below: just as winds are the causes of waves and not waves of
|
||
|
winds. Else we might as well say that earth was the cause; for it is
|
||
|
upset in an earthquake, just like water (for effusion is a form of
|
||
|
upsetting). No, earth and water are material causes (being patients,
|
||
|
not agents): the true cause is the wind.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The combination of a tidal wave with an earthquake is due to the
|
||
|
presence of contrary winds. It occurs when the wind which is shaking
|
||
|
the earth does not entirely succeed in driving off the sea which
|
||
|
another wind is bringing on, but pushes it back and heaps it up in a
|
||
|
great mass in one place. Given this situation it follows that when
|
||
|
this wind gives way the whole body of the sea, driven on by the
|
||
|
other wind, will burst out and overwhelm the land. This is what
|
||
|
happened in Achaea. There a south wind was blowing, but outside a
|
||
|
north wind; then there was a calm and the wind entered the earth,
|
||
|
and then the tidal wave came on and simultaneously there was an
|
||
|
earthquake. This was the more violent as the sea allowed no exit to
|
||
|
the wind that had entered the earth, but shut it in. So in their
|
||
|
struggle with one another the wind caused the earthquake, and the wave
|
||
|
by its settling down the inundation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Earthquakes are local and often affect a small district only;
|
||
|
whereas winds are not local. Such phenomena are local when the
|
||
|
evaporations at a given place are joined by those from the next and
|
||
|
unite; this, as we explained, is what happens when there is drought or
|
||
|
excessive rain locally. Now earthquakes do come about in this way
|
||
|
but winds do not. For earthquakes, rains, and droughts have their
|
||
|
source and origin inside the earth, so that the sun is not equally
|
||
|
able to direct all the evaporations in one direction. But on the
|
||
|
evaporations in the air the sun has more influence so that, when
|
||
|
once they have been given an impulse by its motion, which is
|
||
|
determined by its various positions, they flow in one direction.
|
||
|
|
||
|
When the wind is present in sufficient quantity there is an
|
||
|
earthquake. The shocks are horizontal like a tremor; except
|
||
|
occasionally, in a few places, where they act vertically, upwards from
|
||
|
below, like a throbbing. It is the vertical direction which makes this
|
||
|
kind of earthquake so rare. The motive force does not easily
|
||
|
accumulate in great quantity in the position required, since the
|
||
|
surface of the earth secretes far more of the evaporation than its
|
||
|
depths. Wherever an earthquake of this kind does occur a quantity of
|
||
|
stones comes to the surface of the earth (as when you throw up
|
||
|
things in a winnowing fan), as we see from Sipylus and the
|
||
|
Phlegraean plain and the district in Liguria, which were devastated by
|
||
|
this kind of earthquake.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Islands in the middle of the sea are less exposed to earthquakes
|
||
|
than those near land. First, the volume of the sea cools the
|
||
|
evaporations and overpowers them by its weight and so crushes them.
|
||
|
Then, currents and not shocks are produced in the sea by the action of
|
||
|
the winds. Again, it is so extensive that evaporations do not
|
||
|
collect in it but issue from it, and these draw the evaporations
|
||
|
from the earth after them. Islands near the continent really form part
|
||
|
of it: the intervening sea is not enough to make any difference; but
|
||
|
those in the open sea can only be shaken if the whole of the sea
|
||
|
that surrounds them is shaken too.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now explained earthquakes, their nature and cause, and the
|
||
|
most important of the circumstances attendant on their appearance.
|
||
|
|
||
|
9
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us go on to explain lightning and thunder, and further
|
||
|
whirlwind, fire-wind, and thunderbolts: for the cause of them all is
|
||
|
the same.
|
||
|
|
||
|
As we have said, there are two kinds of exhalation, moist and dry,
|
||
|
and the atmosphere contains them both potentially. It, as we have said
|
||
|
before, condenses into cloud, and the density of the clouds is highest
|
||
|
at their upper limit. (For they must be denser and colder on the
|
||
|
side where the heat escapes to the upper region and leaves them.
|
||
|
This explains why hurricanes and thunderbolts and all analogous
|
||
|
phenomena move downwards in spite of the fact that everything hot
|
||
|
has a natural tendency upwards. Just as the pips that we squeeze
|
||
|
between our fingers are heavy but often jump upwards: so these
|
||
|
things are necessarily squeezed out away from the densest part of
|
||
|
the cloud.) Now the heat that escapes disperses to the up region.
|
||
|
But if any of the dry exhalation is caught in the process as the air
|
||
|
cools, it is squeezed out as the clouds contract, and collides in
|
||
|
its rapid course with the neighbouring clouds, and the sound of this
|
||
|
collision is what we call thunder. This collision is analogous, to
|
||
|
compare small with great, to the sound we hear in a flame which men
|
||
|
call the laughter or the threat of Hephaestus or of Hestia. This
|
||
|
occurs when the wood dries and cracks and the exhalation rushes on the
|
||
|
flame in a body. So in the clouds, the exhalation is projected and its
|
||
|
impact on dense clouds causes thunder: the variety of the sound is due
|
||
|
to the irregularity of the clouds and the hollows that intervene where
|
||
|
their density is interrupted. This then, is thunder, and this its
|
||
|
cause.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It usually happens that the exhalation that is ejected is inflamed
|
||
|
and burns with a thin and faint fire: this is what we call
|
||
|
lightning, where we see as it were the exhalation coloured in the
|
||
|
act of its ejection. It comes into existence after the collision and
|
||
|
the thunder, though we see it earlier because sight is quicker than
|
||
|
hearing. The rowing of triremes illustrates this: the oars are going
|
||
|
back again before the sound of their striking the water reaches us.
|
||
|
|
||
|
However, there are some who maintain that there is actually fire
|
||
|
in the clouds. Empedocles says that it consists of some of the sun's
|
||
|
rays which are intercepted: Anaxagoras that it is part of the upper
|
||
|
ether (which he calls fire) which has descended from above. Lightning,
|
||
|
then, is the gleam of this fire, and thunder the hissing noise of
|
||
|
its extinction in the cloud.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But this involves the view that lightning actually is prior to
|
||
|
thunder and does not merely appear to be so. Again, this
|
||
|
intercepting of the fire is impossible on either theory, but
|
||
|
especially it is said to be drawn down from the upper ether. Some
|
||
|
reason ought to be given why that which naturally ascends should
|
||
|
descend, and why it should not always do so, but only when it is
|
||
|
cloudy. When the sky is clear there is no lightning: to say that there
|
||
|
is, is altogether wanton.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The view that the heat of the sun's rays intercepted in the clouds
|
||
|
is the cause of these phenomena is equally unattractive: this, too, is
|
||
|
a most careless explanation. Thunder, lightning, and the rest must
|
||
|
have a separate and determinate cause assigned to them on which they
|
||
|
ensue. But this theory does nothing of the sort. It is like
|
||
|
supposing that water, snow, and hail existed all along and were
|
||
|
produced when the time came and not generated at all, as if the
|
||
|
atmosphere brought each to hand out of its stock from time to time.
|
||
|
They are concretions in the same way as thunder and lightning are
|
||
|
discretions, so that if it is true of either that they are not
|
||
|
generated but pre-exist, the same must be true of the other. Again,
|
||
|
how can any distinction be made about the intercepting between this
|
||
|
case and that of interception in denser substances such as water?
|
||
|
Water, too, is heated by the sun and by fire: yet when it contracts
|
||
|
again and grows cold and freezes no such ejection as they describe
|
||
|
occurs, though it ought on their the. to take place on a proportionate
|
||
|
scale. Boiling is due to the exhalation generated by fire: but it is
|
||
|
impossible for it to exist in the water beforehand; and besides they
|
||
|
call the noise 'hissing', not 'boiling'. But hissing is really boiling
|
||
|
on a small scale: for when that which is brought into contact with
|
||
|
moisture and is in process of being extinguished gets the better of
|
||
|
it, then it boils and makes the noise in question. Some-Cleidemus is
|
||
|
one of them-say that lightning is nothing objective but merely an
|
||
|
appearance. They compare it to what happens when you strike the sea
|
||
|
with a rod by night and the water is seen to shine. They say that
|
||
|
the moisture in the cloud is beaten about in the same way, and that
|
||
|
lightning is the appearance of brightness that ensues.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This theory is due to ignorance of the theory of reflection, which
|
||
|
is the real cause of that phenomenon. The water appears to shine
|
||
|
when struck because our sight is reflected from it to some bright
|
||
|
object: hence the phenomenon occurs mainly by night: the appearance is
|
||
|
not seen by day because the daylight is too in, tense and obscures it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These are the theories of others about thunder and lightning: some
|
||
|
maintaining that lightning is a reflection, the others that
|
||
|
lightning is fire shining through the cloud and thunder its
|
||
|
extinction, the fire not being generated in each case but existing
|
||
|
beforehand. We say that the same stuff is wind on the earth, and
|
||
|
earthquake under it, and in the clouds thunder. The essential
|
||
|
constituent of all these phenomena is the same: namely, the dry
|
||
|
exhalation. If it flows in one direction it is wind, in another it
|
||
|
causes earthquakes; in the clouds, when they are in a process of
|
||
|
change and contract and condense into water, it is ejected and
|
||
|
causes thunder and lightning and the other phenomena of the same
|
||
|
nature.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for thunder and lightning.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Book III
|
||
|
|
||
|
1
|
||
|
|
||
|
LET us explain the remaining operations of this secretion in the
|
||
|
same way as we have treated the rest. When this exhalation is secreted
|
||
|
in small and scattered quantities and frequently, and is transitory,
|
||
|
and its constitution rare, it gives rise to thunder and lightning. But
|
||
|
if it is secreted in a body and is denser, that is, less rare, we
|
||
|
get a hurricane. The fact that it issues in body explains its
|
||
|
violence: it is due to the rapidity of the secretion. Now when this
|
||
|
secretion issues in a great and continuous current the result
|
||
|
corresponds to what we get when the opposite development takes place
|
||
|
and rain and a quantity of water are produced. As far as the matter
|
||
|
from which they are developed goes both sets of phenomena are the
|
||
|
same. As soon as a stimulus to the development of either
|
||
|
potentiality appears, that of which there is the greater quantity
|
||
|
present in the cloud is at once secreted from it, and there results
|
||
|
either rain, or, if the other exhalation prevails, a hurricane.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Sometimes the exhalation in the cloud, when it is being secreted,
|
||
|
collides with another under circumstances like those found when a wind
|
||
|
is forced from an open into a narrow space in a gateway or a road.
|
||
|
It often happens in such cases that the first part of the moving
|
||
|
body is deflected because of the resistance due either to the
|
||
|
narrowness or to a contrary current, and so the wind forms a circle
|
||
|
and eddy. It is prevented from advancing in a straight line: at the
|
||
|
same time it is pushed on from behind; so it is compelled to move
|
||
|
sideways in the direction of least resistance. The same thing
|
||
|
happens to the next part, and the next, and so on, till the series
|
||
|
becomes one, that is, till a circle is formed: for if a figure is
|
||
|
described by a single motion that figure must itself be one. This is
|
||
|
how eddies are generated on the earth, and the case is the same in the
|
||
|
clouds as far as the beginning of them goes. Only here (as in the case
|
||
|
of the hurricane which shakes off the cloud without cessation and
|
||
|
becomes a continuous wind) the cloud follows the exhalation
|
||
|
unbroken, and the exhalation, failing to break away from the cloud
|
||
|
because of its density, first moves in a circle for the reason given
|
||
|
and then descends, because clouds are always densest on the side where
|
||
|
the heat escapes. This phenomenon is called a whirlwind when it is
|
||
|
colourless; and it is a sort of undigested hurricane. There is never a
|
||
|
whirlwind when the weather is northerly, nor a hurricane when there is
|
||
|
snow. The reason is that all these phenomena are 'wind', and wind is a
|
||
|
dry and warm evaporation. Now frost and cold prevail over this
|
||
|
principle and quench it at its birth: that they do prevail is clear or
|
||
|
there could be no snow or northerly rain, since these occur when the
|
||
|
cold does prevail.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So the whirlwind originates in the failure of an incipient hurricane
|
||
|
to escape from its cloud: it is due to the resistance which
|
||
|
generates the eddy, and it consists in the spiral which descends to
|
||
|
the earth and drags with it the cloud which it cannot shake off. It
|
||
|
moves things by its wind in the direction in which it is blowing in
|
||
|
a straight line, and whirls round by its circular motion and
|
||
|
forcibly snatches up whatever it meets.
|
||
|
|
||
|
When the cloud burns as it is drawn downwards, that is, when the
|
||
|
exhalation becomes rarer, it is called a fire-wind, for its fire
|
||
|
colours the neighbouring air and inflames it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
When there is a great quantity of exhalation and it is rare and is
|
||
|
squeezed out in the cloud itself we get a thunderbolt. If the
|
||
|
exhalation is exceedingly rare this rareness prevents the
|
||
|
thunderbolt from scorching and the poets call it 'bright': if the
|
||
|
rareness is less it does scorch and they call it 'smoky'. The former
|
||
|
moves rapidly because of its rareness, and because of its rapidity
|
||
|
passes through an object before setting fire to it or dwelling on it
|
||
|
so as to blacken it: the slower one does blacken the object, but
|
||
|
passes through it before it can actually burn it. Further, resisting
|
||
|
substances are affected, unresisting ones are not. For instance, it
|
||
|
has happened that the bronze of a shield has been melted while the
|
||
|
woodwork remained intact because its texture was so loose that the
|
||
|
exhalation filtered through without affecting it. So it has passed
|
||
|
through clothes, too, without burning them, and has merely reduced
|
||
|
them to shreds.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Such evidence is enough by itself to show that the exhalation is
|
||
|
at work in all these cases, but we sometimes get direct evidence as
|
||
|
well, as in the case of the conflagration of the temple at Ephesus
|
||
|
which we lately witnessed. There independent sheets of flame left
|
||
|
the main fire and were carried bodily in many directions. Now that
|
||
|
smoke is exhalation and that smoke burns is certain, and has been
|
||
|
stated in another place before; but when the flame moves bodily,
|
||
|
then we have ocular proof that smoke is exhalation. On this occasion
|
||
|
what is seen in small fires appeared on a much larger scale because of
|
||
|
the quantity of matter that was burning. The beams which were the
|
||
|
source of the exhalation split, and a quantity of it rushed in a
|
||
|
body from the place from which it issued forth and went up in a blaze:
|
||
|
so that the flame was actually seen moving through the air away and
|
||
|
falling on the houses. For we must recognize that exhalation
|
||
|
accompanies and precedes thunderbolts though it is colourless and so
|
||
|
invisible. Hence, where the thunderbolt is going to strike, the object
|
||
|
moves before it is struck, showing that the exhalation leads the way
|
||
|
and falls on the object first. Thunder, too, splits things not by
|
||
|
its noise but because the exhalation that strikes the object and
|
||
|
that which makes the noise are ejected simultaneously. This exhalation
|
||
|
splits the thing it strikes but does not scorch it at all.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now explained thunder and lightning and hurricane, and
|
||
|
further firewinds, whirlwinds, and thunderbolts, and shown that they
|
||
|
are all of them forms of the same thing and wherein they all differ.
|
||
|
|
||
|
2
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us now explain the nature and cause of halo, rainbow, mock suns,
|
||
|
and rods, since the same account applies to them all.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must first describe the phenomena and the circumstances in
|
||
|
which each of them occurs. The halo often appears as a complete
|
||
|
circle: it is seen round the sun and the moon and bright stars, by
|
||
|
night as well as by day, and at midday or in the afternoon, more
|
||
|
rarely about sunrise or sunset.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The rainbow never forms a full circle, nor any segment greater
|
||
|
than a semicircle. At sunset and sunrise the circle is smallest and
|
||
|
the segment largest: as the sun rises higher the circle is larger
|
||
|
and the segment smaller. After the autumn equinox in the shorter
|
||
|
days it is seen at every hour of the day, in the summer not about
|
||
|
midday. There are never more than two rainbows at one time. Each of
|
||
|
them is three-coloured; the colours are the same in both and their
|
||
|
number is the same, but in the outer rainbow they are fainter and
|
||
|
their position is reversed. In the inner rainbow the first and largest
|
||
|
band is red; in the outer rainbow the band that is nearest to this one
|
||
|
and smallest is of the same colour: the other bands correspond on
|
||
|
the same principle. These are almost the only colours which painters
|
||
|
cannot manufacture: for there are colours which they create by mixing,
|
||
|
but no mixing will give red, green, or purple. These are the colours
|
||
|
of the rainbow, though between the red and the green an orange
|
||
|
colour is often seen.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Mock suns and rods are always seen by the side of the sun, not above
|
||
|
or below it nor in the opposite quarter of the sky. They are not
|
||
|
seen at night but always in the neighbourhood of the sun, either as it
|
||
|
is rising or setting but more commonly towards sunset. They have
|
||
|
scarcely ever appeared when the sun was on the meridian, though this
|
||
|
once happened in Bosporus where two mock suns rose with the sun and
|
||
|
followed it all through the day till sunset.
|
||
|
|
||
|
These are the facts about each of these phenomena: the cause of them
|
||
|
all is the same, for they are all reflections. But they are
|
||
|
different varieties, and are distinguished by the surface from which
|
||
|
and the way in which the reflection to the sun or some other bright
|
||
|
object takes place.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The rainbow is seen by day, and it was formerly thought that it
|
||
|
never appeared by night as a moon rainbow. This opinion was due to the
|
||
|
rarity of the occurrence: it was not observed, for though it does
|
||
|
happen it does so rarely. The reason is that the colours are not so
|
||
|
easy to see in the dark and that many other conditions must
|
||
|
coincide, and all that in a single day in the month. For if there is
|
||
|
to be one it must be at full moon, and then as the moon is either
|
||
|
rising or setting. So we have only met with two instances of a moon
|
||
|
rainbow in more than fifty years.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must accept from the theory of optics the fact that sight is
|
||
|
reflected from air and any object with a smooth surface just as it
|
||
|
is from water; also that in some mirrors the forms of things are
|
||
|
reflected, in others only their colours. Of the latter kind are
|
||
|
those mirrors which are so small as to be indivisible for sense. It is
|
||
|
impossible that the figure of a thing should be reflected in them, for
|
||
|
if it is the mirror will be sensibly divisible since divisibility is
|
||
|
involved in the notion of figure. But since something must be
|
||
|
reflected in them and figure cannot be, it remains that colour alone
|
||
|
should be reflected. The colour of a bright object sometimes appears
|
||
|
bright in the reflection, but it sometimes, either owing to the
|
||
|
admixture of the colour of the mirror or to weakness of sight, gives
|
||
|
rise to the appearance of another colour.
|
||
|
|
||
|
However, we must accept the account we have given of these things in
|
||
|
the theory of sensation, and take some things for granted while we
|
||
|
explain others.
|
||
|
|
||
|
3
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let us begin by explaining the shape of the halo; why it is a circle
|
||
|
and why it appears round the sun or the moon or one of the other
|
||
|
stars: the explanation being in all these cases the same.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Sight is reflected in this way when air and vapour are condensed
|
||
|
into a cloud and the condensed matter is uniform and consists of small
|
||
|
parts. Hence in itself it is a sign of rain, but if it fades away,
|
||
|
of fine weather, if it is broken up, of wind. For if it does not
|
||
|
fade away and is not broken up but is allowed to attain its normal
|
||
|
state, it is naturally a sign of rain since it shows that a process of
|
||
|
condensation is proceeding which must, when it is carried to an end,
|
||
|
result in rain. For the same reason these haloes are the darkest. It
|
||
|
is a sign of wind when it is broken up because its breaking up is
|
||
|
due to a wind which exists there but has not reached us. This view
|
||
|
finds support in the fact that the wind blows from the quarter in
|
||
|
which the main division appears in the halo. Its fading away is a sign
|
||
|
of fine weather because if the air is not yet in a state to get the
|
||
|
better of the heat it contains and proceed to condense into water,
|
||
|
this shows that the moist vapour has not yet separated from the dry
|
||
|
and firelike exhalation: and this is the cause of fine weather.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for the atmospheric conditions under which the reflection
|
||
|
takes place. The reflection is from the mist that forms round the
|
||
|
sun or the moon, and that is why the halo is not seen opposite the sun
|
||
|
like the rainbow.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since the reflection takes place in the same way from every point
|
||
|
the result is necessarily a circle or a segment of a circle: for if
|
||
|
the lines start from the same point and end at the same point and
|
||
|
are equal, the points where they form an angle will always lie on a
|
||
|
circle.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let AGB and AZB and ADB be lines each of which goes from the point A
|
||
|
to the point B and forms an angle. Let the lines AG, AZ, AD be equal
|
||
|
and those at B, GB, ZB, DB equal too. (See diagram.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Draw the line AEB. Then the triangles are equal; for their base
|
||
|
AEB is equal. Draw perpendiculars to AEB from the angles; GE from G,
|
||
|
ZE from Z, DE from D. Then these perpendiculars are equal, being in
|
||
|
equal triangles. And they are all in one plane, being all at right
|
||
|
angles to AEB and meeting at a single point E. So if you draw the line
|
||
|
it will be a circle and E its centre. Now B is the sun, A the eye, and
|
||
|
the circumference passing through the points GZD the cloud from
|
||
|
which the line of sight is reflected to the sun.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The mirrors must be thought of as contiguous: each of them is too
|
||
|
small to be visible, but their contiguity makes the whole made up of
|
||
|
them all to seem one. The bright band is the sun, which is seen as a
|
||
|
circle, appearing successively in each of the mirrors as a point
|
||
|
indivisible to sense. The band of cloud next to it is black, its
|
||
|
colour being intensified by contrast with the brightness of the
|
||
|
halo. The halo is formed rather near the earth because that is calmer:
|
||
|
for where there is wind it is clear that no halo can maintain its
|
||
|
position.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Haloes are commoner round the moon because the greater heat of the
|
||
|
sun dissolves the condensations of the air more rapidly.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Haloes are formed round stars for the same reasons, but they are not
|
||
|
prognostic in the same way because the condensation they imply is so
|
||
|
insignificant as to be barren.
|
||
|
|
||
|
4
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have already stated that the rainbow is a reflection: we have now
|
||
|
to explain what sort of reflection it is, to describe its various
|
||
|
concomitants, and to assign their causes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Sight is reflected from all smooth surfaces, such as are air and
|
||
|
water among others. Air must be condensed if it is to act as a mirror,
|
||
|
though it often gives a reflection even uncondensed when the sight
|
||
|
is weak. Such was the case of a man whose sight was faint and
|
||
|
indistinct. He always saw an image in front of him and facing him as
|
||
|
he walked. This was because his sight was reflected back to him. Its
|
||
|
morbid condition made it so weak and delicate that the air close by
|
||
|
acted as a mirror, just as distant and condensed air normally does,
|
||
|
and his sight could not push it back. So promontories in the sea
|
||
|
'loom' when there is a south-east wind, and everything seems bigger,
|
||
|
and in a mist, too, things seem bigger: so, too, the sun and the stars
|
||
|
seem bigger when rising and setting than on the meridian. But things
|
||
|
are best reflected from water, and even in process of formation it
|
||
|
is a better mirror than air, for each of the particles, the union of
|
||
|
which constitutes a raindrop, is necessarily a better mirror than
|
||
|
mist. Now it is obvious and has already been stated that a mirror of
|
||
|
this kind renders the colour of an object only, but not its shape.
|
||
|
Hence it follows that when it is on the point of raining and the air
|
||
|
in the clouds is in process of forming into raindrops but the rain
|
||
|
is not yet actually there, if the sun is opposite, or any other object
|
||
|
bright enough to make the cloud a mirror and cause the sight to be
|
||
|
reflected to the object then the reflection must render the colour
|
||
|
of the object without its shape. Since each of the mirrors is so small
|
||
|
as to be invisible and what we see is the continuous magnitude made up
|
||
|
of them all, the reflection necessarily gives us a continuous
|
||
|
magnitude made up of one colour; each of the mirrors contributing
|
||
|
the same colour to the whole. We may deduce that since these
|
||
|
conditions are realizable there will be an appearance due to
|
||
|
reflection whenever the sun and the cloud are related in the way
|
||
|
described and we are between them. But these are just the conditions
|
||
|
under which the rainbow appears. So it is clear that the rainbow is
|
||
|
a reflection of sight to the sun.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So the rainbow always appears opposite the sun whereas the halo is
|
||
|
round it. They are both reflections, but the rainbow is
|
||
|
distinguished by the variety of its colours. The reflection in the one
|
||
|
case is from water which is dark and from a distance; in the other
|
||
|
from air which is nearer and lighter in colour. White light through
|
||
|
a dark medium or on a dark surface (it makes no difference) looks red.
|
||
|
We know how red the flame of green wood is: this is because so much
|
||
|
smoke is mixed with the bright white firelight: so, too, the sun
|
||
|
appears red through smoke and mist. That is why in the rainbow
|
||
|
reflection the outer circumference is red (the reflection being from
|
||
|
small particles of water), but not in the case of the halo. The
|
||
|
other colours shall be explained later. Again, a condensation of
|
||
|
this kind cannot persist in the neighbourhood of the sun: it must
|
||
|
either turn to rain or be dissolved, but opposite to the sun there
|
||
|
is an interval during which the water is formed. If there were not
|
||
|
this distinction haloes would be coloured like the rainbow. Actually
|
||
|
no complete or circular halo presents this colour, only small and
|
||
|
fragmentary appearances called 'rods'. But if a haze due to water or
|
||
|
any other dark substance formed there we should have had, as we
|
||
|
maintain, a complete rainbow like that which we do find lamps. A
|
||
|
rainbow appears round these in winter, generally with southerly winds.
|
||
|
Persons whose eyes are moist see it most clearly because their sight
|
||
|
is weak and easily reflected. It is due to the moistness of the air
|
||
|
and the soot which the flame gives off and which mixes with the air
|
||
|
and makes it a mirror, and to the blackness which that mirror
|
||
|
derives from the smoky nature of the soot. The light of the lamp
|
||
|
appears as a circle which is not white but purple. It shows the
|
||
|
colours of the rainbow; but because the sight that is reflected is too
|
||
|
weak and the mirror too dark, red is absent. The rainbow that is
|
||
|
seen when oars are raised out of the sea involves the same relative
|
||
|
positions as that in the sky, but its colour is more like that round
|
||
|
the lamps, being purple rather than red. The reflection is from very
|
||
|
small particles continuous with one another, and in this case the
|
||
|
particles are fully formed water. We get a rainbow, too, if a man
|
||
|
sprinkles fine drops in a room turned to the sun so that the sun is
|
||
|
shining in part of the room and throwing a shadow in the rest. Then if
|
||
|
one man sprinkles in the room, another, standing outside, sees a
|
||
|
rainbow where the sun's rays cease and make the shadow. Its nature and
|
||
|
colour is like that from the oars and its cause is the same, for the
|
||
|
sprinkling hand corresponds to the oar.
|
||
|
|
||
|
That the colours of the rainbow are those we described and how the
|
||
|
other colours come to appear in it will be clear from the following
|
||
|
considerations. We must recognize, as we have said, and lay down:
|
||
|
first, that white colour on a black surface or seen through a black
|
||
|
medium gives red; second, that sight when strained to a distance
|
||
|
becomes weaker and less; third, that black is in a sort the negation
|
||
|
of sight: an object is black because sight fails; so everything at a
|
||
|
distance looks blacker, because sight does not reach it. The theory of
|
||
|
these matters belongs to the account of the senses, which are the
|
||
|
proper subjects of such an inquiry; we need only state about them what
|
||
|
is necessary for us. At all events, that is the reason why distant
|
||
|
objects and objects seen in a mirror look darker and smaller and
|
||
|
smoother, why the reflection of clouds in water is darker than the
|
||
|
clouds themselves. This latter is clearly the case: the reflection
|
||
|
diminishes the sight that reaches them. It makes no difference whether
|
||
|
the change is in the object seen or. in the sight, the result being in
|
||
|
either case the same. The following fact further is worth noticing.
|
||
|
When there is a cloud near the sun and we look at it does not look
|
||
|
coloured at all but white, but when we look at the same cloud in water
|
||
|
it shows a trace of rainbow colouring. Clearly, then, when sight is
|
||
|
reflected it is weakened and, as it makes dark look darker, so it
|
||
|
makes white look less white, changing it and bringing it nearer to
|
||
|
black. When the sight is relatively strong the change is to red; the
|
||
|
next stage is green, and a further degree of weakness gives violet. No
|
||
|
further change is visible, but three completes the series of colours
|
||
|
(as we find three does in most other things), and the change into
|
||
|
the rest is imperceptible to sense. Hence also the rainbow appears
|
||
|
with three colours; this is true of each of the two, but in a contrary
|
||
|
way. The outer band of the primary rainbow is red: for the largest
|
||
|
band reflects most sight to the sun, and the outer band is largest.
|
||
|
The middle band and the third go on the same principle. So if the
|
||
|
principles we laid down about the appearance of colours are true the
|
||
|
rainbow necessarily has three colours, and these three and no
|
||
|
others. The appearance of yellow is due to contrast, for the red is
|
||
|
whitened by its juxtaposition with green. We can see this from the
|
||
|
fact that the rainbow is purest when the cloud is blackest; and then
|
||
|
the red shows most yellow. (Yellow in the rainbow comes between red
|
||
|
and green.) So the whole of the red shows white by contrast with the
|
||
|
blackness of the cloud around: for it is white compared to the cloud
|
||
|
and the green. Again, when the rainbow is fading away and the red is
|
||
|
dissolving, the white cloud is brought into contact with the green and
|
||
|
becomes yellow. But the moon rainbow affords the best instance of this
|
||
|
colour contrast. It looks quite white: this is because it appears on
|
||
|
the dark cloud and at night. So, just as fire is intensified by
|
||
|
added fire, black beside black makes that which is in some degree
|
||
|
white look quite white. Bright dyes too show the effect of contrast.
|
||
|
In woven and embroidered stuffs the appearance of colours is
|
||
|
profoundly affected by their juxtaposition with one another (purple,
|
||
|
for instance, appears different on white and on black wool), and
|
||
|
also by differences of illumination. Thus embroiderers say that they
|
||
|
often make mistakes in their colours when they work by lamplight,
|
||
|
and use the wrong ones.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now shown why the rainbow has three colours and that these
|
||
|
are its only colours. The same cause explains the double rainbow and
|
||
|
the faintness of the colours in the outer one and their inverted
|
||
|
order. When sight is strained to a great distance the appearance of
|
||
|
the distant object is affected in a certain way: and the same thing
|
||
|
holds good here. So the reflection from the outer rainbow is weaker
|
||
|
because it takes place from a greater distance and less of it
|
||
|
reaches the sun, and so the colours seen are fainter. Their order is
|
||
|
reversed because more reflection reaches the sun from the smaller,
|
||
|
inner band. For that reflection is nearer to our sight which is
|
||
|
reflected from the band which is nearest to the primary rainbow. Now
|
||
|
the smallest band in the outer rainbow is that which is nearest, and
|
||
|
so it will be red; and the second and the third will follow the same
|
||
|
principle. Let B be the outer rainbow, A the inner one; let R stand
|
||
|
for the red colour, G for green, V for violet; yellow appears at the
|
||
|
point Y. Three rainbows or more are not found because even the
|
||
|
second is fainter, so that the third reflection can have no strength
|
||
|
whatever and cannot reach the sun at all. (See diagram.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
5
|
||
|
|
||
|
The rainbow can never be a circle nor a segment of a circle
|
||
|
greater than a semicircle. The consideration of the diagram will prove
|
||
|
this and the other properties of the rainbow. (See diagram.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let A be a hemisphere resting on the circle of the horizon, let
|
||
|
its centre be K and let H be another point appearing on the horizon.
|
||
|
Then, if the lines that fall in a cone from K have HK as their axis,
|
||
|
and, K and M being joined, the lines KM are reflected from the
|
||
|
hemisphere to H over the greater angle, the lines from K will fall
|
||
|
on the circumference of a circle. If the reflection takes place when
|
||
|
the luminous body is rising or setting the segment of the circle above
|
||
|
the earth which is cut off by the horizon will be a semi-circle; if
|
||
|
the luminous body is above the horizon it will always be less than a
|
||
|
semicircle, and it will be smallest when the luminous body culminates.
|
||
|
First let the luminous body be appearing on the horizon at the point
|
||
|
H, and let KM be reflected to H, and let the plane in which A is,
|
||
|
determined by the triangle HKM, be produced. Then the section of the
|
||
|
sphere will be a great circle. Let it be A (for it makes no difference
|
||
|
which of the planes passing through the line HK and determined by
|
||
|
the triangle KMH is produced). Now the lines drawn from H and K to a
|
||
|
point on the semicircle A are in a certain ratio to one another, and
|
||
|
no lines drawn from the same points to another point on that
|
||
|
semicircle can have the same ratio. For since both the points H and
|
||
|
K and the line KH are given, the line MH will be given too;
|
||
|
consequently the ratio of the line MH to the line MK will be given
|
||
|
too. So M will touch a given circumference. Let this be NM. Then the
|
||
|
intersection of the circumferences is given, and the same ratio cannot
|
||
|
hold between lines in the same plane drawn from the same points to any
|
||
|
other circumference but MN.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Draw a line DB outside of the figure and divide it so that
|
||
|
D:B=MH:MK. But MH is greater than MK since the reflection of the
|
||
|
cone is over the greater angle (for it subtends the greater angle of
|
||
|
the triangle KMH). Therefore D is greater than B. Then add to B a line
|
||
|
Z such that B+Z:D=D:B. Then make another line having the same ratio to
|
||
|
B as KH has to Z, and join MI.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Then I is the pole of the circle on which the lines from K fall. For
|
||
|
the ratio of D to IM is the same as that of Z to KH and of B to KI. If
|
||
|
not, let D be in the same ratio to a line indifferently lesser or
|
||
|
greater than IM, and let this line be IP. Then HK and KI and IP will
|
||
|
have the same ratios to one another as Z, B, and D. But the ratios
|
||
|
between Z, B, and D were such that Z+B:D=D: B. Therefore
|
||
|
IH:IP=IP:IK. Now, if the points K, H be joined with the point P by the
|
||
|
lines HP, KP, these lines will be to one another as IH is to IP, for
|
||
|
the sides of the triangles HIP, KPI about the angle I are
|
||
|
homologous. Therefore, HP too will be to KP as HI is to IP. But this
|
||
|
is also the ratio of MH to MK, for the ratio both of HI to IP and of
|
||
|
MH to MK is the same as that of D to B. Therefore, from the points
|
||
|
H, K there will have been drawn lines with the same ratio to one
|
||
|
another, not only to the circumference MN but to another point as
|
||
|
well, which is impossible. Since then D cannot bear that ratio to
|
||
|
any line either lesser or greater than IM (the proof being in either
|
||
|
case the same), it follows that it must stand in that ratio to MI
|
||
|
itself. Therefore as MI is to IK so IH will be to MI and finally MH to
|
||
|
MK.
|
||
|
|
||
|
If, then, a circle be described with I as pole at the distance MI it
|
||
|
will touch all the angles which the lines from H and K make by their
|
||
|
reflection. If not, it can be shown, as before, that lines drawn to
|
||
|
different points in the semicircle will have the same ratio to one
|
||
|
another, which was impossible. If, then, the semicircle A be
|
||
|
revolved about the diameter HKI, the lines reflected from the points
|
||
|
H, K at the point M will have the same ratio, and will make the
|
||
|
angle KMH equal, in every plane. Further, the angle which HM and MI
|
||
|
make with HI will always be the same. So there are a number of
|
||
|
triangles on HI and KI equal to the triangles HMI and KMI. Their
|
||
|
perpendiculars will fall on HI at the same point and will be equal.
|
||
|
Let O be the point on which they fall. Then O is the centre of the
|
||
|
circle, half of which, MN, is cut off by the horizon. (See diagram.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Next let the horizon be ABG but let H have risen above the
|
||
|
horizon. Let the axis now be HI. The proof will be the same for the
|
||
|
rest as before, but the pole I of the circle will be below the horizon
|
||
|
AG since the point H has risen above the horizon. But the pole, and
|
||
|
the centre of the circle, and the centre of that circle (namely HI)
|
||
|
which now determines the position of the sun are on the same line. But
|
||
|
since KH lies above the diameter AG, the centre will be at O on the
|
||
|
line KI below the plane of the circle AG determined the position of
|
||
|
the sun before. So the segment YX which is above the horizon will be
|
||
|
less than a semicircle. For YXM was a semicircle and it has now been
|
||
|
cut off by the horizon AG. So part of it, YM, will be invisible when
|
||
|
the sun has risen above the horizon, and the segment visible will be
|
||
|
smallest when the sun is on the meridian; for the higher H is the
|
||
|
lower the pole and the centre of the circle will be.
|
||
|
|
||
|
In the shorter days after the autumn equinox there may be a
|
||
|
rainbow at any time of the day, but in the longer days from the spring
|
||
|
to the autumn equinox there cannot be a rainbow about midday. The
|
||
|
reason for this is that when the sun is north of the equator the
|
||
|
visible arcs of its course are all greater than a semicircle, and go
|
||
|
on increasing, while the invisible arc is small, but when the sun is
|
||
|
south of the equator the visible arc is small and the invisible arc
|
||
|
great, and the farther the sun moves south of the equator the
|
||
|
greater is the invisible arc. Consequently, in the days near the
|
||
|
summer solstice, the size of the visible arc is such that before the
|
||
|
point H reaches the middle of that arc, that is its point of
|
||
|
culmination, the point is well below the horizon; the reason for
|
||
|
this being the great size of the visible arc, and the consequent
|
||
|
distance of the point of culmination from the earth. But in the days
|
||
|
near the winter solstice the visible arcs are small, and the
|
||
|
contrary is necessarily the case: for the sun is on the meridian
|
||
|
before the point H has risen far.
|
||
|
|
||
|
6
|
||
|
|
||
|
Mock suns, and rods too, are due to the causes we have described.
|
||
|
A mock sun is caused by the reflection of sight to the sun. Rods are
|
||
|
seen when sight reaches the sun under circumstances like those which
|
||
|
we described, when there are clouds near the sun and sight is
|
||
|
reflected from some liquid surface to the cloud. Here the clouds
|
||
|
themselves are colourless when you look at them directly, but in the
|
||
|
water they are full of rods. The only difference is that in this
|
||
|
latter case the colour of the cloud seems to reside in the water,
|
||
|
but in the case of rods on the cloud itself. Rods appear when the
|
||
|
composition of the cloud is uneven, dense in part and in part rare,
|
||
|
and more and less watery in different parts. Then the sight is
|
||
|
reflected to the sun: the mirrors are too small for the shape of the
|
||
|
sun to appear, but, the bright white light of the sun, to which the
|
||
|
sight is reflected, being seen on the uneven mirror, its colour
|
||
|
appears partly red, partly green or yellow. It makes no difference
|
||
|
whether sight passes through or is reflected from a medium of that
|
||
|
kind; the colour is the same in both cases; if it is red in the
|
||
|
first case it must be the same in the other.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Rods then are occasioned by the unevenness of the mirror-as
|
||
|
regards colour, not form. The mock sun, on the contrary, appears
|
||
|
when the air is very uniform, and of the same density throughout. This
|
||
|
is why it is white: the uniform character of the mirror gives the
|
||
|
reflection in it a single colour, while the fact that the sight is
|
||
|
reflected in a body and is thrown on the sun all together by the mist,
|
||
|
which is dense and watery though not yet quite water, causes the sun's
|
||
|
true colour to appear just as it does when the reflection is from
|
||
|
the dense, smooth surface of copper. So the sun's colour being
|
||
|
white, the mock sun is white too. This, too, is the reason why the
|
||
|
mock sun is a surer sign of rain than the rods; it indicates, more
|
||
|
than they do, that the air is ripe for the production of water.
|
||
|
Further a mock sun to the south is a surer sign of rain than one to
|
||
|
the north, for the air in the south is readier to turn into water than
|
||
|
that in the north.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Mock suns and rods are found, as we stated, about sunset and
|
||
|
sunrise, not above the sun nor below it, but beside it. They are not
|
||
|
found very close to the sun, nor very far from it, for the sun
|
||
|
dissolves the cloud if it is near, but if it is far off the reflection
|
||
|
cannot take place, since sight weakens when it is reflected from a
|
||
|
small mirror to a very distant object. (This is why a halo is never
|
||
|
found opposite to the sun.) If the cloud is above the sun and close to
|
||
|
it the sun will dissolve it; if it is above the sun but at a
|
||
|
distance the sight is too weak for the reflection to take place, and
|
||
|
so it will not reach the sun. But at the side of the sun, it is
|
||
|
possible for the mirror to be at such an interval that the sun does
|
||
|
not dissolve the cloud, and yet sight reaches it undiminished
|
||
|
because it moves close to the earth and is not dissipated in the
|
||
|
immensity of space. It cannot subsist below the sun because close to
|
||
|
the earth the sun's rays would dissolve it, but if it were high up and
|
||
|
the sun in the middle of the heavens, sight would be dissipated.
|
||
|
Indeed, even by the side of the sun, it is not found when the sun is
|
||
|
in the middle of the sky, for then the line of vision is not close
|
||
|
to the earth, and so but little sight reaches the mirror and the
|
||
|
reflection from it is altogether feeble.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some account has now been given of the effects of the secretion
|
||
|
above the surface of the earth; we must go on to describe its
|
||
|
operations below, when it is shut up in the parts of the earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Just as its twofold nature gives rise to various effects in the
|
||
|
upper region, so here it causes two varieties of bodies. We maintain
|
||
|
that there are two exhalations, one vaporous the other smoky, and
|
||
|
there correspond two kinds of bodies that originate in the earth,
|
||
|
'fossiles' and metals. The heat of the dry exhalation is the cause
|
||
|
of all 'fossiles'. Such are the kinds of stones that cannot be melted,
|
||
|
and realgar, and ochre, and ruddle, and sulphur, and the other
|
||
|
things of that kind, most 'fossiles' being either coloured lye or,
|
||
|
like cinnabar, a stone compounded of it. The vaporous exhalation is
|
||
|
the cause of all metals, those bodies which are either fusible or
|
||
|
malleable such as iron, copper, gold. All these originate from the
|
||
|
imprisonment of the vaporous exhalation in the earth, and especially
|
||
|
in stones. Their dryness compresses it, and it congeals just as dew or
|
||
|
hoar-frost does when it has been separated off, though in the
|
||
|
present case the metals are generated before that segregation
|
||
|
occurs. Hence, they are water in a sense, and in a sense not. Their
|
||
|
matter was that which might have become water, but it can no longer do
|
||
|
so: nor are they, like savours, due to a qualitative change in
|
||
|
actual water. Copper and gold are not formed like that, but in every
|
||
|
case the evaporation congealed before water was formed. Hence, they
|
||
|
all (except gold) are affected by fire, and they possess an
|
||
|
admixture of earth; for they still contain the dry exhalation.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This is the general theory of all these bodies, but we must take
|
||
|
up each kind of them and discuss it separately.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Book IV
|
||
|
|
||
|
1
|
||
|
|
||
|
WE have explained that the qualities that constitute the elements
|
||
|
are four, and that their combinations determine the number of the
|
||
|
elements to be four.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Two of the qualities, the hot and the cold, are active; two, the dry
|
||
|
and the moist, passive. We can satisfy ourselves of this by looking at
|
||
|
instances. In every case heat and cold determine, conjoin, and
|
||
|
change things of the same kind and things of different kinds,
|
||
|
moistening, drying, hardening, and softening them. Things dry and
|
||
|
moist, on the other hand, both in isolation and when present
|
||
|
together in the same body are the subjects of that determination and
|
||
|
of the other affections enumerated. The account we give of the
|
||
|
qualities when we define their character shows this too. Hot and
|
||
|
cold we describe as active, for 'congregating' is essentially a
|
||
|
species of 'being active': moist and dry are passive, for it is in
|
||
|
virtue of its being acted upon in a certain way that a thing is said
|
||
|
to be 'easy to determine' or 'difficult to determine'. So it is
|
||
|
clear that some of the qualities are active and some passive.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Next we must describe the operations of the active qualities and the
|
||
|
forms taken by the passive. First of all, true becoming, that is,
|
||
|
natural change, is always the work of these powers and so is the
|
||
|
corresponding natural destruction; and this becoming and this
|
||
|
destruction are found in plants and animals and their parts. True
|
||
|
natural becoming is a change introduced by these powers into the
|
||
|
matter underlying a given thing when they are in a certain ratio to
|
||
|
that matter, which is the passive qualities we have mentioned. When
|
||
|
the hot and the cold are masters of the matter they generate a
|
||
|
thing: if they are not, and the failure is partial, the object is
|
||
|
imperfectly boiled or otherwise unconcocted. But the strictest general
|
||
|
opposite of true becoming is putrefaction. All natural destruction
|
||
|
is on the way to it, as are, for instance, growing old or growing dry.
|
||
|
Putrescence is the end of all these things, that is of all natural
|
||
|
objects, except such as are destroyed by violence: you can burn, for
|
||
|
instance, flesh, bone, or anything else, but the natural course of
|
||
|
their destruction ends in putrefaction. Hence things that putrefy
|
||
|
begin by being moist and end by being dry. For the moist and the dry
|
||
|
were their matter, and the operation of the active qualities caused
|
||
|
the dry to be determined by the moist.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Destruction supervenes when the determined gets the better of the
|
||
|
determining by the help of the environment (though in a special
|
||
|
sense the word putrefaction is applied to partial destruction, when
|
||
|
a thing's nature is perverted). Hence everything, except fire, is
|
||
|
liable to putrefy; for earth, water, and air putrefy, being all of
|
||
|
them matter relatively to fire. The definition of putrefaction is: the
|
||
|
destruction of the peculiar and natural heat in any moist subject by
|
||
|
external heat, that is, by the heat of the environment. So since
|
||
|
lack of heat is the ground of this affection and everything in as
|
||
|
far as it lacks heat is cold, both heat and cold will be the causes of
|
||
|
putrefaction, which will be due indifferently to cold in the
|
||
|
putrefying subject or to heat in the environment.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This explains why everything that putrefies grows drier and ends
|
||
|
by becoming earth or dung. The subject's own heat departs and causes
|
||
|
the natural moisture to evaporate with it, and then there is nothing
|
||
|
left to draw in moisture, for it is a thing's peculiar heat that
|
||
|
attracts moisture and draws it in. Again, putrefaction takes place
|
||
|
less in cold that in hot seasons, for in winter the surrounding air
|
||
|
and water contain but little heat and it has no power, but in summer
|
||
|
there is more. Again, what is frozen does not putrefy, for its cold is
|
||
|
greater that the heat of the air and so is not mastered, whereas
|
||
|
what affects a thing does master it. Nor does that which is boiling or
|
||
|
hot putrefy, for the heat in the air being less than that in the
|
||
|
object does not prevail over it or set up any change. So too
|
||
|
anything that is flowing or in motion is less apt to putrefy than a
|
||
|
thing at rest, for the motion set up by the heat in the air is
|
||
|
weaker than that pre-existing in the object, and so it causes no
|
||
|
change. For the same reason a great quantity of a thing putrefies less
|
||
|
readily than a little, for the greater quantity contains too much
|
||
|
proper fire and cold for the corresponding qualities in the
|
||
|
environment to get the better of. Hence, the sea putrefies quickly
|
||
|
when broken up into parts, but not as a whole; and all other waters
|
||
|
likewise. Animals too are generated in putrefying bodies, because
|
||
|
the heat that has been secreted, being natural, organizes the
|
||
|
particles secreted with it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for the nature of becoming and of destruction.
|
||
|
|
||
|
2
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must now describe the next kinds of processes which the qualities
|
||
|
already mentioned set up in actually existing natural objects as
|
||
|
matter.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of these concoction is due to heat; its species are ripening,
|
||
|
boiling, broiling. Inconcoction is due to cold and its species are
|
||
|
rawness, imperfect boiling, imperfect broiling. (We must recognize
|
||
|
that the things are not properly denoted by these words: the various
|
||
|
classes of similar objects have no names universally applicable to
|
||
|
them; consequently we must think of the species enumerated as being
|
||
|
not what those words denote but something like it.) Let us say what
|
||
|
each of them is. Concoction is a process in which the natural and
|
||
|
proper heat of an object perfects the corresponding passive qualities,
|
||
|
which are the proper matter of any given object. For when concoction
|
||
|
has taken place we say that a thing has been perfected and has come to
|
||
|
be itself. It is the proper heat of a thing that sets up this
|
||
|
perfecting, though external influences may contribute in some
|
||
|
degrees to its fulfilment. Baths, for instance, and other things of
|
||
|
the kind contribute to the digestion of food, but the primary cause is
|
||
|
the proper heat of the body. In some cases of concoction the end of
|
||
|
the process is the nature of the thing-nature, that is, in the sense
|
||
|
of the formal cause and essence. In other cases it leads to some
|
||
|
presupposed state which is attained when the moisture has acquired
|
||
|
certain properties or a certain magnitude in the process of being
|
||
|
broiled or boiled or of putrefying, or however else it is being
|
||
|
heated. This state is the end, for when it has been reached the
|
||
|
thing has some use and we say that concoction has taken place. Must is
|
||
|
an instance of this, and the matter in boils when it becomes purulent,
|
||
|
and tears when they become rheum, and so with the rest.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Concoction ensues whenever the matter, the moisture, is
|
||
|
mastered. For the matter is what is determined by the heat
|
||
|
connatural to the object, and as long as the ratio between them exists
|
||
|
in it a thing maintains its nature. Hence things like the liquid and
|
||
|
solid excreta and ejecta in general are signs of health, and
|
||
|
concoction is said to have taken place in them, for they show that the
|
||
|
proper heat has got the better of the indeterminate matter.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Things that undergo a process of concoction necessarily become
|
||
|
thicker and hotter, for the action of heat is to make things more
|
||
|
compact, thicker, and drier.
|
||
|
|
||
|
This then is the nature of concoction: but inconcoction is an
|
||
|
imperfect state due to lack of proper heat, that is, to cold. That
|
||
|
of which the imperfect state is, is the corresponding passive
|
||
|
qualities which are the natural matter of anything.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So much for the definition of concoction and inconcoction.
|
||
|
|
||
|
3
|
||
|
|
||
|
Ripening is a sort of concoction; for we call it ripening when there
|
||
|
is a concoction of the nutriment in fruit. And since concoction is a
|
||
|
sort of perfecting, the process of ripening is perfect when the
|
||
|
seeds in fruit are able to reproduce the fruit in which they are
|
||
|
found; for in all other cases as well this is what we mean by
|
||
|
'perfect'. This is what 'ripening' means when the word is applied to
|
||
|
fruit. However, many other things that have undergone concoction are
|
||
|
said to be 'ripe', the general character of the process being the
|
||
|
same, though the word is applied by an extension of meaning. The
|
||
|
reason for this extension is, as we explained before, that the various
|
||
|
modes in which natural heat and cold perfect the matter they determine
|
||
|
have not special names appropriated to them. In the case of boils
|
||
|
and phlegm, and the like, the process of ripening is the concoction of
|
||
|
the moisture in them by their natural heat, for only that which gets
|
||
|
the better of matter can determine it. So everything that ripens is
|
||
|
condensed from a spirituous into a watery state, and from a watery
|
||
|
into an earthy state, and in general from being rare becomes dense. In
|
||
|
this process the nature of the thing that is ripening incorporates
|
||
|
some of the matter in itself, and some it rejects. So much for the
|
||
|
definition of ripening.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Rawness is its opposite and is therefore an imperfect concoction
|
||
|
of the nutriment in the fruit, namely, of the undetermined moisture.
|
||
|
Consequently a raw thing is either spirituous or watery or contains
|
||
|
both spirit and water. Ripening being a kind of perfecting, rawness
|
||
|
will be an imperfect state, and this state is due to a lack of natural
|
||
|
heat and its disproportion to the moisture that is undergoing the
|
||
|
process of ripening. (Nothing moist ripens without the admixture of
|
||
|
some dry matter: water alone of liquids does not thicken.) This
|
||
|
disproportion may be due either to defect of heat or to excess of
|
||
|
the matter to be determined: hence the juice of raw things is thin,
|
||
|
cold rather than hot, and unfit for food or drink. Rawness, like
|
||
|
ripening, is used to denote a variety of states. Thus the liquid and
|
||
|
solid excreta and catarrhs are called raw for the same reason, for
|
||
|
in every case the word is applied to things because their heat has not
|
||
|
got the mastery in them and compacted them. If we go further, brick is
|
||
|
called raw and so is milk and many other things too when they are such
|
||
|
as to admit of being changed and compacted by heat but have remained
|
||
|
unaffected. Hence, while we speak of 'boiled' water, we cannot speak
|
||
|
of raw water, since it does not thicken. We have now defined
|
||
|
ripening and rawness and assigned their causes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Boiling is, in general, a concoction by moist heat of the
|
||
|
indeterminate matter contained in the moisture of the thing boiled,
|
||
|
and the word is strictly applicable only to things boiled in the way
|
||
|
of cooking. The indeterminate matter, as we said, will be either
|
||
|
spirituous or watery. The cause of the concoction is the fire
|
||
|
contained in the moisture; for what is cooked in a frying-pan is
|
||
|
broiled: it is the heat outside that affects it and, as for the
|
||
|
moisture in which it is contained, it dries this up and draws it
|
||
|
into itself. But a thing that is being boiled behaves in the
|
||
|
opposite way: the moisture contained in it is drawn out of it by the
|
||
|
heat in the liquid outside. Hence boiled meats are drier than broiled;
|
||
|
for, in boiling, things do not draw the moisture into themselves,
|
||
|
since the external heat gets the better of the internal: if the
|
||
|
internal heat had got the better it would have drawn the moisture to
|
||
|
itself. Not every body admits of the process of boiling: if there is
|
||
|
no moisture in it, it does not (for instance, stones), nor does it
|
||
|
if there is moisture in it but the density of the body is too great
|
||
|
for it-to-be mastered, as in the case of wood. But only those bodies
|
||
|
can be boiled that contain moisture which can be acted on by the
|
||
|
heat contained in the liquid outside. It is true that gold and wood
|
||
|
and many other things are said to be 'boiled': but this is a stretch
|
||
|
of the meaning of the word, though the kind of thing intended is the
|
||
|
same, the reason for the usage being that the various cases have no
|
||
|
names appropriated to them. Liquids too, like milk and must, are
|
||
|
said to undergo a process of 'boiling' when the external fire that
|
||
|
surrounds and heats them changes the savour in the liquid into a given
|
||
|
form, the process being thus in a way like what we have called
|
||
|
boiling.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The end of the things that undergo boiling, or indeed any form of
|
||
|
concoction, is not always the same: some are meant to be eaten, some
|
||
|
drunk, and some are intended for other uses; for instance dyes, too,
|
||
|
are said to be 'boiled'.
|
||
|
|
||
|
All those things then admit of 'boiling' which can grow denser,
|
||
|
smaller, or heavier; also those which do that with a part of
|
||
|
themselves and with a part do the opposite, dividing in such a way
|
||
|
that one portion thickens while the other grows thinner, like milk
|
||
|
when it divides into whey and curd. Oil by itself is affected in
|
||
|
none of these ways, and therefore cannot be said to admit of
|
||
|
'boiling'. Such then is the pfcies of concoction known as 'boiling',
|
||
|
and the process is the same in an artificial and in a natural
|
||
|
instrument, for the cause will be the same in every case.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Imperfect boiling is the form of inconcoction opposed to boiling.
|
||
|
Now the opposite of boiling properly so called is an inconcoction of
|
||
|
the undetermined matter in a body due to lack of heat in the
|
||
|
surrounding liquid. (Lack of heat implies, as we have pointed out, the
|
||
|
presence of cold.) The motion which causes imperfect boiling is
|
||
|
different from that which causes boiling, for the heat which
|
||
|
operates the concoction is driven out. The lack of heat is due
|
||
|
either to the amount of cold in the liquid or to the quantity of
|
||
|
moisture in the object undergoing the process of boiling. Where either
|
||
|
of these conditions is realized the heat in the surrounding liquid
|
||
|
is too great to have no effect at all, but too small to carry out
|
||
|
the process of concocting uniformly and thoroughly. Hence things are
|
||
|
harder when they are imperfectly boiled than when they are boiled, and
|
||
|
the moisture in them more distinct from the solid parts. So much for
|
||
|
the definition and causes of boiling and imperfect boiling.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Broiling is concoction by dry foreign heat. Hence if a man were to
|
||
|
boil a thing but the change and concoction in it were due, not to
|
||
|
the heat of the liquid but to that of the fire, the thing will have
|
||
|
been broiled and not boiled when the process has been carried to
|
||
|
completion: if the process has gone too far we use the word 'scorched'
|
||
|
to describe it. If the process leaves the thing drier at the end the
|
||
|
agent has been dry heat. Hence the outside is drier than the inside,
|
||
|
the opposite being true of things boiled. Where the process is
|
||
|
artificial, broiling is more difficult than boiling, for it is
|
||
|
difficult to heat the inside and the outside uniformly, since the
|
||
|
parts nearer to the fire are the first to get dry and consequently get
|
||
|
more intensely dry. In this way the outer pores contract and the
|
||
|
moisture in the thing cannot be secreted but is shut in by the closing
|
||
|
of the pores. Now broiling and boiling are artificial processes, but
|
||
|
the same general kind of thing, as we said, is found in nature too.
|
||
|
The affections produced are similar though they lack a name; for art
|
||
|
imitates nature. For instance, the concoction of food in the body is
|
||
|
like boiling, for it takes place in a hot and moist medium and the
|
||
|
agent is the heat of the body. So, too, certain forms of indigestion
|
||
|
are like imperfect boiling. And it is not true that animals are
|
||
|
generated in the concoction of food, as some say. Really they are
|
||
|
generated in the excretion which putrefies in the lower belly, and
|
||
|
they ascend afterwards. For concoction goes on in the upper belly
|
||
|
but the excretion putrefies in the lower: the reason for this has been
|
||
|
explained elsewhere.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have seen that the opposite of boiling is imperfect boiling:
|
||
|
now there is something correspondingly opposed to the species of
|
||
|
concoction called broiling, but it is more difficult to find a name
|
||
|
for it. It would be the kind of thing that would happen if there
|
||
|
were imperfect broiling instead of broiling proper through lack of
|
||
|
heat due to deficiency in the external fire or to the quantity of
|
||
|
water in the thing undergoing the process. For then we should get
|
||
|
too much heat for no effect to be produced, but too little for
|
||
|
concoction to take place.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We have now explained concoction and inconcoction, ripening and
|
||
|
rawness, boiling and broiling, and their opposites.
|
||
|
|
||
|
4
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must now describe the forms taken by the passive qualities the
|
||
|
moist and the dry. The elements of bodies, that is, the passive
|
||
|
ones, are the moist and the dry; the bodies themselves are
|
||
|
compounded of them and whichever predominates determines the nature of
|
||
|
the body; thus some bodies partake more of the dry, others of the
|
||
|
moist. All the forms to be described will exist either actually, or
|
||
|
potentially and in their opposite: for instance, there is actual
|
||
|
melting and on the other hand that which admits of being melted.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since the moist is easily determined and the dry determined with
|
||
|
difficulty, their relation to one another is like that of a dish and
|
||
|
its condiments. The moist is what makes the dry determinable, and each
|
||
|
serves as a sort of glue to the other-as Empedocles said in his poem
|
||
|
on Nature, 'glueing meal together by means of water.' Thus the
|
||
|
determined body involves them both. Of the elements earth is
|
||
|
especially representative of the dry, water of the moist, and
|
||
|
therefore all determinate bodies in our world involve earth and water.
|
||
|
Every body shows the quality of that element which predominates in it.
|
||
|
It is because earth and water are the material elements of all
|
||
|
bodies that animals live in them alone and not in air or fire.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of the qualities of bodies hardness and softness are those which
|
||
|
must primarily belong to a determined thing, for anything made up of
|
||
|
the dry and the moist is necessarily either hard or soft. Hard is that
|
||
|
the surface of which does not yield into itself; soft that which
|
||
|
does yield but not by interchange of place: water, for instance, is
|
||
|
not soft, for its surface does not yield to pressure or sink in but
|
||
|
there is an interchange of place. Those things are absolutely hard and
|
||
|
soft which satisfy the definition absolutely, and those things
|
||
|
relatively so which do so compared with another thing. Now
|
||
|
relatively to one another hard and soft are indefinable, because it is
|
||
|
a matter of degree, but since all the objects of sense are
|
||
|
determined by reference to the faculty of sense it is clearly the
|
||
|
relation to touch which determines that which is hard and soft
|
||
|
absolutely, and touch is that which we use as a standard or mean. So
|
||
|
we call that which exceeds it hard and that which falls short of it
|
||
|
soft.
|
||
|
|
||
|
5
|
||
|
|
||
|
A body determined by its own boundary must be either hard or soft;
|
||
|
for it either yields or does not.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It must also be concrete: or it could not be so determined. So since
|
||
|
everything that is determined and solid is either hard or soft and
|
||
|
these qualities are due to concretion, all composite and determined
|
||
|
bodies must involve concretion. Concretion therefore must be
|
||
|
discussed.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now there are two causes besides matter, the agent and the quality
|
||
|
brought about, the agent being the efficient cause, the quality the
|
||
|
formal cause. Hence concretion and disaggregation, drying and
|
||
|
moistening, must have these two causes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
But since concretion is a form of drying let us speak of the
|
||
|
latter first.
|
||
|
|
||
|
As we have explained, the agent operates by means of two qualities
|
||
|
and the patient is acted on in virtue of two qualities: action takes
|
||
|
place by means of heat or cold, and the quality is produced either
|
||
|
by the presence or by the absence of heat or cold; but that which is
|
||
|
acted upon is moist or dry or a compound of both. Water is the element
|
||
|
characterized by the moist, earth that characterized by the dry, for
|
||
|
these among the elements that admit the qualities moist and dry are
|
||
|
passive. Therefore cold, too, being found in water and earth (both
|
||
|
of which we recognize to be cold), must be reckoned rather as a
|
||
|
passive quality. It is active only as contributing to destruction or
|
||
|
incidentally in the manner described before; for cold is sometimes
|
||
|
actually said to burn and to warm, but not in the same way as heat
|
||
|
does, but by collecting and concentrating heat.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The subjects of drying are water and the various watery fluids and
|
||
|
those bodies which contain water either foreign or connatural. By
|
||
|
foreign I mean like the water in wool, by connatural, like that in
|
||
|
milk. The watery fluids are wine, urine, whey, and in general those
|
||
|
fluids which have no sediment or only a little, except where this
|
||
|
absence of sediment is due to viscosity. For in some cases, in oil and
|
||
|
pitch for instance, it is the viscosity which prevents any sediment
|
||
|
from appearing.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It is always a process of heating or cooling that dries things,
|
||
|
but the agent in both cases is heat, either internal or external.
|
||
|
For even when things are dried by cooling, like a garment, where the
|
||
|
moisture exists separately it is the internal heat that dries them. It
|
||
|
carries off the moisture in the shape of vapour (if there is not too
|
||
|
much of it), being itself driven out by the surrounding cold. So
|
||
|
everything is dried, as we have said, by a process either of heating
|
||
|
or cooling, but the agent is always heat, either internal or external,
|
||
|
carrying off the moisture in vapour. By external heat I mean as
|
||
|
where things are boiled: by internal where the heat breathes out and
|
||
|
takes away and uses up its moisture. So much for drying.
|
||
|
|
||
|
6
|
||
|
|
||
|
Liquefaction is, first, condensation into water; second, the melting
|
||
|
of a solidified body. The first, condensation, is due to the cooling
|
||
|
of vapour: what melting is will appear from the account of
|
||
|
solidification.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Whatever solidifies is either water or a mixture of earth and water,
|
||
|
and the agent is either dry heat or cold. Hence those of the bodies
|
||
|
solidified by heat or cold which are soluble at all are dissolved by
|
||
|
their opposites. Bodies solidified by the dry-hot are dissolved by
|
||
|
water, which is the moist-cold, while bodies solidified by cold are
|
||
|
dissolved by fire, which is hot. Some things seem to be solidified
|
||
|
by water, e.g. boiled honey, but really it is not the water but the
|
||
|
cold in the water which effects the solidification. Aqueous bodies are
|
||
|
not solidified by fire: for it is fire that dissolves them, and the
|
||
|
same cause in the same relation cannot have opposite effects upon
|
||
|
the same thing. Again, water solidifies owing to the departure of
|
||
|
heat; so it will clearly be dissolved by the entry into it of heat:
|
||
|
cold, therefore, must be the agent in solidifying it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Hence aqueous bodies do not thicken when they solidify; for
|
||
|
thickening occurs when the moisture goes off and the dry matter
|
||
|
comes together, but water is the only liquid that does not thicken.
|
||
|
Those bodies that are made up of both earth and water are solidified
|
||
|
both by fire and by cold and in either case are thickened. The
|
||
|
operation of the two is in a way the same and in a way different. Heat
|
||
|
acts by drawing off the moisture, and as the moisture goes off in
|
||
|
vapour the dry matter thickens and collects. Cold acts by driving
|
||
|
out the heat, which is accompanied by the moisture as this goes off in
|
||
|
vapour with it. Bodies that are soft but not liquid do not thicken but
|
||
|
solidify when the moisture leaves them, e.g. potter's clay in
|
||
|
process of baking: but those mixed bodies that are liquid thicken
|
||
|
besides solidifying, like milk. Those bodies which have first been
|
||
|
thickened or hardened by cold often begin by becoming moist: thus
|
||
|
potter's clay at first in the process of baking steams and grows
|
||
|
softer, and is liable to distortion in the ovens for that reason.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now of the bodies solidified by cold which are made up both of earth
|
||
|
and water but in which the earth preponderates, those which solidify
|
||
|
by the departure of heat melt by heat when it enters into them
|
||
|
again; this is the case with frozen mud. But those which solidify by
|
||
|
refrigeration, where all the moisture has gone off in vapour with
|
||
|
the heat, like iron and horn, cannot be dissolved except by
|
||
|
excessive heat, but they can be softened-though manufactured iron does
|
||
|
melt, to the point of becoming fluid and then solidifying again.
|
||
|
This is how steel is made. The dross sinks to the bottom and is
|
||
|
purged away: when this has been done often and the metal is pure we
|
||
|
have steel. The process is not repeated often because the purification
|
||
|
of the metal involves great waste and loss of weight. But the iron
|
||
|
that has less dross is the better iron. The stone pyrimachus, too,
|
||
|
melts and forms into drops and becomes fluid; after having been in a
|
||
|
fluid state it solidifies and becomes hard again. Millstones, too,
|
||
|
melt and become fluid: when the fluid mass begins to solidify it is
|
||
|
black but its consistency comes to be like that of lime. and earth,
|
||
|
too
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of the bodies which are solidified by dry heat some are insoluble,
|
||
|
others are dissolved by liquid. Pottery and some kinds of stone that
|
||
|
are formed out of earth burnt up by fire, such as millstones, cannot
|
||
|
be dissolved. Natron and salt are soluble by liquid, but not all
|
||
|
liquid but only such as is cold. Hence water and any of its
|
||
|
varieties melt them, but oil does not. For the opposite of the dry-hot
|
||
|
is the cold-moist and what the one solidified the other will dissolve,
|
||
|
and so opposites will have opposite effects.
|
||
|
|
||
|
7
|
||
|
|
||
|
If a body contains more water than earth fire only thickens it: if
|
||
|
it contains more earth fire solidifies it. Hence natron and salt and
|
||
|
stone and potter's clay must contain more earth.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The nature of oil presents the greatest problem. If water
|
||
|
preponderated in it, cold ought to solidify it; if earth
|
||
|
preponderated, then fire ought to do so. Actually neither
|
||
|
solidifies, but both thicken it. The reason is that it is full of
|
||
|
air (hence it floats on the top of water, since air tends to rise).
|
||
|
Cold thickens it by turning the air in it into water, for any
|
||
|
mixture of oil and water is thicker than either. Fire and the lapse of
|
||
|
time thicken and whiten it. The whitening follows on the evaporation
|
||
|
of any water that may have been in it; the is due to the change of the
|
||
|
air into water as the heat in the oil is dissipated. The effect in
|
||
|
both cases is the same and the cause is the same, but the manner of
|
||
|
its operation is different. Both heat and cold thicken it, but neither
|
||
|
dries it (neither the sun nor cold dries oil), not only because it
|
||
|
is glutinous but because it contains air. Its glutinous nature
|
||
|
prevents it from giving off vapour and so fire does not dry it or boil
|
||
|
it off.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Those bodies which are made up of earth and water may be
|
||
|
classified according to the preponderance of either. There is a kind
|
||
|
of wine, for instance, which both solidifies and thickens by boiling-I
|
||
|
mean, must. All bodies of this kind lose their water as they That it
|
||
|
is their water may be seen from the fact that the vapour from them
|
||
|
condenses into water when collected. So wherever some sediment is left
|
||
|
this is of the nature of earth. Some of these bodies, as we have said,
|
||
|
are also thickened and dried by cold. For cold not only solidifies but
|
||
|
also dries water, and thickens things by turning air into water.
|
||
|
(Solidifying, as we have said, is a form of drying.) Now those
|
||
|
things that are not thickened by cold, but solidified, belong rather
|
||
|
to water, e.g.. wine, urine, vinegar, lye, whey. But those things that
|
||
|
are thickened (not by evaporation due to fire) are made up either of
|
||
|
earth or of water and air: honey of earth, while oil contains air.
|
||
|
Milk and blood, too, are made up of both water and earth, though earth
|
||
|
generally predominates in them. So, too, are the liquids out of
|
||
|
which natron and salt are formed; and stones are also formed from some
|
||
|
mixtures of this kind. Hence, if the whey has not been separated, it
|
||
|
burns away if you boil it over a fire. But the earthy element in
|
||
|
milk can also be coagulated by the help of fig-juice, if you boil it
|
||
|
in a certain way as doctors do when they treat it with fig-juice,
|
||
|
and this is how the whey and the cheese are commonly separated.
|
||
|
Whey, once separated, does not thicken, as the milk did, but boils
|
||
|
away like water. Sometimes, however, there is little or no cheese in
|
||
|
milk, and such milk is not nutritive and is more like water. The
|
||
|
case of blood is similar: cold dries and so solidifies it. Those kinds
|
||
|
of blood that do not solidify, like that of the stag, belong rather to
|
||
|
water and are very cold. Hence they contain no fibres: for the
|
||
|
fibres are of earth and solid, and blood from which they have been
|
||
|
removed does not solidify. This is because it cannot dry; for what
|
||
|
remains is water, just as what remains of milk when cheese has been
|
||
|
removed is water. The fact that diseased blood will not solidify is
|
||
|
evidence of the same thing, for such blood is of the nature of serum
|
||
|
and that is phlegm and water, the nature of the animal having failed
|
||
|
to get the better of it and digest it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some of these bodies are soluble, e.g. natron, some insoluble,
|
||
|
e.g. pottery: of the latter, some, like horn, can be softened by heat,
|
||
|
others, like pottery and stone, cannot. The reason is that opposite
|
||
|
causes have opposite effects: consequently, if solidification is due
|
||
|
to two causes, the cold and the dry, solution must be due to the hot
|
||
|
and the moist, that is, to fire and to water (these being
|
||
|
opposites): water dissolving what was solidified by fire alone, fire
|
||
|
what was solidified by cold alone. Consequently, if any things
|
||
|
happen to be solidified by the action of both, these are least apt
|
||
|
to be soluble. Such a case we find where things have been heated and
|
||
|
are then solidified by cold. When the heat in leaving them has
|
||
|
caused most of the moisture to evaporate, the cold so compacts these
|
||
|
bodies together again as to leave no entrance even for moisture.
|
||
|
Therefore heat does not dissolve them (for it only dissolves those
|
||
|
bodies that are solidified by cold alone), nor does water (for it does
|
||
|
not dissolve what cold solidifies, but only what is solidified by
|
||
|
dry heat). But iron is melted by heat and solidified by cold. Wood
|
||
|
consists of earth and air and is therefore combustible but cannot be
|
||
|
melted or softened by heat. (For the same reason it floats in
|
||
|
water-all except ebony. This does not, for other kinds of wood contain
|
||
|
a preponderance of air, but in black ebony the air has escaped and
|
||
|
so earth preponderates in it.) Pottery consists of earth alone because
|
||
|
it solidified gradually in the process of drying. Water cannot get
|
||
|
into it, for the pores were only large enough to admit of vapour
|
||
|
escaping: and seeing that fire solidified it, that cannot dissolve
|
||
|
it either.
|
||
|
|
||
|
So solidification and melting, their causes, and the kinds of
|
||
|
subjects in which they occur have been described.
|
||
|
|
||
|
8
|
||
|
|
||
|
All this makes it clear that bodies are formed by heat and cold
|
||
|
and that these agents operate by thickening and solidifying. It is
|
||
|
because these qualities fashion bodies that we find heat in all of
|
||
|
them, and in some cold in so far as heat is absent. These qualities,
|
||
|
then, are present as active, and the moist and the dry as passive, and
|
||
|
consequently all four are found in mixed bodies. So water and earth
|
||
|
are the constituents of homogeneous bodies both in plants and in
|
||
|
animals and of metals such as gold, silver, and the rest-water and
|
||
|
earth and their respective exhalations shut up in the compound bodies,
|
||
|
as we have explained elsewhere.
|
||
|
|
||
|
All these mixed bodies are distinguished from one another, firstly
|
||
|
by the qualities special to the various senses, that is, by their
|
||
|
capacities of action. (For a thing is white, fragrant, sonant,
|
||
|
sweet, hot, cold in virtue of a power of acting on sense). Secondly by
|
||
|
other more characteristic affections which express their aptitude to
|
||
|
be affected: I mean, for instance, the aptitude to melt or solidify or
|
||
|
bend and so forth, all these qualities, like moist and dry, being
|
||
|
passive. These are the qualities that differentiate bone, flesh,
|
||
|
sinew, wood, bark, stone and all other homogeneous natural bodies. Let
|
||
|
us begin by enumerating these qualities expressing the aptitude or
|
||
|
inaptitude of a thing to be affected in a certain way. They are as
|
||
|
follows: to be apt or inapt to solidify, melt, be softened by heat, be
|
||
|
softened by water, bend, break, be comminuted, impressed, moulded,
|
||
|
squeezed; to be tractile or non-tractile, malleable or
|
||
|
non-malleable, to be fissile or non-fissile, apt or inapt to be cut;
|
||
|
to be viscous or friable, compressible or incompressible,
|
||
|
combustible or incombustible; to be apt or inapt to give off fumes.
|
||
|
These affections differentiate most bodies from one another. Let us go
|
||
|
on to explain the nature of each of them. We have already given a
|
||
|
general account of that which is apt or inapt to solidify or to
|
||
|
melt, but let us return to them again now. Of all the bodies that
|
||
|
admit of solidification and hardening, some are brought into this
|
||
|
state by heat, others by cold. Heat does this by drying up their
|
||
|
moisture, cold by driving out their heat. Consequently some bodies are
|
||
|
affected in this way by defect of moisture, some by defect of heat:
|
||
|
watery bodies by defect of heat, earthy bodies of moisture. Now
|
||
|
those bodies that are so affected by defect of moisture are
|
||
|
dissolved by water, unless like pottery they have so contracted that
|
||
|
their pores are too small for the particles of water to enter. All
|
||
|
those bodies in which this is not the case are dissolved by water,
|
||
|
e.g. natron, salt, dry mud. Those bodies that solidified through
|
||
|
defect of heat are melted by heat, e.g. ice, lead, copper. So much for
|
||
|
the bodies that admit of solidification and of melting, and those that
|
||
|
do not admit of melting.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The bodies which do not admit of solidification are those which
|
||
|
contain no aqueous moisture and are not watery, but in which heat
|
||
|
and earth preponderate, like honey and must (for these are in a sort
|
||
|
of state of effervescence), and those which do possess some water
|
||
|
but have a preponderance of air, like oil and quicksilver, and all
|
||
|
viscous substances such as pitch and birdlime.
|
||
|
|
||
|
9
|
||
|
|
||
|
Those bodies admit of softening which are not (like ice) made up
|
||
|
of water, but in which earth predominates. All their moisture must not
|
||
|
have left them (as in the case of natron and salt), nor must the
|
||
|
relation of dry to moist in them be incongruous (as in the case of
|
||
|
pottery). They must be tractile (without admitting water) or malleable
|
||
|
(without consisting of water), and the agent in softening them is
|
||
|
fire. Such are iron and horn.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Both of bodies that can melt and of bodies that cannot, some do
|
||
|
and some do not admit of softening in water. Copper, for instance,
|
||
|
which can be melted, cannot be softened in water, whereas wool and
|
||
|
earth can be softened in water, for they can be soaked. (It is true
|
||
|
that though copper can be melted the agent in its case is not water,
|
||
|
but some of the bodies that can be melted by water too such as
|
||
|
natron and salt cannot be softened in water: for nothing is said to be
|
||
|
so affected unless the water soaks into it and makes it softer.)
|
||
|
Some things, on the other hand, such as wool and grain, can be
|
||
|
softened by water though they cannot be melted. Any body that is to be
|
||
|
softened by water must be of earth and must have its pores larger than
|
||
|
the particles of water, and the pores themselves must be able to
|
||
|
resist the action of water, whereas bodies that can be 'melted' by
|
||
|
water must have pores throughout.
|
||
|
|
||
|
(Why is it that earth is both 'melted' and softened by moisture,
|
||
|
while natron is 'melted' but not softened? Because natron is
|
||
|
pervaded throughout by pores so that the parts are immediately divided
|
||
|
by the water, but earth has also pores which do not connect and is
|
||
|
therefore differently affected according as the water enters by one or
|
||
|
the other set of pores.)
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some bodies can be bent or straightened, like the reed or the withy,
|
||
|
some cannot, like pottery and stone. Those bodies are apt to be bent
|
||
|
and straightened which can change from being curved to being
|
||
|
straight and from being straight to being curved, and bending and
|
||
|
straightening consist in the change or motion to the straight or to
|
||
|
a curve, for a thing is said to be in process of being bent whether it
|
||
|
is being made to assume a convex or a concave shape. So bending is
|
||
|
defined as motion to the convex or the concave without a change of
|
||
|
length. For if we added 'or to the straight', we should have a thing
|
||
|
bent and straight at once, and it is impossible for that which is
|
||
|
straight to be bent. And if all bending is a bending back or a bending
|
||
|
down, the former being a change to the convex, the latter to the
|
||
|
concave, a motion that leads to the straight cannot be called bending,
|
||
|
but bending and straightening are two different things. These, then,
|
||
|
are the things that can, and those that cannot be bent, and be
|
||
|
straightened.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some things can be both broken and comminuted, others admit only one
|
||
|
or the other. Wood, for instance, can be broken but not comminuted,
|
||
|
ice and stone can be comminuted but not broken, while pottery may
|
||
|
either be comminuted or broken. The distinction is this: breaking is a
|
||
|
division and separation into large parts, comminution into parts of
|
||
|
any size, but there must be more of them than two. Now those solids
|
||
|
that have many pores not communicating with one another are
|
||
|
comminuible (for the limit to their subdivision is set by the
|
||
|
pores), but those whose pores stretch continuously for a long way
|
||
|
are breakable, while those which have pores of both kinds are both
|
||
|
comminuible and breakable.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some things, e.g. copper and wax, are impressible, others, e.g.
|
||
|
pottery and water, are not. The process of being impressed is the
|
||
|
sinking of a part of the surface of a thing in response to pressure or
|
||
|
a blow, in general to contact. Such bodies are either soft, like
|
||
|
wax, where part of the surface is depressed while the rest remains, or
|
||
|
hard, like copper. Non-impressible bodies are either hard, like
|
||
|
pottery (its surface does not give way and sink in), or liquid, like
|
||
|
water (for though water does give way it is not in a part of it, for
|
||
|
there is a reciprocal change of place of all its parts). Those
|
||
|
impressibles that retain the shape impressed on them and are easily
|
||
|
moulded by the hand are called 'plastic'; those that are not easily
|
||
|
moulded, such as stone or wood, or are easily moulded but do not
|
||
|
retain the shape impressed, like wool or a sponge, are not plastic.
|
||
|
The last group are said to be 'squeezable'. Things are 'squeezable'
|
||
|
when they can contract into themselves under pressure, their surface
|
||
|
sinking in without being broken and without the parts interchanging
|
||
|
position as happens in the case of water. (We speak of pressure when
|
||
|
there is movement and the motor remains in contact with the thing
|
||
|
moved, of impact when the movement is due to the local movement of the
|
||
|
motor.) Those bodies are subject to squeezing which have empty
|
||
|
pores-empty, that is, of the stuff of which the body itself
|
||
|
consists-and that can sink upon the void spaces within them, or rather
|
||
|
upon their pores. For sometimes the pores upon which a body sinks in
|
||
|
are not empty (a wet sponge, for instance, has its pores full). But
|
||
|
the pores, if full, must be full of something softer than the body
|
||
|
itself which is to contract. Examples of things squeezable are the
|
||
|
sponge, wax, flesh. Those things are not squeezable which cannot be
|
||
|
made to contract upon their own pores by pressure, either because they
|
||
|
have no pores or because their pores are full of something too hard.
|
||
|
Thus iron, stone, water and all liquids are incapable of being
|
||
|
squeezed.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Things are tractile when their surface can be made to elongate,
|
||
|
for being drawn out is a movement of the surface, remaining
|
||
|
unbroken, in the direction of the mover. Some things are tractile,
|
||
|
e.g. hair, thongs, sinew, dough, birdlime, and some are not, e.g.
|
||
|
water, stone. Some things are both tractile and squeezable, e.g. wool;
|
||
|
in other cases the two qualities do not coincide; phlegm, for
|
||
|
instance, is tractile but not squeezable, and a sponge squeezable
|
||
|
but not tractile.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some things are malleable, like copper. Some are not, like stone and
|
||
|
wood. Things are malleable when their surface can be made to move (but
|
||
|
only in part) both downwards and sideways with one and the same
|
||
|
blow: when this is not possible a body is not malleable. All malleable
|
||
|
bodies are impressible, but not all impressible bodies are
|
||
|
malleable, e.g. wood, though on the whole the two go together. Of
|
||
|
squeezable things some are malleable and some not: wax and mud are
|
||
|
malleable, wool is not. Some things are fissile, e.g. wood, some are
|
||
|
not, e.g. potter's clay. A thing is fissile when it is apt to divide
|
||
|
in advance of the instrument dividing it, for a body is said to
|
||
|
split when it divides to a further point than that to which the
|
||
|
dividing instrument divides it and the act of division advances: which
|
||
|
is not the case with cutting. Those bodies which cannot behave like
|
||
|
this are non-fissile. Nothing soft is fissile (by soft I mean
|
||
|
absolutely soft and not relatively: for iron itself may be
|
||
|
relatively soft); nor are all hard things fissile, but only such as
|
||
|
are neither liquid nor impressible nor comminuible. Such are the
|
||
|
bodies that have the pores along which they cohere lengthwise and
|
||
|
not crosswise.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Those hard or soft solids are apt to be cut which do not necessarily
|
||
|
either split in advance of the instrument or break into minute
|
||
|
fragments when they are being divided. Those that necessarily do so
|
||
|
and liquids cannot be cut. Some things can be both split and cut, like
|
||
|
wood, though generally it is lengthwise that a thing can be split
|
||
|
and crosswise that it can be cut. For, a body being divided into
|
||
|
many parts fin so far as its unity is made up of many lengths it is
|
||
|
apt to be split, in so far as it is made up of many breadths it is apt
|
||
|
to be cut.
|
||
|
|
||
|
A thing is viscous when, being moist or soft, it is tractile. Bodies
|
||
|
owe this property to the interlocking of their parts when they are
|
||
|
composed like chains, for then they can be drawn out to a great length
|
||
|
and contracted again. Bodies that are not like this are friable.
|
||
|
Bodies are compressible when they are squeezable and retain the
|
||
|
shape they have been squeezed into; incompressible when they are
|
||
|
either inapt to be squeezed at all or do not retain the shape they
|
||
|
have been squeezed into.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Some bodies are combustible and some are not. Wood, wool, bone are
|
||
|
combustible; stone, ice are not. Bodies are combustible when their
|
||
|
pores are such as to admit fire and their longitudinal pores contain
|
||
|
moisture weaker than fire. If they have no moisture, or if, as in
|
||
|
ice or very green wood, the moisture is stronger than fire, they are
|
||
|
not combustible.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Those bodies give off fumes which contain moisture, but in such a
|
||
|
form that it does not go off separately in vapour when they are
|
||
|
exposed to fire. For vapour is a moist secretion tending to the nature
|
||
|
of air produced from a liquid by the agency of burning heat. Bodies
|
||
|
that give off fumes give off secretions of the nature of air by the
|
||
|
lapse of time: as they perish away they dry up or become earth. But
|
||
|
the kind of secretion we are concerned with now differs from others in
|
||
|
that it is not moist nor does it become wind (which is a continuous
|
||
|
flow of air in a given direction). Fumes are common secretion of dry
|
||
|
and moist together caused by the agency of burning heat. Hence they do
|
||
|
not moisten things but rather colour them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The fumes of a woody body are called smoke. (I mean to include bones
|
||
|
and hair and everything of this kind in the same class. For there is
|
||
|
no name common to all the objects that I mean, but, for all that,
|
||
|
these things are all in the same class by analogy. Compare what
|
||
|
Empedocles says: They are one and the same, hair and leaves and the
|
||
|
thick wings of birds and scales that grow on stout limbs.) The fumes
|
||
|
of fat are a sooty smoke and those of oily substances a greasy
|
||
|
steam. Oil does not boil away or thicken by evaporation because it
|
||
|
does not give off vapour but fumes. Water on the other hand does not
|
||
|
give off fumes, but vapour. Sweet wine does give off fumes, for it
|
||
|
contains fat and behaves like oil. It does not solidify under the
|
||
|
influence of cold and it is apt to burn. Really it is not wine at
|
||
|
all in spite of its name: for it does not taste like wine and
|
||
|
consequently does not inebriate as ordinary wine does. It contains but
|
||
|
little fumigable stuff and consequently is inflammable.
|
||
|
|
||
|
All bodies are combustible that dissolve into ashes, and all
|
||
|
bodies do this that solidify under the influence either of heat or
|
||
|
of both heat and cold; for we find that all these bodies are
|
||
|
mastered by fire. Of stones the precious stone called carbuncle is
|
||
|
least amenable to fire.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of combustible bodies some are inflammable and some are not, and
|
||
|
some of the former are reduced to coals. Those are called
|
||
|
'inflammable' which produce flame and those which do not are called
|
||
|
'non-inflammable'. Those fumigable bodies that are not liquid are
|
||
|
inflammable, but pitch, oil, wax are inflammable in conjunction with
|
||
|
other bodies rather than by themselves. Most inflammable are those
|
||
|
bodies that give off smoke. Of bodies of this kind those that
|
||
|
contain more earth than smoke are apt to be reduced to coals. Some
|
||
|
bodies that can be melted are not inflammable, e.g. copper; and some
|
||
|
bodies that cannot be melted are inflammable, e.g. wood; and some
|
||
|
bodies can be melted and are also inflammable, e.g. frankincense.
|
||
|
The reason is that wood has its moisture all together and this is
|
||
|
continuous throughout and so it burns up: whereas copper has it in
|
||
|
each part but not continuous, and insufficient in quantity to give
|
||
|
rise to flame. In frankincense it is disposed in both of these ways.
|
||
|
Fumigable bodies are inflammable when earth predominates in them and
|
||
|
they are consequently such as to be unable to melt. These are
|
||
|
inflammable because they are dry like fire. When this dry comes to
|
||
|
be hot there is fire. This is why flame is burning smoke or dry
|
||
|
exhalation. The fumes of wood are smoke, those of wax and frankincense
|
||
|
and such-like, and pitch and whatever contains pitch or such-like
|
||
|
are sooty smoke, while the fumes of oil and oily substances are a
|
||
|
greasy steam; so are those of all substances which are not at all
|
||
|
combustible by themselves because there is too little of the dry in
|
||
|
them (the dry being the means by which the transition to fire is
|
||
|
effected), but burn very readily in conjunction with something else.
|
||
|
(For the fat is just the conjunction of the oily with the dry.) So
|
||
|
those bodies that give off fumes, like oil and pitch, belong rather to
|
||
|
the moist, but those that burn to the dry.
|
||
|
|
||
|
10
|
||
|
|
||
|
Homogeneous bodies differ to touch-by these affections and
|
||
|
differences, as we have said. They also differ in respect of their
|
||
|
smell, taste, and colour.
|
||
|
|
||
|
By homogeneous bodies I mean, for instance, 'metals', gold,
|
||
|
copper, silver, tin, iron, stone, and everything else of this kind and
|
||
|
the bodies that are extracted from them; also the substances found
|
||
|
in animals and plants, for instance, flesh, bones, sinew, skin,
|
||
|
viscera, hair, fibres, veins (these are the elements of which the
|
||
|
non-homogeneous bodies like the face, a hand, a foot, and everything
|
||
|
of that kind are made up), and in plants, wood, bark, leaves, roots,
|
||
|
and the rest like them.
|
||
|
|
||
|
The homogeneous bodies, it is true, are constituted by a different
|
||
|
cause, but the matter of which they are composed is the dry and the
|
||
|
moist, that is, water and earth (for these bodies exhibit those
|
||
|
qualities most clearly). The agents are the hot and the cold, for they
|
||
|
constitute and make concrete the homogeneous bodies out of earth and
|
||
|
water as matter. Let us consider, then, which of the homogeneous
|
||
|
bodies are made of earth and which of water, and which of both.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of organized bodies some are liquid, some soft, some hard. The
|
||
|
soft and the hard are constituted by a process of solidification, as
|
||
|
we have already explained.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Those liquids that go off in vapour are made of water, those that do
|
||
|
not are either of the nature of earth, or a mixture either of earth
|
||
|
and water, like milk, or of earth and air, like wood, or of water
|
||
|
and air, like oil. Those liquids which are thickened by heat are a
|
||
|
mixture. (Wine is a liquid which raises a difficulty: for it is both
|
||
|
liable to evaporation and it also thickens; for instance new wine
|
||
|
does. The reason is that the word 'wine' is ambiguous and different
|
||
|
'wines' behave in different ways. New wine is more earthy than old,
|
||
|
and for this reason it is more apt to be thickened by heat and less
|
||
|
apt to be congealed by cold. For it contains much heat and a great
|
||
|
proportion of earth, as in Arcadia, where it is so dried up in its
|
||
|
skins by the smoke that you scrape it to drink. If all wine has some
|
||
|
sediment in it then it will belong to earth or to water according to
|
||
|
the quantity of the sediment it possesses.) The liquids that are
|
||
|
thickened by cold are of the nature of earth; those that are thickened
|
||
|
either by heat or by cold consist of more than one element, like oil
|
||
|
and honey, and 'sweet wine'.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Of solid bodies those that have been solidified by cold are of
|
||
|
water, e.g. ice, snow, hail, hoar-frost. Those solidified by heat
|
||
|
are of earth, e.g. pottery, cheese, natron, salt. Some bodies are
|
||
|
solidified by both heat and cold. Of this kind are those solidified by
|
||
|
refrigeration, that is by the privation both of heat and of the
|
||
|
moisture which departs with the heat. For salt and the bodies that are
|
||
|
purely of earth solidify by the privation of moisture only, ice by
|
||
|
that of heat only, these bodies by that of both. So both the active
|
||
|
qualities and both kinds of matter were involved in the process. Of
|
||
|
these bodies those from which all the moisture has gone are all of
|
||
|
them of earth, like pottery or amber. (For amber, also, and the bodies
|
||
|
called 'tears' are formed by refrigeration, like myrrh,
|
||
|
frankincense, gum. Amber, too, appears to belong to this class of
|
||
|
things: the animals enclosed in it show that it is formed by
|
||
|
solidification. The heat is driven out of it by the cold of the
|
||
|
river and causes the moisture to evaporate with it, as in the case
|
||
|
of honey when it has been heated and is immersed in water.) Some of
|
||
|
these bodies cannot be melted or softened; for instance, amber and
|
||
|
certain stones, e.g. the stalactites in caves. (For these stalactites,
|
||
|
too, are formed in the same way: the agent is not fire, but cold which
|
||
|
drives out the heat, which, as it leaves the body, draws out the
|
||
|
moisture with it: in the other class of bodies the agent is external
|
||
|
fire.) In those from which the moisture has not wholly gone earth
|
||
|
still preponderates, but they admit of softening by heat, e.g. iron
|
||
|
and horn.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now since we must include among 'meltables' those bodies which are
|
||
|
melted by fire, these contain some water: indeed some of them, like
|
||
|
wax, are common to earth and water alike. But those that are melted by
|
||
|
water are of earth. Those that are not melted either by fire or
|
||
|
water are of earth, or of earth and water.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since, then, all bodies are either liquid or solid, and since the
|
||
|
things that display the affections we have enumerated belong to
|
||
|
these two classes and there is nothing intermediate, it follows that
|
||
|
we have given a complete account of the criteria for distinguishing
|
||
|
whether a body consists of earth or of water or of more elements
|
||
|
than one, and whether fire was the agent in its formation, or cold, or
|
||
|
both.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Gold, then, and silver and copper and tin and lead and glass and
|
||
|
many nameless stone are of water: for they are all melted by heat.
|
||
|
Of water, too, are some wines and urine and vinegar and lye and whey
|
||
|
and serum: for they are all congealed by cold. In iron, horn, nails,
|
||
|
bones, sinews, wood, hair, leaves, bark, earth preponderates. So, too,
|
||
|
in amber, myrrh, frankincense, and all the substances called
|
||
|
'tears', and stalactites, and fruits, such as leguminous plants and
|
||
|
corn. For things of this kind are, to a greater or less degree, of
|
||
|
earth. For of all these bodies some admit of softening by heat, the
|
||
|
rest give off fumes and are formed by refrigeration. So again in
|
||
|
natron, salt, and those kinds of stones that are not formed by
|
||
|
refrigeration and cannot be melted. Blood, on the other hand, and
|
||
|
semen, are made up of earth and water and air. If the blood contains
|
||
|
fibres, earth preponderates in it: consequently its solidifies by
|
||
|
refrigeration and is melted by liquids; if not, it is of water and
|
||
|
therefore does not solidify. Semen solidifies by refrigeration, its
|
||
|
moisture leaving it together with its heat.
|
||
|
|
||
|
11
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must investigate in the light of the results we have arrived at
|
||
|
what solid or liquid bodies are hot and what cold.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Bodies consisting of water are commonly cold, unless (like lye,
|
||
|
urine, wine) they contain foreign heat. Bodies consisting of earth, on
|
||
|
the other hand, are commonly hot because heat was active in forming
|
||
|
them: for instance lime and ashes.
|
||
|
|
||
|
We must recognize that cold is in a sense the matter of bodies.
|
||
|
For the dry and the moist are matter (being passive) and earth and
|
||
|
water are the elements that primarily embody them, and they are
|
||
|
characterized by cold. Consequently cold must predominate in every
|
||
|
body that consists of one or other of the elements simply, unless such
|
||
|
a body contains foreign heat as water does when it boils or when it
|
||
|
has been strained through ashes. This latter, too, has acquired heat
|
||
|
from the ashes, for everything that has been burnt contains more or
|
||
|
less heat. This explains the generation of animals in putrefying
|
||
|
bodies: the putrefying body contains the heat which destroyed its
|
||
|
proper heat.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Bodies made up of earth and water are hot, for most of them derive
|
||
|
their existence from concoction and heat, though some, like the
|
||
|
waste products of the body, are products of putrefaction. Thus
|
||
|
blood, semen, marrow, figjuice, and all things of the kinds are hot as
|
||
|
long as they are in their natural state, but when they perish and fall
|
||
|
away from that state they are so no longer. For what is left of them
|
||
|
is their matter and that is earth and water. Hence both views are held
|
||
|
about them, some people maintaining them to be cold and others to be
|
||
|
warm; for they are observed to be hot when they are in their natural
|
||
|
state, but to solidify when they have fallen away from it. That, then,
|
||
|
is the case of mixed bodies. However, the distinction we laid down
|
||
|
holds good: if its matter is predominantly water a body is cold (water
|
||
|
being the complete opposite of fire), but if earth or air it tends
|
||
|
to be warm.
|
||
|
|
||
|
It sometimes happens that the coldest bodies can be raised to the
|
||
|
highest temperature by foreign heat; for the most solid and the
|
||
|
hardest bodies are coldest when deprived of heat and most burning
|
||
|
after exposure to fire: thus water is more burning than smoke and
|
||
|
stone than water.
|
||
|
|
||
|
12
|
||
|
|
||
|
Having explained all this we must describe the nature of flesh,
|
||
|
bone, and the other homogeneous bodies severally.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Our account of the formation of the homogeneous bodies has given
|
||
|
us the elements out of which they are compounded and the classes
|
||
|
into which they fall, and has made it clear to which class each of
|
||
|
those bodies belongs. The homogeneous bodies are made up of the
|
||
|
elements, and all the works of nature in turn of the homogeneous
|
||
|
bodies as matter. All the homogeneous bodies consist of the elements
|
||
|
described, as matter, but their essential nature is determined by
|
||
|
their definition. This fact is always clearer in the case of the later
|
||
|
products of those, in fact, that are instruments, as it were, and have
|
||
|
an end: it is clearer, for instance, that a dead man is a man only
|
||
|
in name. And so the hand of a dead man, too, will in the same way be a
|
||
|
hand in name only, just as stone flutes might still be called
|
||
|
flutes: for these members, too, are instruments of a kind. But in
|
||
|
the case of flesh and bone the fact is not so clear to see, and in
|
||
|
that of fire and water even less. For the end is least obvious there
|
||
|
where matter predominates most. If you take the extremes, matter is
|
||
|
pure matter and the essence is pure definition; but the bodies
|
||
|
intermediate between the two are matter or definition in proportion as
|
||
|
they are near to either. For each of those elements has an end and
|
||
|
is not water or fire in any and every condition of itself, just as
|
||
|
flesh is not flesh nor viscera viscera, and the same is true in a
|
||
|
higher degree with face and hand. What a thing is always determined by
|
||
|
its function: a thing really is itself when it can perform its
|
||
|
function; an eye, for instance, when it can see. When a thing cannot
|
||
|
do so it is that thing only in name, like a dead eye or one made of
|
||
|
stone, just as a wooden saw is no more a saw than one in a picture.
|
||
|
The same, then, is true of flesh, except that its function is less
|
||
|
clear than that of the tongue. So, too, with fire; but its function is
|
||
|
perhaps even harder to specify by physical inquiry than that of flesh.
|
||
|
The parts of plants, and inanimate bodies like copper and silver,
|
||
|
are in the same case. They all are what they are in virtue of a
|
||
|
certain power of action or passion-just like flesh and sinew. But we
|
||
|
cannot state their form accurately, and so it is not easy to tell when
|
||
|
they are really there and when they are not unless the body is
|
||
|
thoroughly corrupted and its shape only remains. So ancient corpses
|
||
|
suddenly become ashes in the grave and very old fruit preserves its
|
||
|
shape only but not its taste: so, too, with the solids that form
|
||
|
from milk.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now heat and cold and the motions they set up as the bodies are
|
||
|
solidified by the hot and the cold are sufficient to form all such
|
||
|
parts as are the homogeneous bodies, flesh, bone, hair, sinew, and the
|
||
|
rest. For they are all of them differentiated by the various qualities
|
||
|
enumerated above, tension, tractility, comminuibility, hardness,
|
||
|
softness, and the rest of them: all of which are derived from the
|
||
|
hot and the cold and the mixture of their motions. But no one would go
|
||
|
as far as to consider them sufficient in the case of the
|
||
|
non-homogeneous parts (like the head, the hand, or the foot) which
|
||
|
these homogeneous parts go to make up. Cold and heat and their
|
||
|
motion would be admitted to account for the formation of copper or
|
||
|
silver, but not for that of a saw, a bowl, or a box. So here, save
|
||
|
that in the examples given the cause is art, but in the nonhomogeneous
|
||
|
bodies nature or some other cause.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Since, then, we know to what element each of the homogeneous
|
||
|
bodies belongs, we must now find the definition of each of them, the
|
||
|
answer, that is, to the question, 'what is' flesh, semen, and the
|
||
|
rest? For we know the cause of a thing and its definition when we know
|
||
|
the material or the formal or, better, both the material and the
|
||
|
formal conditions of its generation and destruction, and the efficient
|
||
|
cause of it.
|
||
|
|
||
|
After the homogeneous bodies have been explained we must consider
|
||
|
the non-homogeneous too, and lastly the bodies made up of these,
|
||
|
such as man, plants, and the rest.
|
||
|
|
||
|
-THE END-
|
||
|
.
|